diff -r 419116f1157a -r e23770bc97c8 doc-src/IsarImplementation/Thy/logic.thy --- a/doc-src/IsarImplementation/Thy/logic.thy Thu Feb 26 08:44:44 2009 -0800 +++ /dev/null Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000 @@ -1,851 +0,0 @@ -theory logic imports base begin - -chapter {* Primitive logic \label{ch:logic} *} - -text {* - The logical foundations of Isabelle/Isar are that of the Pure logic, - which has been introduced as a natural-deduction framework in - \cite{paulson700}. This is essentially the same logic as ``@{text - "\HOL"}'' in the more abstract setting of Pure Type Systems (PTS) - \cite{Barendregt-Geuvers:2001}, although there are some key - differences in the specific treatment of simple types in - Isabelle/Pure. - - Following type-theoretic parlance, the Pure logic consists of three - levels of @{text "\"}-calculus with corresponding arrows, @{text - "\"} for syntactic function space (terms depending on terms), @{text - "\"} for universal quantification (proofs depending on terms), and - @{text "\"} for implication (proofs depending on proofs). - - Derivations are relative to a logical theory, which declares type - constructors, constants, and axioms. Theory declarations support - schematic polymorphism, which is strictly speaking outside the - logic.\footnote{This is the deeper logical reason, why the theory - context @{text "\"} is separate from the proof context @{text "\"} - of the core calculus.} -*} - - -section {* Types \label{sec:types} *} - -text {* - The language of types is an uninterpreted order-sorted first-order - algebra; types are qualified by ordered type classes. - - \medskip A \emph{type class} is an abstract syntactic entity - declared in the theory context. The \emph{subclass relation} @{text - "c\<^isub>1 \ c\<^isub>2"} is specified by stating an acyclic - generating relation; the transitive closure is maintained - internally. The resulting relation is an ordering: reflexive, - transitive, and antisymmetric. - - A \emph{sort} is a list of type classes written as @{text "s = - {c\<^isub>1, \, c\<^isub>m}"}, which represents symbolic - intersection. Notationally, the curly braces are omitted for - singleton intersections, i.e.\ any class @{text "c"} may be read as - a sort @{text "{c}"}. The ordering on type classes is extended to - sorts according to the meaning of intersections: @{text - "{c\<^isub>1, \ c\<^isub>m} \ {d\<^isub>1, \, d\<^isub>n}"} iff - @{text "\j. \i. c\<^isub>i \ d\<^isub>j"}. The empty intersection - @{text "{}"} refers to the universal sort, which is the largest - element wrt.\ the sort order. The intersections of all (finitely - many) classes declared in the current theory are the minimal - elements wrt.\ the sort order. - - \medskip A \emph{fixed type variable} is a pair of a basic name - (starting with a @{text "'"} character) and a sort constraint, e.g.\ - @{text "('a, s)"} which is usually printed as @{text "\\<^isub>s"}. - A \emph{schematic type variable} is a pair of an indexname and a - sort constraint, e.g.\ @{text "(('a, 0), s)"} which is usually - printed as @{text "?\\<^isub>s"}. - - Note that \emph{all} syntactic components contribute to the identity - of type variables, including the sort constraint. The core logic - handles type variables with the same name but different sorts as - different, although some outer layers of the system make it hard to - produce anything like this. - - A \emph{type constructor} @{text "\"} is a @{text "k"}-ary operator - on types declared in the theory. Type constructor application is - written postfix as @{text "(\\<^isub>1, \, \\<^isub>k)\"}. For - @{text "k = 0"} the argument tuple is omitted, e.g.\ @{text "prop"} - instead of @{text "()prop"}. For @{text "k = 1"} the parentheses - are omitted, e.g.\ @{text "\ list"} instead of @{text "(\)list"}. - Further notation is provided for specific constructors, notably the - right-associative infix @{text "\ \ \"} instead of @{text "(\, - \)fun"}. - - A \emph{type} is defined inductively over type variables and type - constructors as follows: @{text "\ = \\<^isub>s | ?\\<^isub>s | - (\\<^sub>1, \, \\<^sub>k)\"}. - - A \emph{type abbreviation} is a syntactic definition @{text - "(\<^vec>\)\ = \"} of an arbitrary type expression @{text "\"} over - variables @{text "\<^vec>\"}. Type abbreviations appear as type - constructors in the syntax, but are expanded before entering the - logical core. - - A \emph{type arity} declares the image behavior of a type - constructor wrt.\ the algebra of sorts: @{text "\ :: (s\<^isub>1, \, - s\<^isub>k)s"} means that @{text "(\\<^isub>1, \, \\<^isub>k)\"} is - of sort @{text "s"} if every argument type @{text "\\<^isub>i"} is - of sort @{text "s\<^isub>i"}. Arity declarations are implicitly - completed, i.e.\ @{text "\ :: (\<^vec>s)c"} entails @{text "\ :: - (\<^vec>s)c'"} for any @{text "c' \ c"}. - - \medskip The sort algebra is always maintained as \emph{coregular}, - which means that type arities are consistent with the subclass - relation: for any type constructor @{text "\"}, and classes @{text - "c\<^isub>1 \ c\<^isub>2"}, and arities @{text "\ :: - (\<^vec>s\<^isub>1)c\<^isub>1"} and @{text "\ :: - (\<^vec>s\<^isub>2)c\<^isub>2"} holds @{text "\<^vec>s\<^isub>1 \ - \<^vec>s\<^isub>2"} component-wise. - - The key property of a coregular order-sorted algebra is that sort - constraints can be solved in a most general fashion: for each type - constructor @{text "\"} and sort @{text "s"} there is a most general - vector of argument sorts @{text "(s\<^isub>1, \, s\<^isub>k)"} such - that a type scheme @{text "(\\<^bsub>s\<^isub>1\<^esub>, \, - \\<^bsub>s\<^isub>k\<^esub>)\"} is of sort @{text "s"}. - Consequently, type unification has most general solutions (modulo - equivalence of sorts), so type-inference produces primary types as - expected \cite{nipkow-prehofer}. -*} - -text %mlref {* - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML_type class} \\ - @{index_ML_type sort} \\ - @{index_ML_type arity} \\ - @{index_ML_type typ} \\ - @{index_ML map_atyps: "(typ -> typ) -> typ -> typ"} \\ - @{index_ML fold_atyps: "(typ -> 'a -> 'a) -> typ -> 'a -> 'a"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML Sign.subsort: "theory -> sort * sort -> bool"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.of_sort: "theory -> typ * sort -> bool"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.add_types: "(string * int * mixfix) list -> theory -> theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.add_tyabbrs_i: " - (string * string list * typ * mixfix) list -> theory -> theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.primitive_class: "string * class list -> theory -> theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.primitive_classrel: "class * class -> theory -> theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.primitive_arity: "arity -> theory -> theory"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - - \begin{description} - - \item @{ML_type class} represents type classes; this is an alias for - @{ML_type string}. - - \item @{ML_type sort} represents sorts; this is an alias for - @{ML_type "class list"}. - - \item @{ML_type arity} represents type arities; this is an alias for - triples of the form @{text "(\, \<^vec>s, s)"} for @{text "\ :: - (\<^vec>s)s"} described above. - - \item @{ML_type typ} represents types; this is a datatype with - constructors @{ML TFree}, @{ML TVar}, @{ML Type}. - - \item @{ML map_atyps}~@{text "f \"} applies the mapping @{text "f"} - to all atomic types (@{ML TFree}, @{ML TVar}) occurring in @{text - "\"}. - - \item @{ML fold_atyps}~@{text "f \"} iterates the operation @{text - "f"} over all occurrences of atomic types (@{ML TFree}, @{ML TVar}) - in @{text "\"}; the type structure is traversed from left to right. - - \item @{ML Sign.subsort}~@{text "thy (s\<^isub>1, s\<^isub>2)"} - tests the subsort relation @{text "s\<^isub>1 \ s\<^isub>2"}. - - \item @{ML Sign.of_sort}~@{text "thy (\, s)"} tests whether type - @{text "\"} is of sort @{text "s"}. - - \item @{ML Sign.add_types}~@{text "[(\, k, mx), \]"} declares a new - type constructors @{text "\"} with @{text "k"} arguments and - optional mixfix syntax. - - \item @{ML Sign.add_tyabbrs_i}~@{text "[(\, \<^vec>\, \, mx), \]"} - defines a new type abbreviation @{text "(\<^vec>\)\ = \"} with - optional mixfix syntax. - - \item @{ML Sign.primitive_class}~@{text "(c, [c\<^isub>1, \, - c\<^isub>n])"} declares a new class @{text "c"}, together with class - relations @{text "c \ c\<^isub>i"}, for @{text "i = 1, \, n"}. - - \item @{ML Sign.primitive_classrel}~@{text "(c\<^isub>1, - c\<^isub>2)"} declares the class relation @{text "c\<^isub>1 \ - c\<^isub>2"}. - - \item @{ML Sign.primitive_arity}~@{text "(\, \<^vec>s, s)"} declares - the arity @{text "\ :: (\<^vec>s)s"}. - - \end{description} -*} - - - -section {* Terms \label{sec:terms} *} - -text {* - \glossary{Term}{FIXME} - - The language of terms is that of simply-typed @{text "\"}-calculus - with de-Bruijn indices for bound variables (cf.\ \cite{debruijn72} - or \cite{paulson-ml2}), with the types being determined determined - by the corresponding binders. In contrast, free variables and - constants are have an explicit name and type in each occurrence. - - \medskip A \emph{bound variable} is a natural number @{text "b"}, - which accounts for the number of intermediate binders between the - variable occurrence in the body and its binding position. For - example, the de-Bruijn term @{text - "\\<^bsub>nat\<^esub>. \\<^bsub>nat\<^esub>. 1 + 0"} would - correspond to @{text - "\x\<^bsub>nat\<^esub>. \y\<^bsub>nat\<^esub>. x + y"} in a named - representation. Note that a bound variable may be represented by - different de-Bruijn indices at different occurrences, depending on - the nesting of abstractions. - - A \emph{loose variable} is a bound variable that is outside the - scope of local binders. The types (and names) for loose variables - can be managed as a separate context, that is maintained as a stack - of hypothetical binders. The core logic operates on closed terms, - without any loose variables. - - A \emph{fixed variable} is a pair of a basic name and a type, e.g.\ - @{text "(x, \)"} which is usually printed @{text "x\<^isub>\"}. A - \emph{schematic variable} is a pair of an indexname and a type, - e.g.\ @{text "((x, 0), \)"} which is usually printed as @{text - "?x\<^isub>\"}. - - \medskip A \emph{constant} is a pair of a basic name and a type, - e.g.\ @{text "(c, \)"} which is usually printed as @{text - "c\<^isub>\"}. Constants are declared in the context as polymorphic - families @{text "c :: \"}, meaning that all substitution instances - @{text "c\<^isub>\"} for @{text "\ = \\"} are valid. - - The vector of \emph{type arguments} of constant @{text "c\<^isub>\"} - wrt.\ the declaration @{text "c :: \"} is defined as the codomain of - the matcher @{text "\ = {?\\<^isub>1 \ \\<^isub>1, \, - ?\\<^isub>n \ \\<^isub>n}"} presented in canonical order @{text - "(\\<^isub>1, \, \\<^isub>n)"}. Within a given theory context, - there is a one-to-one correspondence between any constant @{text - "c\<^isub>\"} and the application @{text "c(\\<^isub>1, \, - \\<^isub>n)"} of its type arguments. For example, with @{text "plus - :: \ \ \ \ \"}, the instance @{text "plus\<^bsub>nat \ nat \ - nat\<^esub>"} corresponds to @{text "plus(nat)"}. - - Constant declarations @{text "c :: \"} may contain sort constraints - for type variables in @{text "\"}. These are observed by - type-inference as expected, but \emph{ignored} by the core logic. - This means the primitive logic is able to reason with instances of - polymorphic constants that the user-level type-checker would reject - due to violation of type class restrictions. - - \medskip An \emph{atomic} term is either a variable or constant. A - \emph{term} is defined inductively over atomic terms, with - abstraction and application as follows: @{text "t = b | x\<^isub>\ | - ?x\<^isub>\ | c\<^isub>\ | \\<^isub>\. t | t\<^isub>1 t\<^isub>2"}. - Parsing and printing takes care of converting between an external - representation with named bound variables. Subsequently, we shall - use the latter notation instead of internal de-Bruijn - representation. - - The inductive relation @{text "t :: \"} assigns a (unique) type to a - term according to the structure of atomic terms, abstractions, and - applicatins: - \[ - \infer{@{text "a\<^isub>\ :: \"}}{} - \qquad - \infer{@{text "(\x\<^sub>\. t) :: \ \ \"}}{@{text "t :: \"}} - \qquad - \infer{@{text "t u :: \"}}{@{text "t :: \ \ \"} & @{text "u :: \"}} - \] - A \emph{well-typed term} is a term that can be typed according to these rules. - - Typing information can be omitted: type-inference is able to - reconstruct the most general type of a raw term, while assigning - most general types to all of its variables and constants. - Type-inference depends on a context of type constraints for fixed - variables, and declarations for polymorphic constants. - - The identity of atomic terms consists both of the name and the type - component. This means that different variables @{text - "x\<^bsub>\\<^isub>1\<^esub>"} and @{text - "x\<^bsub>\\<^isub>2\<^esub>"} may become the same after type - instantiation. Some outer layers of the system make it hard to - produce variables of the same name, but different types. In - contrast, mixed instances of polymorphic constants occur frequently. - - \medskip The \emph{hidden polymorphism} of a term @{text "t :: \"} - is the set of type variables occurring in @{text "t"}, but not in - @{text "\"}. This means that the term implicitly depends on type - arguments that are not accounted in the result type, i.e.\ there are - different type instances @{text "t\ :: \"} and @{text - "t\' :: \"} with the same type. This slightly - pathological situation notoriously demands additional care. - - \medskip A \emph{term abbreviation} is a syntactic definition @{text - "c\<^isub>\ \ t"} of a closed term @{text "t"} of type @{text "\"}, - without any hidden polymorphism. A term abbreviation looks like a - constant in the syntax, but is expanded before entering the logical - core. Abbreviations are usually reverted when printing terms, using - @{text "t \ c\<^isub>\"} as rules for higher-order rewriting. - - \medskip Canonical operations on @{text "\"}-terms include @{text - "\\\"}-conversion: @{text "\"}-conversion refers to capture-free - renaming of bound variables; @{text "\"}-conversion contracts an - abstraction applied to an argument term, substituting the argument - in the body: @{text "(\x. b)a"} becomes @{text "b[a/x]"}; @{text - "\"}-conversion contracts vacuous application-abstraction: @{text - "\x. f x"} becomes @{text "f"}, provided that the bound variable - does not occur in @{text "f"}. - - Terms are normally treated modulo @{text "\"}-conversion, which is - implicit in the de-Bruijn representation. Names for bound variables - in abstractions are maintained separately as (meaningless) comments, - mostly for parsing and printing. Full @{text "\\\"}-conversion is - commonplace in various standard operations (\secref{sec:obj-rules}) - that are based on higher-order unification and matching. -*} - -text %mlref {* - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML_type term} \\ - @{index_ML "op aconv": "term * term -> bool"} \\ - @{index_ML map_types: "(typ -> typ) -> term -> term"} \\ - @{index_ML fold_types: "(typ -> 'a -> 'a) -> term -> 'a -> 'a"} \\ - @{index_ML map_aterms: "(term -> term) -> term -> term"} \\ - @{index_ML fold_aterms: "(term -> 'a -> 'a) -> term -> 'a -> 'a"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML fastype_of: "term -> typ"} \\ - @{index_ML lambda: "term -> term -> term"} \\ - @{index_ML betapply: "term * term -> term"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.declare_const: "Properties.T -> (binding * typ) * mixfix -> - theory -> term * theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.add_abbrev: "string -> Properties.T -> binding * term -> - theory -> (term * term) * theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.const_typargs: "theory -> string * typ -> typ list"} \\ - @{index_ML Sign.const_instance: "theory -> string * typ list -> typ"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - - \begin{description} - - \item @{ML_type term} represents de-Bruijn terms, with comments in - abstractions, and explicitly named free variables and constants; - this is a datatype with constructors @{ML Bound}, @{ML Free}, @{ML - Var}, @{ML Const}, @{ML Abs}, @{ML "op $"}. - - \item @{text "t"}~@{ML aconv}~@{text "u"} checks @{text - "\"}-equivalence of two terms. This is the basic equality relation - on type @{ML_type term}; raw datatype equality should only be used - for operations related to parsing or printing! - - \item @{ML map_types}~@{text "f t"} applies the mapping @{text - "f"} to all types occurring in @{text "t"}. - - \item @{ML fold_types}~@{text "f t"} iterates the operation @{text - "f"} over all occurrences of types in @{text "t"}; the term - structure is traversed from left to right. - - \item @{ML map_aterms}~@{text "f t"} applies the mapping @{text "f"} - to all atomic terms (@{ML Bound}, @{ML Free}, @{ML Var}, @{ML - Const}) occurring in @{text "t"}. - - \item @{ML fold_aterms}~@{text "f t"} iterates the operation @{text - "f"} over all occurrences of atomic terms (@{ML Bound}, @{ML Free}, - @{ML Var}, @{ML Const}) in @{text "t"}; the term structure is - traversed from left to right. - - \item @{ML fastype_of}~@{text "t"} determines the type of a - well-typed term. This operation is relatively slow, despite the - omission of any sanity checks. - - \item @{ML lambda}~@{text "a b"} produces an abstraction @{text - "\a. b"}, where occurrences of the atomic term @{text "a"} in the - body @{text "b"} are replaced by bound variables. - - \item @{ML betapply}~@{text "(t, u)"} produces an application @{text - "t u"}, with topmost @{text "\"}-conversion if @{text "t"} is an - abstraction. - - \item @{ML Sign.declare_const}~@{text "properties ((c, \), mx)"} - declares a new constant @{text "c :: \"} with optional mixfix - syntax. - - \item @{ML Sign.add_abbrev}~@{text "print_mode properties (c, t)"} - introduces a new term abbreviation @{text "c \ t"}. - - \item @{ML Sign.const_typargs}~@{text "thy (c, \)"} and @{ML - Sign.const_instance}~@{text "thy (c, [\\<^isub>1, \, \\<^isub>n])"} - convert between two representations of polymorphic constants: full - type instance vs.\ compact type arguments form. - - \end{description} -*} - - -section {* Theorems \label{sec:thms} *} - -text {* - \glossary{Proposition}{FIXME A \seeglossary{term} of - \seeglossary{type} @{text "prop"}. Internally, there is nothing - special about propositions apart from their type, but the concrete - syntax enforces a clear distinction. Propositions are structured - via implication @{text "A \ B"} or universal quantification @{text - "\x. B x"} --- anything else is considered atomic. The canonical - form for propositions is that of a \seeglossary{Hereditary Harrop - Formula}. FIXME} - - \glossary{Theorem}{A proven proposition within a certain theory and - proof context, formally @{text "\ \\<^sub>\ \"}; both contexts are - rarely spelled out explicitly. Theorems are usually normalized - according to the \seeglossary{HHF} format. FIXME} - - \glossary{Fact}{Sometimes used interchangeably for - \seeglossary{theorem}. Strictly speaking, a list of theorems, - essentially an extra-logical conjunction. Facts emerge either as - local assumptions, or as results of local goal statements --- both - may be simultaneous, hence the list representation. FIXME} - - \glossary{Schematic variable}{FIXME} - - \glossary{Fixed variable}{A variable that is bound within a certain - proof context; an arbitrary-but-fixed entity within a portion of - proof text. FIXME} - - \glossary{Free variable}{Synonymous for \seeglossary{fixed - variable}. FIXME} - - \glossary{Bound variable}{FIXME} - - \glossary{Variable}{See \seeglossary{schematic variable}, - \seeglossary{fixed variable}, \seeglossary{bound variable}, or - \seeglossary{type variable}. The distinguishing feature of - different variables is their binding scope. FIXME} - - A \emph{proposition} is a well-typed term of type @{text "prop"}, a - \emph{theorem} is a proven proposition (depending on a context of - hypotheses and the background theory). Primitive inferences include - plain natural deduction rules for the primary connectives @{text - "\"} and @{text "\"} of the framework. There is also a builtin - notion of equality/equivalence @{text "\"}. -*} - -subsection {* Primitive connectives and rules \label{sec:prim-rules} *} - -text {* - The theory @{text "Pure"} contains constant declarations for the - primitive connectives @{text "\"}, @{text "\"}, and @{text "\"} of - the logical framework, see \figref{fig:pure-connectives}. The - derivability judgment @{text "A\<^isub>1, \, A\<^isub>n \ B"} is - defined inductively by the primitive inferences given in - \figref{fig:prim-rules}, with the global restriction that the - hypotheses must \emph{not} contain any schematic variables. The - builtin equality is conceptually axiomatized as shown in - \figref{fig:pure-equality}, although the implementation works - directly with derived inferences. - - \begin{figure}[htb] - \begin{center} - \begin{tabular}{ll} - @{text "all :: (\ \ prop) \ prop"} & universal quantification (binder @{text "\"}) \\ - @{text "\ :: prop \ prop \ prop"} & implication (right associative infix) \\ - @{text "\ :: \ \ \ \ prop"} & equality relation (infix) \\ - \end{tabular} - \caption{Primitive connectives of Pure}\label{fig:pure-connectives} - \end{center} - \end{figure} - - \begin{figure}[htb] - \begin{center} - \[ - \infer[@{text "(axiom)"}]{@{text "\ A"}}{@{text "A \ \"}} - \qquad - \infer[@{text "(assume)"}]{@{text "A \ A"}}{} - \] - \[ - \infer[@{text "(\_intro)"}]{@{text "\ \ \x. b[x]"}}{@{text "\ \ b[x]"} & @{text "x \ \"}} - \qquad - \infer[@{text "(\_elim)"}]{@{text "\ \ b[a]"}}{@{text "\ \ \x. b[x]"}} - \] - \[ - \infer[@{text "(\_intro)"}]{@{text "\ - A \ A \ B"}}{@{text "\ \ B"}} - \qquad - \infer[@{text "(\_elim)"}]{@{text "\\<^sub>1 \ \\<^sub>2 \ B"}}{@{text "\\<^sub>1 \ A \ B"} & @{text "\\<^sub>2 \ A"}} - \] - \caption{Primitive inferences of Pure}\label{fig:prim-rules} - \end{center} - \end{figure} - - \begin{figure}[htb] - \begin{center} - \begin{tabular}{ll} - @{text "\ (\x. b[x]) a \ b[a]"} & @{text "\"}-conversion \\ - @{text "\ x \ x"} & reflexivity \\ - @{text "\ x \ y \ P x \ P y"} & substitution \\ - @{text "\ (\x. f x \ g x) \ f \ g"} & extensionality \\ - @{text "\ (A \ B) \ (B \ A) \ A \ B"} & logical equivalence \\ - \end{tabular} - \caption{Conceptual axiomatization of Pure equality}\label{fig:pure-equality} - \end{center} - \end{figure} - - The introduction and elimination rules for @{text "\"} and @{text - "\"} are analogous to formation of dependently typed @{text - "\"}-terms representing the underlying proof objects. Proof terms - are irrelevant in the Pure logic, though; they cannot occur within - propositions. The system provides a runtime option to record - explicit proof terms for primitive inferences. Thus all three - levels of @{text "\"}-calculus become explicit: @{text "\"} for - terms, and @{text "\/\"} for proofs (cf.\ - \cite{Berghofer-Nipkow:2000:TPHOL}). - - Observe that locally fixed parameters (as in @{text "\_intro"}) need - not be recorded in the hypotheses, because the simple syntactic - types of Pure are always inhabitable. ``Assumptions'' @{text "x :: - \"} for type-membership are only present as long as some @{text - "x\<^isub>\"} occurs in the statement body.\footnote{This is the key - difference to ``@{text "\HOL"}'' in the PTS framework - \cite{Barendregt-Geuvers:2001}, where hypotheses @{text "x : A"} are - treated uniformly for propositions and types.} - - \medskip The axiomatization of a theory is implicitly closed by - forming all instances of type and term variables: @{text "\ - A\"} holds for any substitution instance of an axiom - @{text "\ A"}. By pushing substitutions through derivations - inductively, we also get admissible @{text "generalize"} and @{text - "instance"} rules as shown in \figref{fig:subst-rules}. - - \begin{figure}[htb] - \begin{center} - \[ - \infer{@{text "\ \ B[?\]"}}{@{text "\ \ B[\]"} & @{text "\ \ \"}} - \quad - \infer[\quad@{text "(generalize)"}]{@{text "\ \ B[?x]"}}{@{text "\ \ B[x]"} & @{text "x \ \"}} - \] - \[ - \infer{@{text "\ \ B[\]"}}{@{text "\ \ B[?\]"}} - \quad - \infer[\quad@{text "(instantiate)"}]{@{text "\ \ B[t]"}}{@{text "\ \ B[?x]"}} - \] - \caption{Admissible substitution rules}\label{fig:subst-rules} - \end{center} - \end{figure} - - Note that @{text "instantiate"} does not require an explicit - side-condition, because @{text "\"} may never contain schematic - variables. - - In principle, variables could be substituted in hypotheses as well, - but this would disrupt the monotonicity of reasoning: deriving - @{text "\\ \ B\"} from @{text "\ \ B"} is - correct, but @{text "\\ \ \"} does not necessarily hold: - the result belongs to a different proof context. - - \medskip An \emph{oracle} is a function that produces axioms on the - fly. Logically, this is an instance of the @{text "axiom"} rule - (\figref{fig:prim-rules}), but there is an operational difference. - The system always records oracle invocations within derivations of - theorems. Tracing plain axioms (and named theorems) is optional. - - Axiomatizations should be limited to the bare minimum, typically as - part of the initial logical basis of an object-logic formalization. - Later on, theories are usually developed in a strictly definitional - fashion, by stating only certain equalities over new constants. - - A \emph{simple definition} consists of a constant declaration @{text - "c :: \"} together with an axiom @{text "\ c \ t"}, where @{text "t - :: \"} is a closed term without any hidden polymorphism. The RHS - may depend on further defined constants, but not @{text "c"} itself. - Definitions of functions may be presented as @{text "c \<^vec>x \ - t"} instead of the puristic @{text "c \ \\<^vec>x. t"}. - - An \emph{overloaded definition} consists of a collection of axioms - for the same constant, with zero or one equations @{text - "c((\<^vec>\)\) \ t"} for each type constructor @{text "\"} (for - distinct variables @{text "\<^vec>\"}). The RHS may mention - previously defined constants as above, or arbitrary constants @{text - "d(\\<^isub>i)"} for some @{text "\\<^isub>i"} projected from @{text - "\<^vec>\"}. Thus overloaded definitions essentially work by - primitive recursion over the syntactic structure of a single type - argument. -*} - -text %mlref {* - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML_type ctyp} \\ - @{index_ML_type cterm} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.ctyp_of: "theory -> typ -> ctyp"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.cterm_of: "theory -> term -> cterm"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML_type thm} \\ - @{index_ML proofs: "int ref"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.assume: "cterm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.forall_intr: "cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.forall_elim: "cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.implies_intr: "cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.implies_elim: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.generalize: "string list * string list -> int -> thm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.instantiate: "(ctyp * ctyp) list * (cterm * cterm) list -> thm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.axiom: "theory -> string -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Thm.add_oracle: "bstring * ('a -> cterm) -> theory - -> (string * ('a -> thm)) * theory"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML Theory.add_axioms_i: "(binding * term) list -> theory -> theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Theory.add_deps: "string -> string * typ -> (string * typ) list -> theory -> theory"} \\ - @{index_ML Theory.add_defs_i: "bool -> bool -> (binding * term) list -> theory -> theory"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - - \begin{description} - - \item @{ML_type ctyp} and @{ML_type cterm} represent certified types - and terms, respectively. These are abstract datatypes that - guarantee that its values have passed the full well-formedness (and - well-typedness) checks, relative to the declarations of type - constructors, constants etc. in the theory. - - \item @{ML ctyp_of}~@{text "thy \"} and @{ML cterm_of}~@{text "thy - t"} explicitly checks types and terms, respectively. This also - involves some basic normalizations, such expansion of type and term - abbreviations from the theory context. - - Re-certification is relatively slow and should be avoided in tight - reasoning loops. There are separate operations to decompose - certified entities (including actual theorems). - - \item @{ML_type thm} represents proven propositions. This is an - abstract datatype that guarantees that its values have been - constructed by basic principles of the @{ML_struct Thm} module. - Every @{ML thm} value contains a sliding back-reference to the - enclosing theory, cf.\ \secref{sec:context-theory}. - - \item @{ML proofs} determines the detail of proof recording within - @{ML_type thm} values: @{ML 0} records only oracles, @{ML 1} records - oracles, axioms and named theorems, @{ML 2} records full proof - terms. - - \item @{ML Thm.assume}, @{ML Thm.forall_intr}, @{ML - Thm.forall_elim}, @{ML Thm.implies_intr}, and @{ML Thm.implies_elim} - correspond to the primitive inferences of \figref{fig:prim-rules}. - - \item @{ML Thm.generalize}~@{text "(\<^vec>\, \<^vec>x)"} - corresponds to the @{text "generalize"} rules of - \figref{fig:subst-rules}. Here collections of type and term - variables are generalized simultaneously, specified by the given - basic names. - - \item @{ML Thm.instantiate}~@{text "(\<^vec>\\<^isub>s, - \<^vec>x\<^isub>\)"} corresponds to the @{text "instantiate"} rules - of \figref{fig:subst-rules}. Type variables are substituted before - term variables. Note that the types in @{text "\<^vec>x\<^isub>\"} - refer to the instantiated versions. - - \item @{ML Thm.axiom}~@{text "thy name"} retrieves a named - axiom, cf.\ @{text "axiom"} in \figref{fig:prim-rules}. - - \item @{ML Thm.add_oracle}~@{text "(name, oracle)"} produces a named - oracle rule, essentially generating arbitrary axioms on the fly, - cf.\ @{text "axiom"} in \figref{fig:prim-rules}. - - \item @{ML Theory.add_axioms_i}~@{text "[(name, A), \]"} declares - arbitrary propositions as axioms. - - \item @{ML Theory.add_deps}~@{text "name c\<^isub>\ - \<^vec>d\<^isub>\"} declares dependencies of a named specification - for constant @{text "c\<^isub>\"}, relative to existing - specifications for constants @{text "\<^vec>d\<^isub>\"}. - - \item @{ML Theory.add_defs_i}~@{text "unchecked overloaded [(name, c - \<^vec>x \ t), \]"} states a definitional axiom for an existing - constant @{text "c"}. Dependencies are recorded (cf.\ @{ML - Theory.add_deps}), unless the @{text "unchecked"} option is set. - - \end{description} -*} - - -subsection {* Auxiliary definitions *} - -text {* - Theory @{text "Pure"} provides a few auxiliary definitions, see - \figref{fig:pure-aux}. These special constants are normally not - exposed to the user, but appear in internal encodings. - - \begin{figure}[htb] - \begin{center} - \begin{tabular}{ll} - @{text "conjunction :: prop \ prop \ prop"} & (infix @{text "&"}) \\ - @{text "\ A & B \ (\C. (A \ B \ C) \ C)"} \\[1ex] - @{text "prop :: prop \ prop"} & (prefix @{text "#"}, suppressed) \\ - @{text "#A \ A"} \\[1ex] - @{text "term :: \ \ prop"} & (prefix @{text "TERM"}) \\ - @{text "term x \ (\A. A \ A)"} \\[1ex] - @{text "TYPE :: \ itself"} & (prefix @{text "TYPE"}) \\ - @{text "(unspecified)"} \\ - \end{tabular} - \caption{Definitions of auxiliary connectives}\label{fig:pure-aux} - \end{center} - \end{figure} - - Derived conjunction rules include introduction @{text "A \ B \ A & - B"}, and destructions @{text "A & B \ A"} and @{text "A & B \ B"}. - Conjunction allows to treat simultaneous assumptions and conclusions - uniformly. For example, multiple claims are intermediately - represented as explicit conjunction, but this is refined into - separate sub-goals before the user continues the proof; the final - result is projected into a list of theorems (cf.\ - \secref{sec:tactical-goals}). - - The @{text "prop"} marker (@{text "#"}) makes arbitrarily complex - propositions appear as atomic, without changing the meaning: @{text - "\ \ A"} and @{text "\ \ #A"} are interchangeable. See - \secref{sec:tactical-goals} for specific operations. - - The @{text "term"} marker turns any well-typed term into a derivable - proposition: @{text "\ TERM t"} holds unconditionally. Although - this is logically vacuous, it allows to treat terms and proofs - uniformly, similar to a type-theoretic framework. - - The @{text "TYPE"} constructor is the canonical representative of - the unspecified type @{text "\ itself"}; it essentially injects the - language of types into that of terms. There is specific notation - @{text "TYPE(\)"} for @{text "TYPE\<^bsub>\ - itself\<^esub>"}. - Although being devoid of any particular meaning, the @{text - "TYPE(\)"} accounts for the type @{text "\"} within the term - language. In particular, @{text "TYPE(\)"} may be used as formal - argument in primitive definitions, in order to circumvent hidden - polymorphism (cf.\ \secref{sec:terms}). For example, @{text "c - TYPE(\) \ A[\]"} defines @{text "c :: \ itself \ prop"} in terms of - a proposition @{text "A"} that depends on an additional type - argument, which is essentially a predicate on types. -*} - -text %mlref {* - \begin{mldecls} - @{index_ML Conjunction.intr: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Conjunction.elim: "thm -> thm * thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Drule.mk_term: "cterm -> thm"} \\ - @{index_ML Drule.dest_term: "thm -> cterm"} \\ - @{index_ML Logic.mk_type: "typ -> term"} \\ - @{index_ML Logic.dest_type: "term -> typ"} \\ - \end{mldecls} - - \begin{description} - - \item @{ML Conjunction.intr} derives @{text "A & B"} from @{text - "A"} and @{text "B"}. - - \item @{ML Conjunction.elim} derives @{text "A"} and @{text "B"} - from @{text "A & B"}. - - \item @{ML Drule.mk_term} derives @{text "TERM t"}. - - \item @{ML Drule.dest_term} recovers term @{text "t"} from @{text - "TERM t"}. - - \item @{ML Logic.mk_type}~@{text "\"} produces the term @{text - "TYPE(\)"}. - - \item @{ML Logic.dest_type}~@{text "TYPE(\)"} recovers the type - @{text "\"}. - - \end{description} -*} - - -section {* Object-level rules \label{sec:obj-rules} *} - -text %FIXME {* - -FIXME - - A \emph{rule} is any Pure theorem in HHF normal form; there is a - separate calculus for rule composition, which is modeled after - Gentzen's Natural Deduction \cite{Gentzen:1935}, but allows - rules to be nested arbitrarily, similar to \cite{extensions91}. - - Normally, all theorems accessible to the user are proper rules. - Low-level inferences are occasional required internally, but the - result should be always presented in canonical form. The higher - interfaces of Isabelle/Isar will always produce proper rules. It is - important to maintain this invariant in add-on applications! - - There are two main principles of rule composition: @{text - "resolution"} (i.e.\ backchaining of rules) and @{text - "by-assumption"} (i.e.\ closing a branch); both principles are - combined in the variants of @{text "elim-resolution"} and @{text - "dest-resolution"}. Raw @{text "composition"} is occasionally - useful as well, also it is strictly speaking outside of the proper - rule calculus. - - Rules are treated modulo general higher-order unification, which is - unification modulo the equational theory of @{text "\\\"}-conversion - on @{text "\"}-terms. Moreover, propositions are understood modulo - the (derived) equivalence @{text "(A \ (\x. B x)) \ (\x. A \ B x)"}. - - This means that any operations within the rule calculus may be - subject to spontaneous @{text "\\\"}-HHF conversions. It is common - practice not to contract or expand unnecessarily. Some mechanisms - prefer an one form, others the opposite, so there is a potential - danger to produce some oscillation! - - Only few operations really work \emph{modulo} HHF conversion, but - expect a normal form: quantifiers @{text "\"} before implications - @{text "\"} at each level of nesting. - -\glossary{Hereditary Harrop Formula}{The set of propositions in HHF -format is defined inductively as @{text "H = (\x\<^sup>*. H\<^sup>* \ -A)"}, for variables @{text "x"} and atomic propositions @{text "A"}. -Any proposition may be put into HHF form by normalizing with the rule -@{text "(A \ (\x. B x)) \ (\x. A \ B x)"}. In Isabelle, the outermost -quantifier prefix is represented via \seeglossary{schematic -variables}, such that the top-level structure is merely that of a -\seeglossary{Horn Clause}}. - -\glossary{HHF}{See \seeglossary{Hereditary Harrop Formula}.} - - - \[ - \infer[@{text "(assumption)"}]{@{text "C\"}} - {@{text "(\\<^vec>x. \<^vec>H \<^vec>x \ A \<^vec>x) \ C"} & @{text "A\ = H\<^sub>i\"}~~\text{(for some~@{text i})}} - \] - - - \[ - \infer[@{text "(compose)"}]{@{text "\<^vec>A\ \ C\"}} - {@{text "\<^vec>A \ B"} & @{text "B' \ C"} & @{text "B\ = B'\"}} - \] - - - \[ - \infer[@{text "(\_lift)"}]{@{text "(\\<^vec>x. \<^vec>A (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x)) \ (\\<^vec>x. B (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x))"}}{@{text "\<^vec>A ?\<^vec>a \ B ?\<^vec>a"}} - \] - \[ - \infer[@{text "(\_lift)"}]{@{text "(\<^vec>H \ \<^vec>A) \ (\<^vec>H \ B)"}}{@{text "\<^vec>A \ B"}} - \] - - The @{text resolve} scheme is now acquired from @{text "\_lift"}, - @{text "\_lift"}, and @{text compose}. - - \[ - \infer[@{text "(resolution)"}] - {@{text "(\\<^vec>x. \<^vec>H \<^vec>x \ \<^vec>A (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x))\ \ C\"}} - {\begin{tabular}{l} - @{text "\<^vec>A ?\<^vec>a \ B ?\<^vec>a"} \\ - @{text "(\\<^vec>x. \<^vec>H \<^vec>x \ B' \<^vec>x) \ C"} \\ - @{text "(\\<^vec>x. B (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x))\ = B'\"} \\ - \end{tabular}} - \] - - - FIXME @{text "elim_resolution"}, @{text "dest_resolution"} -*} - - -end