diff -r 542fb6c6c9b2 -r 820cca8573f8 doc-src/TutorialI/Misc/document/AdvancedInd.tex --- /dev/null Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000 +++ b/doc-src/TutorialI/Misc/document/AdvancedInd.tex Mon Aug 21 18:45:29 2000 +0200 @@ -0,0 +1,229 @@ +\begin{isabelle}% +% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +Now that we have learned about rules and logic, we take another look at the +finer points of induction. The two questions we answer are: what to do if the +proposition to be proved is not directly amenable to induction, and how to +utilize and even derive new induction schemas.% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +% +\isamarkupsubsection{Massaging the proposition\label{sec:ind-var-in-prems}} +% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +So far we have assumed that the theorem we want to prove is already in a form +that is amenable to induction, but this is not always the case:% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemma}\ {"}xs\ {\isasymnoteq}\ []\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ hd(rev\ xs)\ =\ last\ xs{"}\isanewline +\isacommand{apply}(induct\_tac\ xs)% +\begin{isamarkuptxt}% +\noindent +(where \isa{hd} and \isa{last} return the first and last element of a +non-empty list) +produces the warning +\begin{quote}\tt +Induction variable occurs also among premises! +\end{quote} +and leads to the base case +\begin{isabellepar}% +\ 1.\ xs\ {\isasymnoteq}\ []\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ hd\ (rev\ [])\ =\ last\ [] +\end{isabellepar}% +which, after simplification, becomes +\begin{isabellepar}% +\ 1.\ xs\ {\isasymnoteq}\ []\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ hd\ []\ =\ last\ [] +\end{isabellepar}% +We cannot prove this equality because we do not know what \isa{hd} and +\isa{last} return when applied to \isa{[]}. + +The point is that we have violated the above warning. Because the induction +formula is only the conclusion, the occurrence of \isa{xs} in the premises is +not modified by induction. Thus the case that should have been trivial +becomes unprovable. Fortunately, the solution is easy: +\begin{quote} +\emph{Pull all occurrences of the induction variable into the conclusion +using \isa{\isasymlongrightarrow}.} +\end{quote} +This means we should prove% +\end{isamarkuptxt}% +\isacommand{lemma}\ hd\_rev:\ {"}xs\ {\isasymnoteq}\ []\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ hd(rev\ xs)\ =\ last\ xs{"}% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +This time, induction leaves us with the following base case +\begin{isabellepar}% +\ 1.\ []\ {\isasymnoteq}\ []\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ hd\ (rev\ [])\ =\ last\ [] +\end{isabellepar}% +which is trivial, and \isa{auto} finishes the whole proof. + +If \isa{hd\_rev} is meant to be simplification rule, you are done. But if you +really need the \isa{\isasymLongrightarrow}-version of \isa{hd\_rev}, for +example because you want to apply it as an introduction rule, you need to +derive it separately, by combining it with modus ponens:% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemmas}\ hd\_revI\ =\ hd\_rev[THEN\ mp]% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +which yields the lemma we originally set out to prove. + +In case there are multiple premises $A@1$, \dots, $A@n$ containing the +induction variable, you should turn the conclusion $C$ into +\[ A@1 \longrightarrow \cdots A@n \longrightarrow C \] +(see the remark?? in \S\ref{??}). +Additionally, you may also have to universally quantify some other variables, +which can yield a fairly complex conclusion. +Here is a simple example (which is proved by \isa{blast}):% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemma}\ simple:\ {"}{\isasymforall}\ y.\ A\ y\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ B\ y\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ B\ y\ \&\ A\ y{"}% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +You can get the desired lemma by explicit +application of modus ponens and \isa{spec}:% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemmas}\ myrule\ =\ simple[THEN\ spec,\ THEN\ mp,\ THEN\ mp]% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +or the wholesale stripping of \isa{\isasymforall} and +\isa{\isasymlongrightarrow} in the conclusion via \isa{rulify}% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemmas}\ myrule\ =\ simple[rulify]% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +yielding \isa{{\isasymlbrakk}\mbox{?A}\ \mbox{?y};\ \mbox{?B}\ \mbox{?y}{\isasymrbrakk}\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ \mbox{?B}\ \mbox{?y}\ {\isasymand}\ \mbox{?A}\ \mbox{?y}}. +You can go one step further and include these derivations already in the +statement of your original lemma, thus avoiding the intermediate step:% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemma}\ myrule[rulify]:\ \ {"}{\isasymforall}\ y.\ A\ y\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ B\ y\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ B\ y\ \&\ A\ y{"}% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\bigskip + +A second reason why your proposition may not be amenable to induction is that +you want to induct on a whole term, rather than an individual variable. In +general, when inducting on some term $t$ you must rephrase the conclusion as +\[ \forall y@1 \dots y@n.~ x = t \longrightarrow C \] where $y@1 \dots y@n$ +are the free variables in $t$ and $x$ is new, and perform induction on $x$ +afterwards. An example appears below.% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +% +\isamarkupsubsection{Beyond structural induction} +% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +So far, inductive proofs where by structural induction for +primitive recursive functions and recursion induction for total recursive +functions. But sometimes structural induction is awkward and there is no +recursive function in sight either that could furnish a more appropriate +induction schema. In such cases some existing standard induction schema can +be helpful. We show how to apply such induction schemas by an example. + +Structural induction on \isa{nat} is +usually known as ``mathematical induction''. There is also ``complete +induction'', where you must prove $P(n)$ under the assumption that $P(m)$ +holds for all $m\ nat{"}\isanewline +\isacommand{axioms}\ f\_ax:\ {"}f(f(n))\ <\ f(Suc(n)){"}% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +From the above axiom\footnote{In general, the use of axioms is strongly +discouraged, because of the danger of inconsistencies. The above axiom does +not introduce an inconsistency because, for example, the identity function +satisfies it.} +for \isa{f} it follows that \isa{\mbox{n}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ \mbox{n}}, which can +be proved by induction on \isa{f\ \mbox{n}}. Following the recipy outlined +above, we have to phrase the proposition as follows to allow induction:% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemma}\ f\_incr\_lem:\ {"}{\isasymforall}i.\ k\ =\ f\ i\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ i\ {\isasymle}\ f\ i{"}% +\begin{isamarkuptxt}% +\noindent +To perform induction on \isa{k} using \isa{less\_induct}, we use the same +general induction method as for recursion induction (see +\S\ref{sec:recdef-induction}):% +\end{isamarkuptxt}% +\isacommand{apply}(induct\_tac\ k\ rule:less\_induct)% +\begin{isamarkuptxt}% +\noindent +which leaves us with the following proof state: +\begin{isabellepar}% +\ 1.\ {\isasymAnd}\mbox{n}.\ {\isasymforall}\mbox{m}.\ \mbox{m}\ <\ \mbox{n}\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ ({\isasymforall}\mbox{i}.\ \mbox{m}\ =\ f\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ \mbox{i})\isanewline +\ \ \ \ \ \ \ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ {\isasymforall}\mbox{i}.\ \mbox{n}\ =\ f\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ \mbox{i} +\end{isabellepar}% +After stripping the \isa{\isasymforall i}, the proof continues with a case +distinction on \isa{i}. The case \isa{i = 0} is trivial and we focus on the +other case: +\begin{isabellepar}% +\ 1.\ {\isasymAnd}\mbox{n}\ \mbox{i}\ \mbox{nat}.\isanewline +\ \ \ \ \ \ \ {\isasymlbrakk}{\isasymforall}\mbox{m}.\ \mbox{m}\ <\ \mbox{n}\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ ({\isasymforall}\mbox{i}.\ \mbox{m}\ =\ f\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ \mbox{i});\ \mbox{i}\ =\ Suc\ \mbox{nat}{\isasymrbrakk}\isanewline +\ \ \ \ \ \ \ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ \mbox{n}\ =\ f\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ \mbox{i}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ \mbox{i} +\end{isabellepar}%% +\end{isamarkuptxt}% +\isacommand{by}(blast\ intro!:\ f\_ax\ Suc\_leI\ intro:le\_less\_trans)% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\noindent +It is not surprising if you find the last step puzzling. +The proof goes like this (writing \isa{j} instead of \isa{nat}). +Since \isa{\mbox{i}\ =\ Suc\ \mbox{j}} it suffices to show +\isa{\mbox{j}\ <\ f\ (Suc\ \mbox{j})} (by \isa{Suc\_leI}: \isa{\mbox{?m}\ <\ \mbox{?n}\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ Suc\ \mbox{?m}\ {\isasymle}\ \mbox{?n}}). This is +proved as follows. From \isa{f\_ax} we have \isa{f\ (f\ \mbox{j})\ <\ f\ (Suc\ \mbox{j})} +(1) which implies \isa{f\ \mbox{j}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ (f\ \mbox{j})} (by the induction hypothesis). +Using (1) once more we obtain \isa{f\ \mbox{j}\ <\ f\ (Suc\ \mbox{j})} (2) by transitivity +(\isa{le_less_trans}: \isa{{\isasymlbrakk}\mbox{?i}\ {\isasymle}\ \mbox{?j};\ \mbox{?j}\ <\ \mbox{?k}{\isasymrbrakk}\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ \mbox{?i}\ <\ \mbox{?k}}). +Using the induction hypothesis once more we obtain \isa{\mbox{j}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ \mbox{j}} +which, together with (2) yields \isa{\mbox{j}\ <\ f\ (Suc\ \mbox{j})} (again by +\isa{le_less_trans}). + +This last step shows both the power and the danger of automatic proofs: they +will usually not tell you how the proof goes, because it can be very hard to +translate the internal proof into a human-readable format. Therefore +\S\ref{sec:part2?} introduces a language for writing readable yet concise +proofs. + +We can now derive the desired \isa{\mbox{i}\ {\isasymle}\ f\ \mbox{i}} from \isa{f\_incr}:% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemmas}\ f\_incr\ =\ f\_incr\_lem[rulify,\ OF\ refl]% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +The final \isa{refl} gets rid of the premise \isa{?k = f ?i}. Again, we could +have included this derivation in the original statement of the lemma:% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\isacommand{lemma}\ f\_incr[rulify,\ OF\ refl]:\ {"}{\isasymforall}i.\ k\ =\ f\ i\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ i\ {\isasymle}\ f\ i{"}% +\begin{isamarkuptext}% +\begin{exercise} +From the above axiom and lemma for \isa{f} show that \isa{f} is the identity. +\end{exercise} + +In general, \isa{induct\_tac} can be applied with any rule \isa{r} +whose conclusion is of the form \isa{?P ?x1 \dots ?xn}, in which case the +format is +\begin{ttbox} +apply(induct_tac y1 ... yn rule: r) +\end{ttbox}\index{*induct_tac}% +where \isa{y1}, \dots, \isa{yn} are variables in the first subgoal. +In fact, \isa{induct\_tac} even allows the conclusion of +\isa{r} to be an (iterated) conjunction of formulae of the above form, in +which case the application is +\begin{ttbox} +apply(induct_tac y1 ... yn and ... and z1 ... zm rule: r) +\end{ttbox} + +Finally we should mention that HOL already provides the mother of all +inductions, \emph{wellfounded induction} (\isa{wf\_induct}): +\begin{quote} + +\begin{isabelle}% +{\isasymlbrakk}wf\ \mbox{?r};\ {\isasymAnd}\mbox{x}.\ {\isasymforall}\mbox{y}.\ (\mbox{y},\ \mbox{x})\ {\isasymin}\ \mbox{?r}\ {\isasymlongrightarrow}\ \mbox{?P}\ \mbox{y}\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ \mbox{?P}\ \mbox{x}{\isasymrbrakk}\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ \mbox{?P}\ \mbox{?a} +\end{isabelle}% + +\end{quote} +For details see the library.% +\end{isamarkuptext}% +\end{isabelle}% +%%% Local Variables: +%%% mode: latex +%%% TeX-master: "root" +%%% End: