src/HOL/Isar_examples/Cantor.thy
author wenzelm
Sun, 30 Jul 2000 13:02:56 +0200
changeset 9474 b0ce3b7c9c26
parent 7982 d534b897ce39
child 10007 64bf7da1994a
permissions -rw-r--r--
removed equalityCE;

(*  Title:      HOL/Isar_examples/Cantor.thy
    ID:         $Id$
    Author:     Markus Wenzel, TU Muenchen
*)

header {* Cantor's Theorem *};

theory Cantor = Main:;

text_raw {*
 \footnote{This is an Isar version of the final example of the
 Isabelle/HOL manual \cite{isabelle-HOL}.}
*};

text {*
 Cantor's Theorem states that every set has more subsets than it has
 elements.  It has become a favorite basic example in pure
 higher-order logic since it is so easily expressed: \[\all{f::\alpha
 \To \alpha \To \idt{bool}} \ex{S::\alpha \To \idt{bool}}
 \all{x::\alpha} f \ap x \not= S\]
  
 Viewing types as sets, $\alpha \To \idt{bool}$ represents the
 powerset of $\alpha$.  This version of the theorem states that for
 every function from $\alpha$ to its powerset, some subset is outside
 its range.  The Isabelle/Isar proofs below uses HOL's set theory,
 with the type $\alpha \ap \idt{set}$ and the operator
 $\idt{range}::(\alpha \To \beta) \To \beta \ap \idt{set}$.
  
 \bigskip We first consider a slightly awkward version of the proof,
 with the innermost reasoning expressed quite naively.
*};

theorem "EX S. S ~: range (f :: 'a => 'a set)";
proof;
  let ?S = "{x. x ~: f x}";
  show "?S ~: range f";
  proof;
    assume "?S : range f";
    thus False;
    proof;
      fix y; 
      assume "?S = f y";
      thus ?thesis;
      proof (rule equalityCE);
        assume in_S: "y : ?S";
        assume in_fy: "y : f y";
        from in_S; have notin_fy: "y ~: f y"; ..;
        from notin_fy in_fy; show ?thesis; by contradiction;
      next;
        assume notin_S: "y ~: ?S";
        assume notin_fy: "y ~: f y";
        from notin_S; have in_fy: "y : f y"; ..;
        from notin_fy in_fy; show ?thesis; by contradiction;
      qed;
    qed;
  qed;
qed;

text {*
 The following version of the proof essentially does the same
 reasoning, only that it is expressed more neatly.  In particular, we
 change the order of assumptions introduced in the two cases of rule
 \name{equalityCE}, streamlining the flow of intermediate facts and
 avoiding explicit naming.\footnote{In general, neither the order of
 assumptions as introduced by \isacommand{assume}, nor the order of
 goals as solved by \isacommand{show} is of any significance.  The
 basic logical structure has to be left intact, though.  In
 particular, assumptions ``belonging'' to some goal have to be
 introduced \emph{before} its corresponding \isacommand{show}.}
*};

theorem "EX S. S ~: range (f :: 'a => 'a set)";
proof;
  let ?S = "{x. x ~: f x}";
  show "?S ~: range f";
  proof;
    assume "?S : range f";
    thus False;
    proof;
      fix y; 
      assume "?S = f y";
      thus ?thesis;
      proof (rule equalityCE);
        assume "y : f y";
        assume "y : ?S"; hence "y ~: f y"; ..;
        thus ?thesis; by contradiction;
      next;
        assume "y ~: f y";
        assume "y ~: ?S"; hence "y : f y"; ..;
        thus ?thesis; by contradiction;
      qed;
    qed;
  qed;
qed;

text {*
 How much creativity is required?  As it happens, Isabelle can prove
 this theorem automatically using best-first search.  Depth-first
 search would diverge, but best-first search successfully navigates
 through the large search space.  The context of Isabelle's classical
 prover contains rules for the relevant constructs of HOL's set
 theory.
*};

theorem "EX S. S ~: range (f :: 'a => 'a set)";
  by best;

text {*
 While this establishes the same theorem internally, we do not get any
 idea of how the proof actually works.  There is currently no way to
 transform internal system-level representations of Isabelle proofs
 back into Isar text.  Writing intelligible proof documents
 really is a creative process, after all.
*};

end;