doc-src/TutorialI/Recdef/Induction.thy
changeset 8745 13b32661dde4
child 8771 026f37a86ea7
equal deleted inserted replaced
8744:22fa8b16c3ae 8745:13b32661dde4
       
     1 (*<*)
       
     2 theory Induction = examples + simplification:;
       
     3 (*>*)
       
     4 
       
     5 text{*
       
     6 Assuming we have defined our function such that Isabelle could prove
       
     7 termination and that the recursion equations (or some suitable derived
       
     8 equations) are simplification rules, we might like to prove something about
       
     9 our function. Since the function is recursive, the natural proof principle is
       
    10 again induction. But this time the structural form of induction that comes
       
    11 with datatypes is unlikely to work well---otherwise we could have defined the
       
    12 function by \isacommand{primrec}. Therefore \isacommand{recdef} automatically
       
    13 proves a suitable induction rule $f$\isa{.induct} that follows the
       
    14 recursion pattern of the particular function $f$. We call this
       
    15 \textbf{recursion induction}. Roughly speaking, it
       
    16 requires you to prove for each \isacommand{recdef} equation that the property
       
    17 you are trying to establish holds for the left-hand side provided it holds
       
    18 for all recursive calls on the right-hand side. Here is a simple example:
       
    19 *}
       
    20 
       
    21 lemma "map f (sep(x,xs)) = sep(f x, map f xs)";
       
    22 
       
    23 txt{*\noindent
       
    24 involving the predefined \isa{map} functional on lists: \isa{map f xs}
       
    25 is the result of applying \isa{f} to all elements of \isa{xs}. We prove
       
    26 this lemma by recursion induction w.r.t. \isa{sep}:
       
    27 *}
       
    28 
       
    29 apply(induct_tac x xs rule: sep.induct);
       
    30 
       
    31 txt{*\noindent
       
    32 The resulting proof state has three subgoals corresponding to the three
       
    33 clauses for \isa{sep}:
       
    34 \begin{isabellepar}%
       
    35 ~1.~{\isasymAnd}a.~map~f~(sep~(a,~[]))~=~sep~(f~a,~map~f~[])\isanewline
       
    36 ~2.~{\isasymAnd}a~x.~map~f~(sep~(a,~[x]))~=~sep~(f~a,~map~f~[x])\isanewline
       
    37 ~3.~{\isasymAnd}a~x~y~zs.\isanewline
       
    38 ~~~~~~~map~f~(sep~(a,~y~\#~zs))~=~sep~(f~a,~map~f~(y~\#~zs))~{\isasymLongrightarrow}\isanewline
       
    39 ~~~~~~~map~f~(sep~(a,~x~\#~y~\#~zs))~=~sep~(f~a,~map~f~(x~\#~y~\#~zs))%
       
    40 \end{isabellepar}%
       
    41 The rest is pure simplification:
       
    42 *}
       
    43 
       
    44 apply auto.;
       
    45 
       
    46 text{*
       
    47 Try proving the above lemma by structural induction, and you find that you
       
    48 need an additional case distinction. What is worse, the names of variables
       
    49 are invented by Isabelle and have nothing to do with the names in the
       
    50 definition of \isa{sep}.
       
    51 
       
    52 In general, the format of invoking recursion induction is
       
    53 \begin{ttbox}
       
    54 apply(induct_tac \(x@1 \dots x@n\) rule: \(f\).induct)
       
    55 \end{ttbox}\index{*induct_tac}%
       
    56 where $x@1~\dots~x@n$ is a list of free variables in the subgoal and $f$ the
       
    57 name of a function that takes an $n$-tuple. Usually the subgoal will
       
    58 contain the term $f~x@1~\dots~x@n$ but this need not be the case. The
       
    59 induction rules do not mention $f$ at all. For example \isa{sep.induct}
       
    60 \begin{isabellepar}%
       
    61 {\isasymlbrakk}~{\isasymAnd}a.~?P~a~[];\isanewline
       
    62 ~~{\isasymAnd}a~x.~?P~a~[x];\isanewline
       
    63 ~~{\isasymAnd}a~x~y~zs.~?P~a~(y~\#~zs)~{\isasymLongrightarrow}~?P~a~(x~\#~y~\#~zs){\isasymrbrakk}\isanewline
       
    64 {\isasymLongrightarrow}~?P~?u~?v%
       
    65 \end{isabellepar}%
       
    66 merely says that in order to prove a property \isa{?P} of \isa{?u} and
       
    67 \isa{?v} you need to prove it for the three cases where \isa{?v} is the
       
    68 empty list, the singleton list, and the list with at least two elements
       
    69 (in which case you may assume it holds for the tail of that list).
       
    70 *}
       
    71 
       
    72 (*<*)
       
    73 end
       
    74 (*>*)