doc-src/TutorialI/Inductive/Advanced.thy
changeset 48985 5386df44a037
parent 48984 f51d4a302962
child 48986 037d32448e29
--- a/doc-src/TutorialI/Inductive/Advanced.thy	Tue Aug 28 18:46:15 2012 +0200
+++ /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
@@ -1,407 +0,0 @@
-(*<*)theory Advanced imports Even begin
-ML_file "../../antiquote_setup.ML"
-setup Antiquote_Setup.setup
-(*>*)
-
-text {*
-The premises of introduction rules may contain universal quantifiers and
-monotone functions.  A universal quantifier lets the rule 
-refer to any number of instances of 
-the inductively defined set.  A monotone function lets the rule refer
-to existing constructions (such as ``list of'') over the inductively defined
-set.  The examples below show how to use the additional expressiveness
-and how to reason from the resulting definitions.
-*}
-
-subsection{* Universal Quantifiers in Introduction Rules \label{sec:gterm-datatype} *}
-
-text {*
-\index{ground terms example|(}%
-\index{quantifiers!and inductive definitions|(}%
-As a running example, this section develops the theory of \textbf{ground
-terms}: terms constructed from constant and function 
-symbols but not variables. To simplify matters further, we regard a
-constant as a function applied to the null argument  list.  Let us declare a
-datatype @{text gterm} for the type of ground  terms. It is a type constructor
-whose argument is a type of  function symbols. 
-*}
-
-datatype 'f gterm = Apply 'f "'f gterm list"
-
-text {*
-To try it out, we declare a datatype of some integer operations: 
-integer constants, the unary minus operator and the addition 
-operator.
-*}
-
-datatype integer_op = Number int | UnaryMinus | Plus
-
-text {*
-Now the type @{typ "integer_op gterm"} denotes the ground 
-terms built over those symbols.
-
-The type constructor @{text gterm} can be generalized to a function 
-over sets.  It returns 
-the set of ground terms that can be formed over a set @{text F} of function symbols. For
-example,  we could consider the set of ground terms formed from the finite 
-set @{text "{Number 2, UnaryMinus, Plus}"}.
-
-This concept is inductive. If we have a list @{text args} of ground terms 
-over~@{text F} and a function symbol @{text f} in @{text F}, then we 
-can apply @{text f} to @{text args} to obtain another ground term. 
-The only difficulty is that the argument list may be of any length. Hitherto, 
-each rule in an inductive definition referred to the inductively 
-defined set a fixed number of times, typically once or twice. 
-A universal quantifier in the premise of the introduction rule 
-expresses that every element of @{text args} belongs
-to our inductively defined set: is a ground term 
-over~@{text F}.  The function @{term set} denotes the set of elements in a given 
-list. 
-*}
-
-inductive_set
-  gterms :: "'f set \<Rightarrow> 'f gterm set"
-  for F :: "'f set"
-where
-step[intro!]: "\<lbrakk>\<forall>t \<in> set args. t \<in> gterms F;  f \<in> F\<rbrakk>
-               \<Longrightarrow> (Apply f args) \<in> gterms F"
-
-text {*
-To demonstrate a proof from this definition, let us 
-show that the function @{term gterms}
-is \textbf{monotone}.  We shall need this concept shortly.
-*}
-
-lemma gterms_mono: "F\<subseteq>G \<Longrightarrow> gterms F \<subseteq> gterms G"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule gterms.induct)
-apply blast
-done
-(*<*)
-lemma gterms_mono: "F\<subseteq>G \<Longrightarrow> gterms F \<subseteq> gterms G"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule gterms.induct)
-(*>*)
-txt{*
-Intuitively, this theorem says that
-enlarging the set of function symbols enlarges the set of ground 
-terms. The proof is a trivial rule induction.
-First we use the @{text clarify} method to assume the existence of an element of
-@{term "gterms F"}.  (We could have used @{text "intro subsetI"}.)  We then
-apply rule induction. Here is the resulting subgoal:
-@{subgoals[display,indent=0]}
-The assumptions state that @{text f} belongs 
-to~@{text F}, which is included in~@{text G}, and that every element of the list @{text args} is
-a ground term over~@{text G}.  The @{text blast} method finds this chain of reasoning easily.  
-*}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-text {*
-\begin{warn}
-Why do we call this function @{text gterms} instead 
-of @{text gterm}?  A constant may have the same name as a type.  However,
-name  clashes could arise in the theorems that Isabelle generates. 
-Our choice of names keeps @{text gterms.induct} separate from 
-@{text gterm.induct}.
-\end{warn}
-
-Call a term \textbf{well-formed} if each symbol occurring in it is applied
-to the correct number of arguments.  (This number is called the symbol's
-\textbf{arity}.)  We can express well-formedness by
-generalizing the inductive definition of
-\isa{gterms}.
-Suppose we are given a function called @{text arity}, specifying the arities
-of all symbols.  In the inductive step, we have a list @{text args} of such
-terms and a function  symbol~@{text f}. If the length of the list matches the
-function's arity  then applying @{text f} to @{text args} yields a well-formed
-term.
-*}
-
-inductive_set
-  well_formed_gterm :: "('f \<Rightarrow> nat) \<Rightarrow> 'f gterm set"
-  for arity :: "'f \<Rightarrow> nat"
-where
-step[intro!]: "\<lbrakk>\<forall>t \<in> set args. t \<in> well_formed_gterm arity;  
-                length args = arity f\<rbrakk>
-               \<Longrightarrow> (Apply f args) \<in> well_formed_gterm arity"
-
-text {*
-The inductive definition neatly captures the reasoning above.
-The universal quantification over the
-@{text set} of arguments expresses that all of them are well-formed.%
-\index{quantifiers!and inductive definitions|)}
-*}
-
-subsection{* Alternative Definition Using a Monotone Function *}
-
-text {*
-\index{monotone functions!and inductive definitions|(}% 
-An inductive definition may refer to the
-inductively defined  set through an arbitrary monotone function.  To
-demonstrate this powerful feature, let us
-change the  inductive definition above, replacing the
-quantifier by a use of the function @{term lists}. This
-function, from the Isabelle theory of lists, is analogous to the
-function @{term gterms} declared above: if @{text A} is a set then
-@{term "lists A"} is the set of lists whose elements belong to
-@{term A}.  
-
-In the inductive definition of well-formed terms, examine the one
-introduction rule.  The first premise states that @{text args} belongs to
-the @{text lists} of well-formed terms.  This formulation is more
-direct, if more obscure, than using a universal quantifier.
-*}
-
-inductive_set
-  well_formed_gterm' :: "('f \<Rightarrow> nat) \<Rightarrow> 'f gterm set"
-  for arity :: "'f \<Rightarrow> nat"
-where
-step[intro!]: "\<lbrakk>args \<in> lists (well_formed_gterm' arity);  
-                length args = arity f\<rbrakk>
-               \<Longrightarrow> (Apply f args) \<in> well_formed_gterm' arity"
-monos lists_mono
-
-text {*
-We cite the theorem @{text lists_mono} to justify 
-using the function @{term lists}.%
-\footnote{This particular theorem is installed by default already, but we
-include the \isakeyword{monos} declaration in order to illustrate its syntax.}
-@{named_thms [display,indent=0] lists_mono [no_vars] (lists_mono)}
-Why must the function be monotone?  An inductive definition describes
-an iterative construction: each element of the set is constructed by a
-finite number of introduction rule applications.  For example, the
-elements of \isa{even} are constructed by finitely many applications of
-the rules
-@{thm [display,indent=0] even.intros [no_vars]}
-All references to a set in its
-inductive definition must be positive.  Applications of an
-introduction rule cannot invalidate previous applications, allowing the
-construction process to converge.
-The following pair of rules do not constitute an inductive definition:
-\begin{trivlist}
-\item @{term "0 \<in> even"}
-\item @{term "n \<notin> even \<Longrightarrow> (Suc n) \<in> even"}
-\end{trivlist}
-Showing that 4 is even using these rules requires showing that 3 is not
-even.  It is far from trivial to show that this set of rules
-characterizes the even numbers.  
-
-Even with its use of the function \isa{lists}, the premise of our
-introduction rule is positive:
-@{thm [display,indent=0] (prem 1) step [no_vars]}
-To apply the rule we construct a list @{term args} of previously
-constructed well-formed terms.  We obtain a
-new term, @{term "Apply f args"}.  Because @{term lists} is monotone,
-applications of the rule remain valid as new terms are constructed.
-Further lists of well-formed
-terms become available and none are taken away.%
-\index{monotone functions!and inductive definitions|)} 
-*}
-
-subsection{* A Proof of Equivalence *}
-
-text {*
-We naturally hope that these two inductive definitions of ``well-formed'' 
-coincide.  The equality can be proved by separate inclusions in 
-each direction.  Each is a trivial rule induction. 
-*}
-
-lemma "well_formed_gterm arity \<subseteq> well_formed_gterm' arity"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule well_formed_gterm.induct)
-apply auto
-done
-(*<*)
-lemma "well_formed_gterm arity \<subseteq> well_formed_gterm' arity"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule well_formed_gterm.induct)
-(*>*)
-txt {*
-The @{text clarify} method gives
-us an element of @{term "well_formed_gterm arity"} on which to perform 
-induction.  The resulting subgoal can be proved automatically:
-@{subgoals[display,indent=0]}
-This proof resembles the one given in
-{\S}\ref{sec:gterm-datatype} above, especially in the form of the
-induction hypothesis.  Next, we consider the opposite inclusion:
-*}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-lemma "well_formed_gterm' arity \<subseteq> well_formed_gterm arity"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule well_formed_gterm'.induct)
-apply auto
-done
-(*<*)
-lemma "well_formed_gterm' arity \<subseteq> well_formed_gterm arity"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule well_formed_gterm'.induct)
-(*>*)
-txt {*
-The proof script is virtually identical,
-but the subgoal after applying induction may be surprising:
-@{subgoals[display,indent=0,margin=65]}
-The induction hypothesis contains an application of @{term lists}.  Using a
-monotone function in the inductive definition always has this effect.  The
-subgoal may look uninviting, but fortunately 
-@{term lists} distributes over intersection:
-@{named_thms [display,indent=0] lists_Int_eq [no_vars] (lists_Int_eq)}
-Thanks to this default simplification rule, the induction hypothesis 
-is quickly replaced by its two parts:
-\begin{trivlist}
-\item @{term "args \<in> lists (well_formed_gterm' arity)"}
-\item @{term "args \<in> lists (well_formed_gterm arity)"}
-\end{trivlist}
-Invoking the rule @{text well_formed_gterm.step} completes the proof.  The
-call to @{text auto} does all this work.
-
-This example is typical of how monotone functions
-\index{monotone functions} can be used.  In particular, many of them
-distribute over intersection.  Monotonicity implies one direction of
-this set equality; we have this theorem:
-@{named_thms [display,indent=0] mono_Int [no_vars] (mono_Int)}
-*}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-
-
-subsection{* Another Example of Rule Inversion *}
-
-text {*
-\index{rule inversion|(}%
-Does @{term gterms} distribute over intersection?  We have proved that this
-function is monotone, so @{text mono_Int} gives one of the inclusions.  The
-opposite inclusion asserts that if @{term t} is a ground term over both of the
-sets
-@{term F} and~@{term G} then it is also a ground term over their intersection,
-@{term "F \<inter> G"}.
-*}
-
-lemma gterms_IntI:
-     "t \<in> gterms F \<Longrightarrow> t \<in> gterms G \<longrightarrow> t \<in> gterms (F\<inter>G)"
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-text {*
-Attempting this proof, we get the assumption 
-@{term "Apply f args \<in> gterms G"}, which cannot be broken down. 
-It looks like a job for rule inversion:\cmmdx{inductive\protect\_cases}
-*}
-
-inductive_cases gterm_Apply_elim [elim!]: "Apply f args \<in> gterms F"
-
-text {*
-Here is the result.
-@{named_thms [display,indent=0,margin=50] gterm_Apply_elim [no_vars] (gterm_Apply_elim)}
-This rule replaces an assumption about @{term "Apply f args"} by 
-assumptions about @{term f} and~@{term args}.  
-No cases are discarded (there was only one to begin
-with) but the rule applies specifically to the pattern @{term "Apply f args"}.
-It can be applied repeatedly as an elimination rule without looping, so we
-have given the @{text "elim!"} attribute. 
-
-Now we can prove the other half of that distributive law.
-*}
-
-lemma gterms_IntI [rule_format, intro!]:
-     "t \<in> gterms F \<Longrightarrow> t \<in> gterms G \<longrightarrow> t \<in> gterms (F\<inter>G)"
-apply (erule gterms.induct)
-apply blast
-done
-(*<*)
-lemma "t \<in> gterms F \<Longrightarrow> t \<in> gterms G \<longrightarrow> t \<in> gterms (F\<inter>G)"
-apply (erule gterms.induct)
-(*>*)
-txt {*
-The proof begins with rule induction over the definition of
-@{term gterms}, which leaves a single subgoal:  
-@{subgoals[display,indent=0,margin=65]}
-To prove this, we assume @{term "Apply f args \<in> gterms G"}.  Rule inversion,
-in the form of @{text gterm_Apply_elim}, infers
-that every element of @{term args} belongs to 
-@{term "gterms G"}; hence (by the induction hypothesis) it belongs
-to @{term "gterms (F \<inter> G)"}.  Rule inversion also yields
-@{term "f \<in> G"} and hence @{term "f \<in> F \<inter> G"}. 
-All of this reasoning is done by @{text blast}.
-
-\smallskip
-Our distributive law is a trivial consequence of previously-proved results:
-*}
-(*<*)oops(*>*)
-lemma gterms_Int_eq [simp]:
-     "gterms (F \<inter> G) = gterms F \<inter> gterms G"
-by (blast intro!: mono_Int monoI gterms_mono)
-
-text_raw {*
-\index{rule inversion|)}%
-\index{ground terms example|)}
-
-
-\begin{isamarkuptext}
-\begin{exercise}
-A function mapping function symbols to their 
-types is called a \textbf{signature}.  Given a type 
-ranging over type symbols, we can represent a function's type by a
-list of argument types paired with the result type. 
-Complete this inductive definition:
-\begin{isabelle}
-*}
-
-inductive_set
-  well_typed_gterm :: "('f \<Rightarrow> 't list * 't) \<Rightarrow> ('f gterm * 't)set"
-  for sig :: "'f \<Rightarrow> 't list * 't"
-(*<*)
-where
-step[intro!]: 
-    "\<lbrakk>\<forall>pair \<in> set args. pair \<in> well_typed_gterm sig; 
-      sig f = (map snd args, rtype)\<rbrakk>
-     \<Longrightarrow> (Apply f (map fst args), rtype) 
-         \<in> well_typed_gterm sig"
-(*>*)
-text_raw {*
-\end{isabelle}
-\end{exercise}
-\end{isamarkuptext}
-*}
-
-(*<*)
-
-text{*the following declaration isn't actually used*}
-primrec
-  integer_arity :: "integer_op \<Rightarrow> nat"
-where
-  "integer_arity (Number n)        = 0"
-| "integer_arity UnaryMinus        = 1"
-| "integer_arity Plus              = 2"
-
-text{* the rest isn't used: too complicated.  OK for an exercise though.*}
-
-inductive_set
-  integer_signature :: "(integer_op * (unit list * unit)) set"
-where
-  Number:     "(Number n,   ([], ())) \<in> integer_signature"
-| UnaryMinus: "(UnaryMinus, ([()], ())) \<in> integer_signature"
-| Plus:       "(Plus,       ([(),()], ())) \<in> integer_signature"
-
-inductive_set
-  well_typed_gterm' :: "('f \<Rightarrow> 't list * 't) \<Rightarrow> ('f gterm * 't)set"
-  for sig :: "'f \<Rightarrow> 't list * 't"
-where
-step[intro!]: 
-    "\<lbrakk>args \<in> lists(well_typed_gterm' sig); 
-      sig f = (map snd args, rtype)\<rbrakk>
-     \<Longrightarrow> (Apply f (map fst args), rtype) 
-         \<in> well_typed_gterm' sig"
-monos lists_mono
-
-
-lemma "well_typed_gterm sig \<subseteq> well_typed_gterm' sig"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule well_typed_gterm.induct)
-apply auto
-done
-
-lemma "well_typed_gterm' sig \<subseteq> well_typed_gterm sig"
-apply clarify
-apply (erule well_typed_gterm'.induct)
-apply auto
-done
-
-
-end
-(*>*)