doc-src/TutorialI/fp.tex
author nipkow
Thu, 29 May 2008 22:45:33 +0200
changeset 27015 f8537d69f514
parent 25281 8d309beb66d6
child 27712 007a339b9e7d
permissions -rw-r--r--
*** empty log message ***

\chapter{Functional Programming in HOL}

This chapter describes how to write
functional programs in HOL and how to verify them.  However, 
most of the constructs and
proof procedures introduced are general and recur in any specification
or verification task.  We really should speak of functional
\emph{modelling} rather than functional \emph{programming}: 
our primary aim is not
to write programs but to design abstract models of systems.  HOL is
a specification language that goes well beyond what can be expressed as a
program. However, for the time being we concentrate on the computable.

If you are a purist functional programmer, please note that all functions
in HOL must be total:
they must terminate for all inputs.  Lazy data structures are not
directly available.

\section{An Introductory Theory}
\label{sec:intro-theory}

Functional programming needs datatypes and functions. Both of them can be
defined in a theory with a syntax reminiscent of languages like ML or
Haskell. As an example consider the theory in figure~\ref{fig:ToyList}.
We will now examine it line by line.

\begin{figure}[htbp]
\begin{ttbox}\makeatother
\input{ToyList2/ToyList1}\end{ttbox}
\caption{A Theory of Lists}
\label{fig:ToyList}
\end{figure}

\index{*ToyList example|(}
{\makeatother\medskip\input{ToyList/document/ToyList.tex}}

The complete proof script is shown in Fig.\ts\ref{fig:ToyList-proofs}. The
concatenation of Figs.\ts\ref{fig:ToyList} and~\ref{fig:ToyList-proofs}
constitutes the complete theory \texttt{ToyList} and should reside in file
\texttt{ToyList.thy}.
% It is good practice to present all declarations and
%definitions at the beginning of a theory to facilitate browsing.%
\index{*ToyList example|)}

\begin{figure}[htbp]
\begin{ttbox}\makeatother
\input{ToyList2/ToyList2}\end{ttbox}
\caption{Proofs about Lists}
\label{fig:ToyList-proofs}
\end{figure}

\subsubsection*{Review}

This is the end of our toy proof. It should have familiarized you with
\begin{itemize}
\item the standard theorem proving procedure:
state a goal (lemma or theorem); proceed with proof until a separate lemma is
required; prove that lemma; come back to the original goal.
\item a specific procedure that works well for functional programs:
induction followed by all-out simplification via \isa{auto}.
\item a basic repertoire of proof commands.
\end{itemize}

\begin{warn}
It is tempting to think that all lemmas should have the \isa{simp} attribute
just because this was the case in the example above. However, in that example
all lemmas were equations, and the right-hand side was simpler than the
left-hand side --- an ideal situation for simplification purposes. Unless
this is clearly the case, novices should refrain from awarding a lemma the
\isa{simp} attribute, which has a global effect. Instead, lemmas can be
applied locally where they are needed, which is discussed in the following
chapter.
\end{warn}

\section{Some Helpful Commands}
\label{sec:commands-and-hints}

This section discusses a few basic commands for manipulating the proof state
and can be skipped by casual readers.

There are two kinds of commands used during a proof: the actual proof
commands and auxiliary commands for examining the proof state and controlling
the display. Simple proof commands are of the form
\commdx{apply}(\textit{method}), where \textit{method} is typically 
\isa{induct_tac} or \isa{auto}.  All such theorem proving operations
are referred to as \bfindex{methods}, and further ones are
introduced throughout the tutorial.  Unless stated otherwise, you may
assume that a method attacks merely the first subgoal. An exception is
\isa{auto}, which tries to solve all subgoals.

The most useful auxiliary commands are as follows:
\begin{description}
\item[Modifying the order of subgoals:]
\commdx{defer} moves the first subgoal to the end and
\commdx{prefer}~$n$ moves subgoal $n$ to the front.
\item[Printing theorems:]
  \commdx{thm}~\textit{name}$@1$~\dots~\textit{name}$@n$
  prints the named theorems.
\item[Reading terms and types:] \commdx{term}
  \textit{string} reads, type-checks and prints the given string as a term in
  the current context; the inferred type is output as well.
  \commdx{typ} \textit{string} reads and prints the given
  string as a type in the current context.
\end{description}
Further commands are found in the Isabelle/Isar Reference
Manual~\cite{isabelle-isar-ref}.

\begin{pgnote}
Clicking on the \pgmenu{State} button redisplays the current proof state.
This is helpful in case commands like \isacommand{thm} have overwritten it.
\end{pgnote}

We now examine Isabelle's functional programming constructs systematically,
starting with inductive datatypes.


\section{Datatypes}
\label{sec:datatype}

\index{datatypes|(}%
Inductive datatypes are part of almost every non-trivial application of HOL.
First we take another look at an important example, the datatype of
lists, before we turn to datatypes in general. The section closes with a
case study.


\subsection{Lists}

\index{*list (type)}%
Lists are one of the essential datatypes in computing.  We expect that you
are already familiar with their basic operations.
Theory \isa{ToyList} is only a small fragment of HOL's predefined theory
\thydx{List}\footnote{\url{http://isabelle.in.tum.de/library/HOL/List.html}}.
The latter contains many further operations. For example, the functions
\cdx{hd} (``head'') and \cdx{tl} (``tail'') return the first
element and the remainder of a list. (However, pattern matching is usually
preferable to \isa{hd} and \isa{tl}.)  
Also available are higher-order functions like \isa{map} and \isa{filter}.
Theory \isa{List} also contains
more syntactic sugar: \isa{[}$x@1$\isa{,}\dots\isa{,}$x@n$\isa{]} abbreviates
$x@1$\isa{\#}\dots\isa{\#}$x@n$\isa{\#[]}.  In the rest of the tutorial we
always use HOL's predefined lists by building on theory \isa{Main}.


\subsection{The General Format}
\label{sec:general-datatype}

The general HOL \isacommand{datatype} definition is of the form
\[
\isacommand{datatype}~(\alpha@1, \dots, \alpha@n) \, t ~=~
C@1~\tau@{11}~\dots~\tau@{1k@1} ~\mid~ \dots ~\mid~
C@m~\tau@{m1}~\dots~\tau@{mk@m}
\]
where $\alpha@i$ are distinct type variables (the parameters), $C@i$ are distinct
constructor names and $\tau@{ij}$ are types; it is customary to capitalize
the first letter in constructor names. There are a number of
restrictions (such as that the type should not be empty) detailed
elsewhere~\cite{isabelle-HOL}. Isabelle notifies you if you violate them.

Laws about datatypes, such as \isa{[] \isasymnoteq~x\#xs} and
\isa{(x\#xs = y\#ys) = (x=y \isasymand~xs=ys)}, are used automatically
during proofs by simplification.  The same is true for the equations in
primitive recursive function definitions.

Every\footnote{Except for advanced datatypes where the recursion involves
``\isasymRightarrow'' as in {\S}\ref{sec:nested-fun-datatype}.} datatype $t$
comes equipped with a \isa{size} function from $t$ into the natural numbers
(see~{\S}\ref{sec:nat} below). For lists, \isa{size} is just the length, i.e.\
\isa{size [] = 0} and \isa{size(x \# xs) = size xs + 1}.  In general,
\cdx{size} returns
\begin{itemize}
\item zero for all constructors that do not have an argument of type $t$,
\item one plus the sum of the sizes of all arguments of type~$t$,
for all other constructors.
\end{itemize}
Note that because
\isa{size} is defined on every datatype, it is overloaded; on lists
\isa{size} is also called \sdx{length}, which is not overloaded.
Isabelle will always show \isa{size} on lists as \isa{length}.


\subsection{Primitive Recursion}

\index{recursion!primitive}%
Functions on datatypes are usually defined by recursion. In fact, most of the
time they are defined by what is called \textbf{primitive recursion} over some
datatype $t$. This means that the recursion equations must be of the form
\[ f \, x@1 \, \dots \, (C \, y@1 \, \dots \, y@k)\, \dots \, x@n = r \]
such that $C$ is a constructor of $t$ and all recursive calls of
$f$ in $r$ are of the form $f \, \dots \, y@i \, \dots$ for some $i$. Thus
Isabelle immediately sees that $f$ terminates because one (fixed!) argument
becomes smaller with every recursive call. There must be at most one equation
for each constructor.  Their order is immaterial.
A more general method for defining total recursive functions is introduced in
{\S}\ref{sec:fun}.

\begin{exercise}\label{ex:Tree}
\input{Misc/document/Tree.tex}%
\end{exercise}

\input{Misc/document/case_exprs.tex}

\input{Ifexpr/document/Ifexpr.tex}
\index{datatypes|)}


\section{Some Basic Types}

This section introduces the types of natural numbers and ordered pairs.  Also
described is type \isa{option}, which is useful for modelling exceptional
cases. 

\subsection{Natural Numbers}
\label{sec:nat}\index{natural numbers}%
\index{linear arithmetic|(}

\input{Misc/document/fakenat.tex}\medskip
\input{Misc/document/natsum.tex}

\index{linear arithmetic|)}


\subsection{Pairs}
\input{Misc/document/pairs.tex}

\subsection{Datatype {\tt\slshape option}}
\label{sec:option}
\input{Misc/document/Option2.tex}

\section{Definitions}
\label{sec:Definitions}

A definition is simply an abbreviation, i.e.\ a new name for an existing
construction. In particular, definitions cannot be recursive. Isabelle offers
definitions on the level of types and terms. Those on the type level are
called \textbf{type synonyms}; those on the term level are simply called 
definitions.


\subsection{Type Synonyms}

\index{type synonyms}%
Type synonyms are similar to those found in ML\@. They are created by a 
\commdx{types} command:

\medskip
\input{Misc/document/types.tex}

\input{Misc/document/prime_def.tex}


\section{The Definitional Approach}
\label{sec:definitional}

\index{Definitional Approach}%
As we pointed out at the beginning of the chapter, asserting arbitrary
axioms such as $f(n) = f(n) + 1$ can easily lead to contradictions. In order
to avoid this danger, we advocate the definitional rather than
the axiomatic approach: introduce new concepts by definitions. However,  Isabelle/HOL seems to
support many richer definitional constructs, such as
\isacommand{primrec}. The point is that Isabelle reduces such constructs to first principles. For example, each
\isacommand{primrec} function definition is turned into a proper
(nonrecursive!) definition from which the user-supplied recursion equations are
automatically proved.  This process is
hidden from the user, who does not have to understand the details.  Other commands described
later, like \isacommand{fun} and \isacommand{inductive}, work similarly.  
This strict adherence to the definitional approach reduces the risk of 
soundness errors.

\chapter{More Functional Programming}

The purpose of this chapter is to deepen your understanding of the
concepts encountered so far and to introduce advanced forms of datatypes and
recursive functions. The first two sections give a structured presentation of
theorem proving by simplification ({\S}\ref{sec:Simplification}) and discuss
important heuristics for induction ({\S}\ref{sec:InductionHeuristics}).  You can
skip them if you are not planning to perform proofs yourself.
We then present a case
study: a compiler for expressions ({\S}\ref{sec:ExprCompiler}). Advanced
datatypes, including those involving function spaces, are covered in
{\S}\ref{sec:advanced-datatypes}; it closes with another case study, search
trees (``tries'').  Finally we introduce \isacommand{fun}, a general
form of recursive function definition that goes well beyond 
\isacommand{primrec} ({\S}\ref{sec:fun}).


\section{Simplification}
\label{sec:Simplification}
\index{simplification|(}

So far we have proved our theorems by \isa{auto}, which simplifies
all subgoals. In fact, \isa{auto} can do much more than that. 
To go beyond toy examples, you
need to understand the ingredients of \isa{auto}.  This section covers the
method that \isa{auto} always applies first, simplification.

Simplification is one of the central theorem proving tools in Isabelle and
many other systems. The tool itself is called the \textbf{simplifier}. 
This section introduces the many features of the simplifier
and is required reading if you intend to perform proofs.  Later on,
{\S}\ref{sec:simplification-II} explains some more advanced features and a
little bit of how the simplifier works. The serious student should read that
section as well, in particular to understand why the simplifier did
something unexpected.

\subsection{What is Simplification?}

In its most basic form, simplification means repeated application of
equations from left to right. For example, taking the rules for \isa{\at}
and applying them to the term \isa{[0,1] \at\ []} results in a sequence of
simplification steps:
\begin{ttbox}\makeatother
(0#1#[]) @ []  \(\leadsto\)  0#((1#[]) @ [])  \(\leadsto\)  0#(1#([] @ []))  \(\leadsto\)  0#1#[]
\end{ttbox}
This is also known as \bfindex{term rewriting}\indexbold{rewriting} and the
equations are referred to as \bfindex{rewrite rules}.
``Rewriting'' is more honest than ``simplification'' because the terms do not
necessarily become simpler in the process.

The simplifier proves arithmetic goals as described in
{\S}\ref{sec:nat} above.  Arithmetic expressions are simplified using built-in
procedures that go beyond mere rewrite rules.  New simplification procedures
can be coded and installed, but they are definitely not a matter for this
tutorial. 

\input{Misc/document/simp.tex}

\index{simplification|)}

\input{Misc/document/Itrev.tex}
\begin{exercise}
\input{Misc/document/Plus.tex}%
\end{exercise}
\begin{exercise}
\input{Misc/document/Tree2.tex}%
\end{exercise}

\input{CodeGen/document/CodeGen.tex}


\section{Advanced Datatypes}
\label{sec:advanced-datatypes}
\index{datatype@\isacommand {datatype} (command)|(}
\index{primrec@\isacommand {primrec} (command)|(}
%|)

This section presents advanced forms of datatypes: mutual and nested
recursion.  A series of examples will culminate in a treatment of the trie
data structure.


\subsection{Mutual Recursion}
\label{sec:datatype-mut-rec}

\input{Datatype/document/ABexpr.tex}

\subsection{Nested Recursion}
\label{sec:nested-datatype}

{\makeatother\input{Datatype/document/Nested.tex}}


\subsection{The Limits of Nested Recursion}
\label{sec:nested-fun-datatype}

How far can we push nested recursion? By the unfolding argument above, we can
reduce nested to mutual recursion provided the nested recursion only involves
previously defined datatypes. This does not include functions:
\begin{isabelle}
\isacommand{datatype} t = C "t \isasymRightarrow\ bool"
\end{isabelle}
This declaration is a real can of worms.
In HOL it must be ruled out because it requires a type
\isa{t} such that \isa{t} and its power set \isa{t \isasymFun\ bool} have the
same cardinality --- an impossibility. For the same reason it is not possible
to allow recursion involving the type \isa{t set}, which is isomorphic to
\isa{t \isasymFun\ bool}.

Fortunately, a limited form of recursion
involving function spaces is permitted: the recursive type may occur on the
right of a function arrow, but never on the left. Hence the above can of worms
is ruled out but the following example of a potentially 
\index{infinitely branching trees}%
infinitely branching tree is accepted:
\smallskip

\input{Datatype/document/Fundata.tex}

If you need nested recursion on the left of a function arrow, there are
alternatives to pure HOL\@.  In the Logic for Computable Functions 
(\rmindex{LCF}), types like
\begin{isabelle}
\isacommand{datatype} lam = C "lam \isasymrightarrow\ lam"
\end{isabelle}
do indeed make sense~\cite{paulson87}.  Note the different arrow,
\isa{\isasymrightarrow} instead of \isa{\isasymRightarrow},
expressing the type of \emph{continuous} functions. 
There is even a version of LCF on top of HOL,
called \rmindex{HOLCF}~\cite{MuellerNvOS99}.
\index{datatype@\isacommand {datatype} (command)|)}
\index{primrec@\isacommand {primrec} (command)|)}


\subsection{Case Study: Tries}
\label{sec:Trie}

\index{tries|(}%
Tries are a classic search tree data structure~\cite{Knuth3-75} for fast
indexing with strings. Figure~\ref{fig:trie} gives a graphical example of a
trie containing the words ``all'', ``an'', ``ape'', ``can'', ``car'' and
``cat''.  When searching a string in a trie, the letters of the string are
examined sequentially. Each letter determines which subtrie to search next.
In this case study we model tries as a datatype, define a lookup and an
update function, and prove that they behave as expected.

\begin{figure}[htbp]
\begin{center}
\unitlength1mm
\begin{picture}(60,30)
\put( 5, 0){\makebox(0,0)[b]{l}}
\put(25, 0){\makebox(0,0)[b]{e}}
\put(35, 0){\makebox(0,0)[b]{n}}
\put(45, 0){\makebox(0,0)[b]{r}}
\put(55, 0){\makebox(0,0)[b]{t}}
%
\put( 5, 9){\line(0,-1){5}}
\put(25, 9){\line(0,-1){5}}
\put(44, 9){\line(-3,-2){9}}
\put(45, 9){\line(0,-1){5}}
\put(46, 9){\line(3,-2){9}}
%
\put( 5,10){\makebox(0,0)[b]{l}}
\put(15,10){\makebox(0,0)[b]{n}}
\put(25,10){\makebox(0,0)[b]{p}}
\put(45,10){\makebox(0,0)[b]{a}}
%
\put(14,19){\line(-3,-2){9}}
\put(15,19){\line(0,-1){5}}
\put(16,19){\line(3,-2){9}}
\put(45,19){\line(0,-1){5}}
%
\put(15,20){\makebox(0,0)[b]{a}}
\put(45,20){\makebox(0,0)[b]{c}}
%
\put(30,30){\line(-3,-2){13}}
\put(30,30){\line(3,-2){13}}
\end{picture}
\end{center}
\caption{A Sample Trie}
\label{fig:trie}
\end{figure}

Proper tries associate some value with each string. Since the
information is stored only in the final node associated with the string, many
nodes do not carry any value. This distinction is modeled with the help
of the predefined datatype \isa{option} (see {\S}\ref{sec:option}).
\input{Trie/document/Trie.tex}
\index{tries|)}

\section{Total Recursive Functions: \isacommand{fun}}
\label{sec:fun}
\index{fun@\isacommand {fun} (command)|(}\index{functions!total|(}

Although many total functions have a natural primitive recursive definition,
this is not always the case. Arbitrary total recursive functions can be
defined by means of \isacommand{fun}: you can use full pattern matching,
recursion need not involve datatypes, and termination is proved by showing
that the arguments of all recursive calls are smaller in a suitable sense.
In this section we restrict ourselves to functions where Isabelle can prove
termination automatically. More advanced function definitions, including user
supplied termination proofs, nested recursion and partiality, are discussed
in a separate tutorial~\cite{isabelle-function}.

\input{Fun/document/fun0.tex}

\index{fun@\isacommand {fun} (command)|)}\index{functions!total|)}