10218
|
1 |
(*<*)theory CTLind = CTL:(*>*)
|
|
2 |
|
|
3 |
subsection{*CTL revisited*}
|
|
4 |
|
|
5 |
text{*\label{sec:CTL-revisited}
|
10281
|
6 |
The purpose of this section is twofold: we want to demonstrate
|
|
7 |
some of the induction principles and heuristics discussed above and we want to
|
|
8 |
show how inductive definitions can simplify proofs.
|
10218
|
9 |
In \S\ref{sec:CTL} we gave a fairly involved proof of the correctness of a
|
|
10 |
model checker for CTL. In particular the proof of the
|
|
11 |
@{thm[source]infinity_lemma} on the way to @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} is not as
|
|
12 |
simple as one might intuitively expect, due to the @{text SOME} operator
|
10281
|
13 |
involved. Below we give a simpler proof of @{thm[source]AF_lemma2}
|
|
14 |
based on an auxiliary inductive definition.
|
10218
|
15 |
|
|
16 |
Let us call a (finite or infinite) path \emph{@{term A}-avoiding} if it does
|
|
17 |
not touch any node in the set @{term A}. Then @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} says
|
|
18 |
that if no infinite path from some state @{term s} is @{term A}-avoiding,
|
|
19 |
then @{prop"s \<in> lfp(af A)"}. We prove this by inductively defining the set
|
|
20 |
@{term"Avoid s A"} of states reachable from @{term s} by a finite @{term
|
|
21 |
A}-avoiding path:
|
10241
|
22 |
% Second proof of opposite direction, directly by well-founded induction
|
10218
|
23 |
% on the initial segment of M that avoids A.
|
|
24 |
*}
|
|
25 |
|
|
26 |
consts Avoid :: "state \<Rightarrow> state set \<Rightarrow> state set";
|
|
27 |
inductive "Avoid s A"
|
|
28 |
intros "s \<in> Avoid s A"
|
|
29 |
"\<lbrakk> t \<in> Avoid s A; t \<notin> A; (t,u) \<in> M \<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> u \<in> Avoid s A";
|
|
30 |
|
|
31 |
text{*
|
|
32 |
It is easy to see that for any infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f}
|
|
33 |
with @{prop"f 0 \<in> Avoid s A"} there is an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path
|
|
34 |
starting with @{term s} because (by definition of @{term Avoid}) there is a
|
|
35 |
finite @{term A}-avoiding path from @{term s} to @{term"f 0"}.
|
|
36 |
The proof is by induction on @{prop"f 0 \<in> Avoid s A"}. However,
|
|
37 |
this requires the following
|
|
38 |
reformulation, as explained in \S\ref{sec:ind-var-in-prems} above;
|
|
39 |
the @{text rule_format} directive undoes the reformulation after the proof.
|
|
40 |
*}
|
|
41 |
|
|
42 |
lemma ex_infinite_path[rule_format]:
|
|
43 |
"t \<in> Avoid s A \<Longrightarrow>
|
|
44 |
\<forall>f\<in>Paths t. (\<forall>i. f i \<notin> A) \<longrightarrow> (\<exists>p\<in>Paths s. \<forall>i. p i \<notin> A)";
|
|
45 |
apply(erule Avoid.induct);
|
|
46 |
apply(blast);
|
|
47 |
apply(clarify);
|
|
48 |
apply(drule_tac x = "\<lambda>i. case i of 0 \<Rightarrow> t | Suc i \<Rightarrow> f i" in bspec);
|
|
49 |
apply(simp_all add:Paths_def split:nat.split);
|
|
50 |
done
|
|
51 |
|
|
52 |
text{*\noindent
|
|
53 |
The base case (@{prop"t = s"}) is trivial (@{text blast}).
|
|
54 |
In the induction step, we have an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f}
|
|
55 |
starting from @{term u}, a successor of @{term t}. Now we simply instantiate
|
|
56 |
the @{text"\<forall>f\<in>Paths t"} in the induction hypothesis by the path starting with
|
|
57 |
@{term t} and continuing with @{term f}. That is what the above $\lambda$-term
|
|
58 |
expresses. That fact that this is a path starting with @{term t} and that
|
|
59 |
the instantiated induction hypothesis implies the conclusion is shown by
|
|
60 |
simplification.
|
|
61 |
|
|
62 |
Now we come to the key lemma. It says that if @{term t} can be reached by a
|
|
63 |
finite @{term A}-avoiding path from @{term s}, then @{prop"t \<in> lfp(af A)"},
|
|
64 |
provided there is no infinite @{term A}-avoiding path starting from @{term
|
|
65 |
s}.
|
|
66 |
*}
|
|
67 |
|
|
68 |
lemma Avoid_in_lfp[rule_format(no_asm)]:
|
|
69 |
"\<forall>p\<in>Paths s. \<exists>i. p i \<in> A \<Longrightarrow> t \<in> Avoid s A \<longrightarrow> t \<in> lfp(af A)";
|
|
70 |
txt{*\noindent
|
|
71 |
The trick is not to induct on @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"}, as already the base
|
10241
|
72 |
case would be a problem, but to proceed by well-founded induction @{term
|
10218
|
73 |
t}. Hence @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"} needs to be brought into the conclusion as
|
|
74 |
well, which the directive @{text rule_format} undoes at the end (see below).
|
10241
|
75 |
But induction with respect to which well-founded relation? The restriction
|
10218
|
76 |
of @{term M} to @{term"Avoid s A"}:
|
|
77 |
@{term[display]"{(y,x). (x,y) \<in> M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> y \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}"}
|
|
78 |
As we shall see in a moment, the absence of infinite @{term A}-avoiding paths
|
10241
|
79 |
starting from @{term s} implies well-foundedness of this relation. For the
|
10218
|
80 |
moment we assume this and proceed with the induction:
|
|
81 |
*}
|
|
82 |
|
|
83 |
apply(subgoal_tac
|
|
84 |
"wf{(y,x). (x,y)\<in>M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> y \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}");
|
|
85 |
apply(erule_tac a = t in wf_induct);
|
|
86 |
apply(clarsimp);
|
|
87 |
|
|
88 |
txt{*\noindent
|
|
89 |
Now can assume additionally (induction hypothesis) that if @{prop"t \<notin> A"}
|
|
90 |
then all successors of @{term t} that are in @{term"Avoid s A"} are in
|
|
91 |
@{term"lfp (af A)"}. To prove the actual goal we unfold @{term lfp} once. Now
|
|
92 |
we have to prove that @{term t} is in @{term A} or all successors of @{term
|
|
93 |
t} are in @{term"lfp (af A)"}. If @{term t} is not in @{term A}, the second
|
|
94 |
@{term Avoid}-rule implies that all successors of @{term t} are in
|
|
95 |
@{term"Avoid s A"} (because we also assume @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"}), and
|
|
96 |
hence, by the induction hypothesis, all successors of @{term t} are indeed in
|
|
97 |
@{term"lfp(af A)"}. Mechanically:
|
|
98 |
*}
|
|
99 |
|
|
100 |
apply(rule ssubst [OF lfp_unfold[OF mono_af]]);
|
|
101 |
apply(simp only: af_def);
|
|
102 |
apply(blast intro:Avoid.intros);
|
|
103 |
|
|
104 |
txt{*
|
|
105 |
Having proved the main goal we return to the proof obligation that the above
|
10241
|
106 |
relation is indeed well-founded. This is proved by contraposition: we assume
|
|
107 |
the relation is not well-founded. Thus there exists an infinite @{term
|
10218
|
108 |
A}-avoiding path all in @{term"Avoid s A"}, by theorem
|
|
109 |
@{thm[source]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain}:
|
|
110 |
@{thm[display]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain[no_vars]}
|
|
111 |
From lemma @{thm[source]ex_infinite_path} the existence of an infinite
|
|
112 |
@{term A}-avoiding path starting in @{term s} follows, just as required for
|
|
113 |
the contraposition.
|
|
114 |
*}
|
|
115 |
|
10235
|
116 |
apply(erule contrapos_pp);
|
10218
|
117 |
apply(simp add:wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain);
|
|
118 |
apply(erule exE);
|
|
119 |
apply(rule ex_infinite_path);
|
|
120 |
apply(auto simp add:Paths_def);
|
|
121 |
done
|
|
122 |
|
|
123 |
text{*
|
|
124 |
The @{text"(no_asm)"} modifier of the @{text"rule_format"} directive means
|
|
125 |
that the assumption is left unchanged---otherwise the @{text"\<forall>p"} is turned
|
|
126 |
into a @{text"\<And>p"}, which would complicate matters below. As it is,
|
|
127 |
@{thm[source]Avoid_in_lfp} is now
|
|
128 |
@{thm[display]Avoid_in_lfp[no_vars]}
|
|
129 |
The main theorem is simply the corollary where @{prop"t = s"},
|
|
130 |
in which case the assumption @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"} is trivially true
|
|
131 |
by the first @{term Avoid}-rule). Isabelle confirms this:
|
|
132 |
*}
|
|
133 |
|
|
134 |
theorem AF_lemma2:
|
|
135 |
"{s. \<forall>p \<in> Paths s. \<exists> i. p i \<in> A} \<subseteq> lfp(af A)";
|
|
136 |
by(auto elim:Avoid_in_lfp intro:Avoid.intros);
|
|
137 |
|
|
138 |
|
|
139 |
(*<*)end(*>*)
|