author | paulson |
Fri, 28 Jul 1995 17:41:31 +0200 | |
changeset 1210 | 230b9b4b783e |
parent 1197 | ae58cd15e802 |
child 1421 | 1471e85624a7 |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
1197 | 1 |
\documentstyle[a4,proof209,iman,extra,12pt]{llncs} |
103 | 2 |
\newif\ifCADE |
497
990d2573efa6
revised for new theory system: removal of ext, addition of thy_name
lcp
parents:
455
diff
changeset
|
3 |
\CADEfalse |
103 | 4 |
|
355 | 5 |
\title{A Fixedpoint Approach to Implementing\\ |
6 |
(Co)Inductive Definitions\thanks{J. Grundy and S. Thompson made detailed |
|
7 |
comments; the referees were also helpful. Research funded by |
|
8 |
SERC grants GR/G53279, GR/H40570 and by the ESPRIT Project 6453 |
|
9 |
`Types'.}} |
|
103 | 10 |
|
355 | 11 |
\author{Lawrence C. Paulson\\{\tt lcp@cl.cam.ac.uk}} |
12 |
\institute{Computer Laboratory, University of Cambridge, England} |
|
103 | 13 |
\date{\today} |
14 |
\setcounter{secnumdepth}{2} \setcounter{tocdepth}{2} |
|
15 |
||
16 |
\newcommand\sbs{\subseteq} |
|
17 |
\let\To=\Rightarrow |
|
18 |
||
19 |
||
355 | 20 |
\newcommand\pow{{\cal P}} |
21 |
%%%\let\pow=\wp |
|
22 |
\newcommand\RepFun{\hbox{\tt RepFun}} |
|
23 |
\newcommand\cons{\hbox{\tt cons}} |
|
24 |
\def\succ{\hbox{\tt succ}} |
|
25 |
\newcommand\split{\hbox{\tt split}} |
|
26 |
\newcommand\fst{\hbox{\tt fst}} |
|
27 |
\newcommand\snd{\hbox{\tt snd}} |
|
28 |
\newcommand\converse{\hbox{\tt converse}} |
|
29 |
\newcommand\domain{\hbox{\tt domain}} |
|
30 |
\newcommand\range{\hbox{\tt range}} |
|
31 |
\newcommand\field{\hbox{\tt field}} |
|
32 |
\newcommand\lfp{\hbox{\tt lfp}} |
|
33 |
\newcommand\gfp{\hbox{\tt gfp}} |
|
34 |
\newcommand\id{\hbox{\tt id}} |
|
35 |
\newcommand\trans{\hbox{\tt trans}} |
|
36 |
\newcommand\wf{\hbox{\tt wf}} |
|
37 |
\newcommand\nat{\hbox{\tt nat}} |
|
38 |
\newcommand\rank{\hbox{\tt rank}} |
|
39 |
\newcommand\univ{\hbox{\tt univ}} |
|
40 |
\newcommand\Vrec{\hbox{\tt Vrec}} |
|
41 |
\newcommand\Inl{\hbox{\tt Inl}} |
|
42 |
\newcommand\Inr{\hbox{\tt Inr}} |
|
43 |
\newcommand\case{\hbox{\tt case}} |
|
44 |
\newcommand\lst{\hbox{\tt list}} |
|
45 |
\newcommand\Nil{\hbox{\tt Nil}} |
|
46 |
\newcommand\Cons{\hbox{\tt Cons}} |
|
103 | 47 |
\newcommand\lstcase{\hbox{\tt list\_case}} |
48 |
\newcommand\lstrec{\hbox{\tt list\_rec}} |
|
355 | 49 |
\newcommand\length{\hbox{\tt length}} |
50 |
\newcommand\listn{\hbox{\tt listn}} |
|
51 |
\newcommand\acc{\hbox{\tt acc}} |
|
52 |
\newcommand\primrec{\hbox{\tt primrec}} |
|
53 |
\newcommand\SC{\hbox{\tt SC}} |
|
54 |
\newcommand\CONST{\hbox{\tt CONST}} |
|
55 |
\newcommand\PROJ{\hbox{\tt PROJ}} |
|
56 |
\newcommand\COMP{\hbox{\tt COMP}} |
|
57 |
\newcommand\PREC{\hbox{\tt PREC}} |
|
103 | 58 |
|
355 | 59 |
\newcommand\quniv{\hbox{\tt quniv}} |
60 |
\newcommand\llist{\hbox{\tt llist}} |
|
61 |
\newcommand\LNil{\hbox{\tt LNil}} |
|
62 |
\newcommand\LCons{\hbox{\tt LCons}} |
|
63 |
\newcommand\lconst{\hbox{\tt lconst}} |
|
64 |
\newcommand\lleq{\hbox{\tt lleq}} |
|
65 |
\newcommand\map{\hbox{\tt map}} |
|
66 |
\newcommand\term{\hbox{\tt term}} |
|
67 |
\newcommand\Apply{\hbox{\tt Apply}} |
|
68 |
\newcommand\termcase{\hbox{\tt term\_case}} |
|
69 |
\newcommand\rev{\hbox{\tt rev}} |
|
70 |
\newcommand\reflect{\hbox{\tt reflect}} |
|
71 |
\newcommand\tree{\hbox{\tt tree}} |
|
72 |
\newcommand\forest{\hbox{\tt forest}} |
|
73 |
\newcommand\Part{\hbox{\tt Part}} |
|
74 |
\newcommand\TF{\hbox{\tt tree\_forest}} |
|
75 |
\newcommand\Tcons{\hbox{\tt Tcons}} |
|
76 |
\newcommand\Fcons{\hbox{\tt Fcons}} |
|
77 |
\newcommand\Fnil{\hbox{\tt Fnil}} |
|
103 | 78 |
\newcommand\TFcase{\hbox{\tt TF\_case}} |
355 | 79 |
\newcommand\Fin{\hbox{\tt Fin}} |
80 |
\newcommand\QInl{\hbox{\tt QInl}} |
|
81 |
\newcommand\QInr{\hbox{\tt QInr}} |
|
82 |
\newcommand\qsplit{\hbox{\tt qsplit}} |
|
83 |
\newcommand\qcase{\hbox{\tt qcase}} |
|
84 |
\newcommand\Con{\hbox{\tt Con}} |
|
85 |
\newcommand\data{\hbox{\tt data}} |
|
103 | 86 |
|
87 |
\binperiod %%%treat . like a binary operator |
|
88 |
||
89 |
\begin{document} |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
90 |
\pagestyle{empty} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
91 |
\begin{titlepage} |
103 | 92 |
\maketitle |
93 |
\begin{abstract} |
|
355 | 94 |
This paper presents a fixedpoint approach to inductive definitions. |
95 |
Instead of using a syntactic test such as `strictly positive,' the |
|
96 |
approach lets definitions involve any operators that have been proved |
|
97 |
monotone. It is conceptually simple, which has allowed the easy |
|
98 |
implementation of mutual recursion and other conveniences. It also |
|
99 |
handles coinductive definitions: simply replace the least fixedpoint by a |
|
100 |
greatest fixedpoint. This represents the first automated support for |
|
101 |
coinductive definitions. |
|
130 | 102 |
|
597 | 103 |
The method has been implemented in two of Isabelle's logics, ZF set theory |
104 |
and higher-order logic. It should be applicable to any logic in which |
|
105 |
the Knaster-Tarski Theorem can be proved. Examples include lists of $n$ |
|
106 |
elements, the accessible part of a relation and the set of primitive |
|
107 |
recursive functions. One example of a coinductive definition is |
|
108 |
bisimulations for lazy lists. \ifCADE\else Recursive datatypes are |
|
109 |
examined in detail, as well as one example of a {\bf codatatype}: lazy |
|
110 |
lists. The appendices are simple user's manuals for this Isabelle |
|
111 |
package.\fi |
|
103 | 112 |
\end{abstract} |
113 |
% |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
114 |
\bigskip\centerline{Copyright \copyright{} \number\year{} by Lawrence C. Paulson} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
115 |
\thispagestyle{empty} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
116 |
\end{titlepage} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
117 |
\tableofcontents\cleardoublepage\pagestyle{plain} |
103 | 118 |
|
119 |
\section{Introduction} |
|
120 |
Several theorem provers provide commands for formalizing recursive data |
|
121 |
structures, like lists and trees. Examples include Boyer and Moore's shell |
|
597 | 122 |
principle~\cite{bm79} and Melham's recursive type package for the Cambridge HOL |
103 | 123 |
system~\cite{melham89}. Such data structures are called {\bf datatypes} |
124 |
below, by analogy with {\tt datatype} definitions in Standard~ML\@. |
|
125 |
||
130 | 126 |
A datatype is but one example of an {\bf inductive definition}. This |
103 | 127 |
specifies the least set closed under given rules~\cite{aczel77}. The |
128 |
collection of theorems in a logic is inductively defined. A structural |
|
129 |
operational semantics~\cite{hennessy90} is an inductive definition of a |
|
130 |
reduction or evaluation relation on programs. A few theorem provers |
|
131 |
provide commands for formalizing inductive definitions; these include |
|
132 |
Coq~\cite{paulin92} and again the HOL system~\cite{camilleri92}. |
|
133 |
||
130 | 134 |
The dual notion is that of a {\bf coinductive definition}. This specifies |
103 | 135 |
the greatest set closed under given rules. Important examples include |
136 |
using bisimulation relations to formalize equivalence of |
|
137 |
processes~\cite{milner89} or lazy functional programs~\cite{abramsky90}. |
|
138 |
Other examples include lazy lists and other infinite data structures; these |
|
130 | 139 |
are called {\bf codatatypes} below. |
103 | 140 |
|
355 | 141 |
Not all inductive definitions are meaningful. {\bf Monotone} inductive |
142 |
definitions are a large, well-behaved class. Monotonicity can be enforced |
|
143 |
by syntactic conditions such as `strictly positive,' but this could lead to |
|
144 |
monotone definitions being rejected on the grounds of their syntactic form. |
|
145 |
More flexible is to formalize monotonicity within the logic and allow users |
|
146 |
to prove it. |
|
103 | 147 |
|
148 |
This paper describes a package based on a fixedpoint approach. Least |
|
149 |
fixedpoints yield inductive definitions; greatest fixedpoints yield |
|
355 | 150 |
coinductive definitions. The package has several advantages: |
103 | 151 |
\begin{itemize} |
355 | 152 |
\item It allows reference to any operators that have been proved monotone. |
153 |
Thus it accepts all provably monotone inductive definitions, including |
|
154 |
iterated definitions. |
|
597 | 155 |
\item It accepts a wide class of datatype definitions, including those with |
156 |
infinite branching. |
|
130 | 157 |
\item It handles coinductive and codatatype definitions. Most of |
158 |
the discussion below applies equally to inductive and coinductive |
|
103 | 159 |
definitions, and most of the code is shared. To my knowledge, this is |
130 | 160 |
the only package supporting coinductive definitions. |
103 | 161 |
\item Definitions may be mutually recursive. |
162 |
\end{itemize} |
|
597 | 163 |
The package has been implemented in Isabelle~\cite{isabelle-intro} using ZF |
164 |
set theory \cite{paulson-set-I,paulson-set-II}; part of it has since been |
|
165 |
ported to Isabelle's higher-order logic. However, the fixedpoint approach is |
|
166 |
independent of Isabelle. The recursion equations are specified as |
|
167 |
introduction rules for the mutually recursive sets. The package transforms |
|
168 |
these rules into a mapping over sets, and attempts to prove that the |
|
169 |
mapping is monotonic and well-typed. If successful, the package makes |
|
170 |
fixedpoint definitions and proves the introduction, elimination and |
|
130 | 171 |
(co)induction rules. The package consists of several Standard ML |
103 | 172 |
functors~\cite{paulson91}; it accepts its argument and returns its result |
355 | 173 |
as ML structures.\footnote{This use of ML modules is not essential; the |
174 |
package could also be implemented as a function on records.} |
|
103 | 175 |
|
176 |
Most datatype packages equip the new datatype with some means of expressing |
|
355 | 177 |
recursive functions. This is the main omission from my package. Its |
178 |
fixedpoint operators define only recursive sets. To define recursive |
|
179 |
functions, the Isabelle/ZF theory provides well-founded recursion and other |
|
180 |
logical tools~\cite{paulson-set-II}. |
|
103 | 181 |
|
355 | 182 |
{\bf Outline.} Section~2 introduces the least and greatest fixedpoint |
183 |
operators. Section~3 discusses the form of introduction rules, mutual |
|
184 |
recursion and other points common to inductive and coinductive definitions. |
|
185 |
Section~4 discusses induction and coinduction rules separately. Section~5 |
|
186 |
presents several examples, including a coinductive definition. Section~6 |
|
187 |
describes datatype definitions. Section~7 presents related work. |
|
188 |
Section~8 draws brief conclusions. \ifCADE\else The appendices are simple |
|
597 | 189 |
user's manuals for this Isabelle package.\fi |
103 | 190 |
|
191 |
Most of the definitions and theorems shown below have been generated by the |
|
192 |
package. I have renamed some variables to improve readability. |
|
193 |
||
194 |
\section{Fixedpoint operators} |
|
195 |
In set theory, the least and greatest fixedpoint operators are defined as |
|
196 |
follows: |
|
197 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
198 |
\lfp(D,h) & \equiv & \inter\{X\sbs D. h(X)\sbs X\} \\ |
|
199 |
\gfp(D,h) & \equiv & \union\{X\sbs D. X\sbs h(X)\} |
|
200 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
130 | 201 |
Let $D$ be a set. Say that $h$ is {\bf bounded by}~$D$ if $h(D)\sbs D$, and |
202 |
{\bf monotone below~$D$} if |
|
103 | 203 |
$h(A)\sbs h(B)$ for all $A$ and $B$ such that $A\sbs B\sbs D$. If $h$ is |
204 |
bounded by~$D$ and monotone then both operators yield fixedpoints: |
|
205 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
206 |
\lfp(D,h) & = & h(\lfp(D,h)) \\ |
|
207 |
\gfp(D,h) & = & h(\gfp(D,h)) |
|
208 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
355 | 209 |
These equations are instances of the Knaster-Tarski Theorem, which states |
103 | 210 |
that every monotonic function over a complete lattice has a |
211 |
fixedpoint~\cite{davey&priestley}. It is obvious from their definitions |
|
212 |
that $\lfp$ must be the least fixedpoint, and $\gfp$ the greatest. |
|
213 |
||
355 | 214 |
This fixedpoint theory is simple. The Knaster-Tarski Theorem is easy to |
103 | 215 |
prove. Showing monotonicity of~$h$ is trivial, in typical cases. We must |
355 | 216 |
also exhibit a bounding set~$D$ for~$h$. Frequently this is trivial, as |
179 | 217 |
when a set of `theorems' is (co)inductively defined over some previously |
355 | 218 |
existing set of `formulae.' Isabelle/ZF provides a suitable bounding set |
219 |
for finitely branching (co)datatype definitions; see~\S\ref{univ-sec} |
|
220 |
below. Bounding sets are also called {\bf domains}. |
|
103 | 221 |
|
355 | 222 |
The powerset operator is monotone, but by Cantor's Theorem there is no |
223 |
set~$A$ such that $A=\pow(A)$. We cannot put $A=\lfp(D,\pow)$ because |
|
224 |
there is no suitable domain~$D$. But \S\ref{acc-sec} demonstrates |
|
225 |
that~$\pow$ is still useful in inductive definitions. |
|
103 | 226 |
|
130 | 227 |
\section{Elements of an inductive or coinductive definition}\label{basic-sec} |
228 |
Consider a (co)inductive definition of the sets $R_1$, \ldots,~$R_n$, in |
|
355 | 229 |
mutual recursion. They will be constructed from domains $D_1$, |
230 |
\ldots,~$D_n$, respectively. The construction yields not $R_i\sbs D_i$ but |
|
231 |
$R_i\sbs D_1+\cdots+D_n$, where $R_i$ is contained in the image of~$D_i$ |
|
232 |
under an injection. Reasons for this are discussed |
|
130 | 233 |
elsewhere~\cite[\S4.5]{paulson-set-II}. |
103 | 234 |
|
235 |
The definition may involve arbitrary parameters $\vec{p}=p_1$, |
|
236 |
\ldots,~$p_k$. Each recursive set then has the form $R_i(\vec{p})$. The |
|
237 |
parameters must be identical every time they occur within a definition. This |
|
238 |
would appear to be a serious restriction compared with other systems such as |
|
239 |
Coq~\cite{paulin92}. For instance, we cannot define the lists of |
|
240 |
$n$ elements as the set $\listn(A,n)$ using rules where the parameter~$n$ |
|
355 | 241 |
varies. Section~\ref{listn-sec} describes how to express this set using the |
130 | 242 |
inductive definition package. |
103 | 243 |
|
244 |
To avoid clutter below, the recursive sets are shown as simply $R_i$ |
|
245 |
instead of $R_i(\vec{p})$. |
|
246 |
||
247 |
\subsection{The form of the introduction rules}\label{intro-sec} |
|
248 |
The body of the definition consists of the desired introduction rules, |
|
249 |
specified as strings. The conclusion of each rule must have the form $t\in |
|
250 |
R_i$, where $t$ is any term. Premises typically have the same form, but |
|
251 |
they can have the more general form $t\in M(R_i)$ or express arbitrary |
|
252 |
side-conditions. |
|
253 |
||
254 |
The premise $t\in M(R_i)$ is permitted if $M$ is a monotonic operator on |
|
255 |
sets, satisfying the rule |
|
256 |
\[ \infer{M(A)\sbs M(B)}{A\sbs B} \] |
|
130 | 257 |
The user must supply the package with monotonicity rules for all such premises. |
103 | 258 |
|
355 | 259 |
The ability to introduce new monotone operators makes the approach |
260 |
flexible. A suitable choice of~$M$ and~$t$ can express a lot. The |
|
261 |
powerset operator $\pow$ is monotone, and the premise $t\in\pow(R)$ |
|
262 |
expresses $t\sbs R$; see \S\ref{acc-sec} for an example. The `list of' |
|
263 |
operator is monotone, as is easily proved by induction. The premise |
|
264 |
$t\in\lst(R)$ avoids having to encode the effect of~$\lst(R)$ using mutual |
|
265 |
recursion; see \S\ref{primrec-sec} and also my earlier |
|
266 |
paper~\cite[\S4.4]{paulson-set-II}. |
|
103 | 267 |
|
268 |
Introduction rules may also contain {\bf side-conditions}. These are |
|
269 |
premises consisting of arbitrary formulae not mentioning the recursive |
|
270 |
sets. Side-conditions typically involve type-checking. One example is the |
|
271 |
premise $a\in A$ in the following rule from the definition of lists: |
|
272 |
\[ \infer{\Cons(a,l)\in\lst(A)}{a\in A & l\in\lst(A)} \] |
|
273 |
||
274 |
\subsection{The fixedpoint definitions} |
|
275 |
The package translates the list of desired introduction rules into a fixedpoint |
|
455 | 276 |
definition. Consider, as a running example, the finite powerset operator |
103 | 277 |
$\Fin(A)$: the set of all finite subsets of~$A$. It can be |
278 |
defined as the least set closed under the rules |
|
279 |
\[ \emptyset\in\Fin(A) \qquad |
|
280 |
\infer{\{a\}\un b\in\Fin(A)}{a\in A & b\in\Fin(A)} |
|
281 |
\] |
|
282 |
||
130 | 283 |
The domain in a (co)inductive definition must be some existing set closed |
103 | 284 |
under the rules. A suitable domain for $\Fin(A)$ is $\pow(A)$, the set of all |
285 |
subsets of~$A$. The package generates the definition |
|
286 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
287 |
\Fin(A) & \equiv & \lfp(\pow(A), \; |
|
288 |
\begin{array}[t]{r@{\,}l} |
|
289 |
\lambda X. \{z\in\pow(A). & z=\emptyset \disj{} \\ |
|
290 |
&(\exists a\,b. z=\{a\}\un b\conj a\in A\conj b\in X)\}) |
|
291 |
\end{array} |
|
130 | 292 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
103 | 293 |
The contribution of each rule to the definition of $\Fin(A)$ should be |
130 | 294 |
obvious. A coinductive definition is similar but uses $\gfp$ instead |
103 | 295 |
of~$\lfp$. |
296 |
||
297 |
The package must prove that the fixedpoint operator is applied to a |
|
298 |
monotonic function. If the introduction rules have the form described |
|
299 |
above, and if the package is supplied a monotonicity theorem for every |
|
300 |
$t\in M(R_i)$ premise, then this proof is trivial.\footnote{Due to the |
|
301 |
presence of logical connectives in the fixedpoint's body, the |
|
302 |
monotonicity proof requires some unusual rules. These state that the |
|
130 | 303 |
connectives $\conj$, $\disj$ and $\exists$ preserve monotonicity with respect |
304 |
to the partial ordering on unary predicates given by $P\sqsubseteq Q$ if and |
|
103 | 305 |
only if $\forall x.P(x)\imp Q(x)$.} |
306 |
||
355 | 307 |
The package returns its result as an ML structure, which consists of named |
308 |
components; we may regard it as a record. The result structure contains |
|
309 |
the definitions of the recursive sets as a theorem list called {\tt defs}. |
|
310 |
It also contains, as the theorem {\tt unfold}, a fixedpoint equation such |
|
311 |
as |
|
103 | 312 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
313 |
\Fin(A) & = & |
|
314 |
\begin{array}[t]{r@{\,}l} |
|
315 |
\{z\in\pow(A). & z=\emptyset \disj{} \\ |
|
316 |
&(\exists a\,b. z=\{a\}\un b\conj a\in A\conj b\in \Fin(A))\} |
|
317 |
\end{array} |
|
318 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
130 | 319 |
It also contains, as the theorem {\tt dom\_subset}, an inclusion such as |
103 | 320 |
$\Fin(A)\sbs\pow(A)$. |
321 |
||
322 |
||
323 |
\subsection{Mutual recursion} \label{mutual-sec} |
|
130 | 324 |
In a mutually recursive definition, the domain of the fixedpoint construction |
103 | 325 |
is the disjoint sum of the domain~$D_i$ of each~$R_i$, for $i=1$, |
326 |
\ldots,~$n$. The package uses the injections of the |
|
327 |
binary disjoint sum, typically $\Inl$ and~$\Inr$, to express injections |
|
130 | 328 |
$h_{1n}$, \ldots, $h_{nn}$ for the $n$-ary disjoint sum $D_1+\cdots+D_n$. |
103 | 329 |
|
330 |
As discussed elsewhere \cite[\S4.5]{paulson-set-II}, Isabelle/ZF defines the |
|
331 |
operator $\Part$ to support mutual recursion. The set $\Part(A,h)$ |
|
332 |
contains those elements of~$A$ having the form~$h(z)$: |
|
333 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
334 |
\Part(A,h) & \equiv & \{x\in A. \exists z. x=h(z)\}. |
|
335 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
336 |
For mutually recursive sets $R_1$, \ldots,~$R_n$ with |
|
337 |
$n>1$, the package makes $n+1$ definitions. The first defines a set $R$ using |
|
338 |
a fixedpoint operator. The remaining $n$ definitions have the form |
|
339 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
130 | 340 |
R_i & \equiv & \Part(R,h_{in}), \qquad i=1,\ldots, n. |
103 | 341 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
342 |
It follows that $R=R_1\un\cdots\un R_n$, where the $R_i$ are pairwise disjoint. |
|
343 |
||
344 |
||
345 |
\subsection{Proving the introduction rules} |
|
130 | 346 |
The user supplies the package with the desired form of the introduction |
103 | 347 |
rules. Once it has derived the theorem {\tt unfold}, it attempts |
130 | 348 |
to prove those rules. From the user's point of view, this is the |
103 | 349 |
trickiest stage; the proofs often fail. The task is to show that the domain |
350 |
$D_1+\cdots+D_n$ of the combined set $R_1\un\cdots\un R_n$ is |
|
351 |
closed under all the introduction rules. This essentially involves replacing |
|
352 |
each~$R_i$ by $D_1+\cdots+D_n$ in each of the introduction rules and |
|
353 |
attempting to prove the result. |
|
354 |
||
355 |
Consider the $\Fin(A)$ example. After substituting $\pow(A)$ for $\Fin(A)$ |
|
356 |
in the rules, the package must prove |
|
357 |
\[ \emptyset\in\pow(A) \qquad |
|
358 |
\infer{\{a\}\un b\in\pow(A)}{a\in A & b\in\pow(A)} |
|
359 |
\] |
|
597 | 360 |
Such proofs can be regarded as type-checking the definition.\footnote{The |
361 |
Isabelle/HOL version does not require these proofs, as HOL has implicit |
|
362 |
type-checking.} The user supplies the package with type-checking rules to |
|
363 |
apply. Usually these are general purpose rules from the ZF theory. They |
|
364 |
could however be rules specifically proved for a particular inductive |
|
365 |
definition; sometimes this is the easiest way to get the definition |
|
366 |
through! |
|
103 | 367 |
|
130 | 368 |
The result structure contains the introduction rules as the theorem list {\tt |
369 |
intrs}. |
|
103 | 370 |
|
355 | 371 |
\subsection{The case analysis rule} |
372 |
The elimination rule, called {\tt elim}, performs case analysis. There is one |
|
130 | 373 |
case for each introduction rule. The elimination rule |
374 |
for $\Fin(A)$ is |
|
103 | 375 |
\[ \infer{Q}{x\in\Fin(A) & \infer*{Q}{[x=\emptyset]} |
376 |
& \infer*{Q}{[x=\{a\}\un b & a\in A &b\in\Fin(A)]_{a,b}} } |
|
377 |
\] |
|
355 | 378 |
The subscripted variables $a$ and~$b$ above the third premise are |
379 |
eigenvariables, subject to the usual `not free in \ldots' proviso. |
|
380 |
The rule states that if $x\in\Fin(A)$ then either $x=\emptyset$ or else |
|
130 | 381 |
$x=\{a\}\un b$ for some $a\in A$ and $b\in\Fin(A)$; it is a simple consequence |
382 |
of {\tt unfold}. |
|
383 |
||
355 | 384 |
The package also returns a function for generating simplified instances of |
385 |
the case analysis rule. It works for datatypes and for inductive |
|
386 |
definitions involving datatypes, such as an inductively defined relation |
|
387 |
between lists. It instantiates {\tt elim} with a user-supplied term then |
|
388 |
simplifies the cases using freeness of the underlying datatype. The |
|
389 |
simplified rules perform `rule inversion' on the inductive definition. |
|
390 |
Section~\S\ref{mkcases} presents an example. |
|
391 |
||
103 | 392 |
|
130 | 393 |
\section{Induction and coinduction rules} |
394 |
Here we must consider inductive and coinductive definitions separately. |
|
103 | 395 |
For an inductive definition, the package returns an induction rule derived |
396 |
directly from the properties of least fixedpoints, as well as a modified |
|
397 |
rule for mutual recursion and inductively defined relations. For a |
|
130 | 398 |
coinductive definition, the package returns a basic coinduction rule. |
103 | 399 |
|
400 |
\subsection{The basic induction rule}\label{basic-ind-sec} |
|
130 | 401 |
The basic rule, called {\tt induct}, is appropriate in most situations. |
103 | 402 |
For inductive definitions, it is strong rule induction~\cite{camilleri92}; for |
403 |
datatype definitions (see below), it is just structural induction. |
|
404 |
||
405 |
The induction rule for an inductively defined set~$R$ has the following form. |
|
406 |
The major premise is $x\in R$. There is a minor premise for each |
|
407 |
introduction rule: |
|
408 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
409 |
\item If the introduction rule concludes $t\in R_i$, then the minor premise |
|
410 |
is~$P(t)$. |
|
411 |
||
412 |
\item The minor premise's eigenvariables are precisely the introduction |
|
130 | 413 |
rule's free variables that are not parameters of~$R$. For instance, the |
414 |
eigenvariables in the $\Fin(A)$ rule below are $a$ and $b$, but not~$A$. |
|
103 | 415 |
|
416 |
\item If the introduction rule has a premise $t\in R_i$, then the minor |
|
417 |
premise discharges the assumption $t\in R_i$ and the induction |
|
418 |
hypothesis~$P(t)$. If the introduction rule has a premise $t\in M(R_i)$ |
|
419 |
then the minor premise discharges the single assumption |
|
420 |
\[ t\in M(\{z\in R_i. P(z)\}). \] |
|
421 |
Because $M$ is monotonic, this assumption implies $t\in M(R_i)$. The |
|
422 |
occurrence of $P$ gives the effect of an induction hypothesis, which may be |
|
423 |
exploited by appealing to properties of~$M$. |
|
424 |
\end{itemize} |
|
130 | 425 |
The induction rule for $\Fin(A)$ resembles the elimination rule shown above, |
426 |
but includes an induction hypothesis: |
|
103 | 427 |
\[ \infer{P(x)}{x\in\Fin(A) & P(\emptyset) |
428 |
& \infer*{P(\{a\}\un b)}{[a\in A & b\in\Fin(A) & P(b)]_{a,b}} } |
|
429 |
\] |
|
355 | 430 |
Stronger induction rules often suggest themselves. We can derive a rule |
431 |
for $\Fin(A)$ whose third premise discharges the extra assumption $a\not\in |
|
432 |
b$. The Isabelle/ZF theory defines the {\bf rank} of a |
|
433 |
set~\cite[\S3.4]{paulson-set-II}, which supports well-founded induction and |
|
434 |
recursion over datatypes. The package proves a rule for mutual induction |
|
435 |
and inductive relations. |
|
103 | 436 |
|
437 |
\subsection{Mutual induction} |
|
438 |
The mutual induction rule is called {\tt |
|
439 |
mutual\_induct}. It differs from the basic rule in several respects: |
|
440 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
441 |
\item Instead of a single predicate~$P$, it uses $n$ predicates $P_1$, |
|
442 |
\ldots,~$P_n$: one for each recursive set. |
|
443 |
||
444 |
\item There is no major premise such as $x\in R_i$. Instead, the conclusion |
|
445 |
refers to all the recursive sets: |
|
446 |
\[ (\forall z.z\in R_1\imp P_1(z))\conj\cdots\conj |
|
447 |
(\forall z.z\in R_n\imp P_n(z)) |
|
448 |
\] |
|
355 | 449 |
Proving the premises establishes $P_i(z)$ for $z\in R_i$ and $i=1$, |
450 |
\ldots,~$n$. |
|
103 | 451 |
|
452 |
\item If the domain of some $R_i$ is the Cartesian product |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
453 |
$A_1\times\cdots\times A_m$ (associated to the right), then the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
454 |
corresponding predicate $P_i$ takes $m$ arguments and the corresponding |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
455 |
conjunct of the conclusion is |
103 | 456 |
\[ (\forall z_1\ldots z_m.\pair{z_1,\ldots,z_m}\in R_i\imp P_i(z_1,\ldots,z_m)) |
457 |
\] |
|
458 |
\end{itemize} |
|
459 |
The last point above simplifies reasoning about inductively defined |
|
460 |
relations. It eliminates the need to express properties of $z_1$, |
|
461 |
\ldots,~$z_m$ as properties of the tuple $\pair{z_1,\ldots,z_m}$. |
|
462 |
||
130 | 463 |
\subsection{Coinduction}\label{coind-sec} |
464 |
A coinductive definition yields a primitive coinduction rule, with no |
|
103 | 465 |
refinements such as those for the induction rules. (Experience may suggest |
130 | 466 |
refinements later.) Consider the codatatype of lazy lists as an example. For |
103 | 467 |
suitable definitions of $\LNil$ and $\LCons$, lazy lists may be defined as the |
468 |
greatest fixedpoint satisfying the rules |
|
469 |
\[ \LNil\in\llist(A) \qquad |
|
470 |
\infer[(-)]{\LCons(a,l)\in\llist(A)}{a\in A & l\in\llist(A)} |
|
471 |
\] |
|
130 | 472 |
The $(-)$ tag stresses that this is a coinductive definition. A suitable |
103 | 473 |
domain for $\llist(A)$ is $\quniv(A)$, a set closed under variant forms of |
474 |
sum and product for representing infinite data structures |
|
130 | 475 |
(see~\S\ref{univ-sec}). Coinductive definitions use these variant sums and |
103 | 476 |
products. |
477 |
||
478 |
The package derives an {\tt unfold} theorem similar to that for $\Fin(A)$. |
|
355 | 479 |
Then it proves the theorem {\tt coinduct}, which expresses that $\llist(A)$ |
103 | 480 |
is the greatest solution to this equation contained in $\quniv(A)$: |
130 | 481 |
\[ \infer{x\in\llist(A)}{x\in X & X\sbs \quniv(A) & |
103 | 482 |
\infer*{z=\LNil\disj \bigl(\exists a\,l.\, |
355 | 483 |
z=\LCons(a,l) \conj a\in A \conj l\in X\un\llist(A) \bigr)} |
484 |
{[z\in X]_z}} |
|
485 |
% \begin{array}[t]{@{}l} |
|
486 |
% z=\LCons(a,l) \conj a\in A \conj{}\\ |
|
487 |
% l\in X\un\llist(A) \bigr) |
|
488 |
% \end{array} }{[z\in X]_z}} |
|
103 | 489 |
\] |
130 | 490 |
This rule complements the introduction rules; it provides a means of showing |
491 |
$x\in\llist(A)$ when $x$ is infinite. For instance, if $x=\LCons(0,x)$ then |
|
355 | 492 |
applying the rule with $X=\{x\}$ proves $x\in\llist(\nat)$. (Here $\nat$ |
493 |
is the set of natural numbers.) |
|
130 | 494 |
|
103 | 495 |
Having $X\un\llist(A)$ instead of simply $X$ in the third premise above |
496 |
represents a slight strengthening of the greatest fixedpoint property. I |
|
130 | 497 |
discuss several forms of coinduction rules elsewhere~\cite{paulson-coind}. |
103 | 498 |
|
499 |
||
130 | 500 |
\section{Examples of inductive and coinductive definitions}\label{ind-eg-sec} |
455 | 501 |
This section presents several examples: the finite powerset operator, |
103 | 502 |
lists of $n$ elements, bisimulations on lazy lists, the well-founded part |
503 |
of a relation, and the primitive recursive functions. |
|
504 |
||
455 | 505 |
\subsection{The finite powerset operator} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
506 |
This operator has been discussed extensively above. Here is the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
507 |
corresponding invocation in an Isabelle theory file. Note that |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
508 |
$\cons(a,b)$ abbreviates $\{a\}\un b$ in Isabelle/ZF. |
103 | 509 |
\begin{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
510 |
Finite = Arith + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
511 |
consts Fin :: "i=>i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
512 |
inductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
513 |
domains "Fin(A)" <= "Pow(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
514 |
intrs |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
515 |
emptyI "0 : Fin(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
516 |
consI "[| a: A; b: Fin(A) |] ==> cons(a,b) : Fin(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
517 |
type_intrs "[empty_subsetI, cons_subsetI, PowI]" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
518 |
type_elims "[make_elim PowD]" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
519 |
end |
103 | 520 |
\end{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
521 |
Theory {\tt Finite} extends the parent theory {\tt Arith} by declaring the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
522 |
unary function symbol~$\Fin$, which is defined inductively. Its domain is |
355 | 523 |
specified as $\pow(A)$, where $A$ is the parameter appearing in the |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
524 |
introduction rules. For type-checking, we supply two introduction |
355 | 525 |
rules: |
103 | 526 |
\[ \emptyset\sbs A \qquad |
527 |
\infer{\{a\}\un B\sbs C}{a\in C & B\sbs C} |
|
528 |
\] |
|
529 |
A further introduction rule and an elimination rule express the two |
|
530 |
directions of the equivalence $A\in\pow(B)\bimp A\sbs B$. Type-checking |
|
355 | 531 |
involves mostly introduction rules. |
532 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
533 |
Like all Isabelle theory files, this one yields a structure containing the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
534 |
new theory as an \ML{} value. Structure {\tt Finite} also has a |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
535 |
substructure, called~{\tt Fin}. After declaring \hbox{\tt open Finite;} we |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
536 |
can refer to the $\Fin(A)$ introduction rules as the list {\tt Fin.intrs} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
537 |
or individually as {\tt Fin.emptyI} and {\tt Fin.consI}. The induction |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
538 |
rule is {\tt Fin.induct}. |
355 | 539 |
|
103 | 540 |
|
541 |
\subsection{Lists of $n$ elements}\label{listn-sec} |
|
179 | 542 |
This has become a standard example of an inductive definition. Following |
543 |
Paulin-Mohring~\cite{paulin92}, we could attempt to define a new datatype |
|
544 |
$\listn(A,n)$, for lists of length~$n$, as an $n$-indexed family of sets. |
|
545 |
But her introduction rules |
|
355 | 546 |
\[ \hbox{\tt Niln}\in\listn(A,0) \qquad |
547 |
\infer{\hbox{\tt Consn}(n,a,l)\in\listn(A,\succ(n))} |
|
103 | 548 |
{n\in\nat & a\in A & l\in\listn(A,n)} |
549 |
\] |
|
550 |
are not acceptable to the inductive definition package: |
|
551 |
$\listn$ occurs with three different parameter lists in the definition. |
|
552 |
||
597 | 553 |
The Isabelle version of this example suggests a general treatment of |
355 | 554 |
varying parameters. Here, we use the existing datatype definition of |
555 |
$\lst(A)$, with constructors $\Nil$ and~$\Cons$. Then incorporate the |
|
556 |
parameter~$n$ into the inductive set itself, defining $\listn(A)$ as a |
|
557 |
relation. It consists of pairs $\pair{n,l}$ such that $n\in\nat$ |
|
558 |
and~$l\in\lst(A)$ and $l$ has length~$n$. In fact, $\listn(A)$ is the |
|
559 |
converse of the length function on~$\lst(A)$. The Isabelle/ZF introduction |
|
560 |
rules are |
|
103 | 561 |
\[ \pair{0,\Nil}\in\listn(A) \qquad |
562 |
\infer{\pair{\succ(n),\Cons(a,l)}\in\listn(A)} |
|
563 |
{a\in A & \pair{n,l}\in\listn(A)} |
|
564 |
\] |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
565 |
The Isabelle theory file takes, as parent, the theory~{\tt List} of lists. |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
566 |
We declare the constant~$\listn$ and supply an inductive definition, |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
567 |
specifying the domain as $\nat\times\lst(A)$: |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
568 |
\begin{ttbox} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
569 |
ListN = List + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
570 |
consts listn ::"i=>i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
571 |
inductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
572 |
domains "listn(A)" <= "nat*list(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
573 |
intrs |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
574 |
NilI "<0,Nil> : listn(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
575 |
ConsI "[| a: A; <n,l> : listn(A) |] ==> <succ(n), Cons(a,l)> : listn(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
576 |
type_intrs "nat_typechecks @ list.intrs" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
577 |
end |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
578 |
\end{ttbox} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
579 |
The type-checking rules include those for 0, $\succ$, $\Nil$ and $\Cons$. |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
580 |
Because $\listn(A)$ is a set of pairs, type-checking requires the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
581 |
equivalence $\pair{a,b}\in A\times B \bimp a\in A \conj b\in B$; the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
582 |
package always includes the necessary rules. |
103 | 583 |
|
584 |
The package returns introduction, elimination and induction rules for |
|
585 |
$\listn$. The basic induction rule, {\tt ListN.induct}, is |
|
586 |
\[ \infer{P(x)}{x\in\listn(A) & P(\pair{0,\Nil}) & |
|
587 |
\infer*{P(\pair{\succ(n),\Cons(a,l)})} |
|
588 |
{[a\in A & \pair{n,l}\in\listn(A) & P(\pair{n,l})]_{a,l,n}}} |
|
589 |
\] |
|
590 |
This rule requires the induction formula to be a |
|
591 |
unary property of pairs,~$P(\pair{n,l})$. The alternative rule, {\tt |
|
592 |
ListN.mutual\_induct}, uses a binary property instead: |
|
130 | 593 |
\[ \infer{\forall n\,l. \pair{n,l}\in\listn(A) \imp P(n,l)} |
103 | 594 |
{P(0,\Nil) & |
595 |
\infer*{P(\succ(n),\Cons(a,l))} |
|
596 |
{[a\in A & \pair{n,l}\in\listn(A) & P(n,l)]_{a,l,n}}} |
|
597 |
\] |
|
598 |
It is now a simple matter to prove theorems about $\listn(A)$, such as |
|
599 |
\[ \forall l\in\lst(A). \pair{\length(l),\, l}\in\listn(A) \] |
|
600 |
\[ \listn(A)``\{n\} = \{l\in\lst(A). \length(l)=n\} \] |
|
130 | 601 |
This latter result --- here $r``X$ denotes the image of $X$ under $r$ |
103 | 602 |
--- asserts that the inductive definition agrees with the obvious notion of |
603 |
$n$-element list. |
|
604 |
||
605 |
Unlike in Coq, the definition does not declare a new datatype. A `list of |
|
130 | 606 |
$n$ elements' really is a list and is subject to list operators such |
607 |
as append (concatenation). For example, a trivial induction on |
|
608 |
$\pair{m,l}\in\listn(A)$ yields |
|
103 | 609 |
\[ \infer{\pair{m\mathbin{+} m,\, l@l'}\in\listn(A)} |
610 |
{\pair{m,l}\in\listn(A) & \pair{m',l'}\in\listn(A)} |
|
611 |
\] |
|
612 |
where $+$ here denotes addition on the natural numbers and @ denotes append. |
|
613 |
||
355 | 614 |
\subsection{A demonstration of rule inversion}\label{mkcases} |
103 | 615 |
The elimination rule, {\tt ListN.elim}, is cumbersome: |
616 |
\[ \infer{Q}{x\in\listn(A) & |
|
617 |
\infer*{Q}{[x = \pair{0,\Nil}]} & |
|
618 |
\infer*{Q} |
|
619 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} |
|
620 |
x = \pair{\succ(n),\Cons(a,l)} \\ |
|
621 |
a\in A \\ |
|
622 |
\pair{n,l}\in\listn(A) |
|
623 |
\end{array} \right]_{a,l,n}}} |
|
624 |
\] |
|
179 | 625 |
The ML function {\tt ListN.mk\_cases} generates simplified instances of |
626 |
this rule. It works by freeness reasoning on the list constructors: |
|
627 |
$\Cons(a,l)$ is injective in its two arguments and differs from~$\Nil$. If |
|
628 |
$x$ is $\pair{i,\Nil}$ or $\pair{i,\Cons(a,l)}$ then {\tt ListN.mk\_cases} |
|
355 | 629 |
deduces the corresponding form of~$i$; this is called rule inversion. For |
630 |
example, |
|
103 | 631 |
\begin{ttbox} |
632 |
ListN.mk_cases List.con_defs "<i,Cons(a,l)> : listn(A)" |
|
633 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
130 | 634 |
yields a rule with only two premises: |
103 | 635 |
\[ \infer{Q}{\pair{i, \Cons(a,l)}\in\listn(A) & |
636 |
\infer*{Q} |
|
637 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} |
|
638 |
i = \succ(n) \\ a\in A \\ \pair{n,l}\in\listn(A) |
|
639 |
\end{array} \right]_{n}}} |
|
640 |
\] |
|
641 |
The package also has built-in rules for freeness reasoning about $0$ |
|
642 |
and~$\succ$. So if $x$ is $\pair{0,l}$ or $\pair{\succ(i),l}$, then {\tt |
|
643 |
ListN.mk\_cases} can similarly deduce the corresponding form of~$l$. |
|
644 |
||
355 | 645 |
The function {\tt mk\_cases} is also useful with datatype definitions. The |
646 |
instance from the definition of lists, namely {\tt List.mk\_cases}, can |
|
647 |
prove the rule |
|
103 | 648 |
\[ \infer{Q}{\Cons(a,l)\in\lst(A) & |
649 |
& \infer*{Q}{[a\in A &l\in\lst(A)]} } |
|
650 |
\] |
|
355 | 651 |
A typical use of {\tt mk\_cases} concerns inductive definitions of |
652 |
evaluation relations. Then rule inversion yields case analysis on possible |
|
653 |
evaluations. For example, the Isabelle/ZF theory includes a short proof |
|
654 |
of the diamond property for parallel contraction on combinators. |
|
103 | 655 |
|
130 | 656 |
\subsection{A coinductive definition: bisimulations on lazy lists} |
657 |
This example anticipates the definition of the codatatype $\llist(A)$, which |
|
658 |
consists of finite and infinite lists over~$A$. Its constructors are $\LNil$ |
|
659 |
and |
|
660 |
$\LCons$, satisfying the introduction rules shown in~\S\ref{coind-sec}. |
|
103 | 661 |
Because $\llist(A)$ is defined as a greatest fixedpoint and uses the variant |
662 |
pairing and injection operators, it contains non-well-founded elements such as |
|
663 |
solutions to $\LCons(a,l)=l$. |
|
664 |
||
130 | 665 |
The next step in the development of lazy lists is to define a coinduction |
103 | 666 |
principle for proving equalities. This is done by showing that the equality |
667 |
relation on lazy lists is the greatest fixedpoint of some monotonic |
|
668 |
operation. The usual approach~\cite{pitts94} is to define some notion of |
|
669 |
bisimulation for lazy lists, define equivalence to be the greatest |
|
670 |
bisimulation, and finally to prove that two lazy lists are equivalent if and |
|
130 | 671 |
only if they are equal. The coinduction rule for equivalence then yields a |
672 |
coinduction principle for equalities. |
|
103 | 673 |
|
674 |
A binary relation $R$ on lazy lists is a {\bf bisimulation} provided $R\sbs |
|
675 |
R^+$, where $R^+$ is the relation |
|
130 | 676 |
\[ \{\pair{\LNil,\LNil}\} \un |
677 |
\{\pair{\LCons(a,l),\LCons(a,l')} . a\in A \conj \pair{l,l'}\in R\}. |
|
103 | 678 |
\] |
679 |
||
680 |
A pair of lazy lists are {\bf equivalent} if they belong to some bisimulation. |
|
130 | 681 |
Equivalence can be coinductively defined as the greatest fixedpoint for the |
103 | 682 |
introduction rules |
130 | 683 |
\[ \pair{\LNil,\LNil} \in\lleq(A) \qquad |
684 |
\infer[(-)]{\pair{\LCons(a,l),\LCons(a,l')} \in\lleq(A)} |
|
685 |
{a\in A & \pair{l,l'}\in \lleq(A)} |
|
103 | 686 |
\] |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
687 |
To make this coinductive definition, the theory file includes (after the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
688 |
declaration of $\llist(A)$) the following lines: |
103 | 689 |
\begin{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
690 |
consts lleq :: "i=>i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
691 |
coinductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
692 |
domains "lleq(A)" <= "llist(A) * llist(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
693 |
intrs |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
694 |
LNil "<LNil, LNil> : lleq(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
695 |
LCons "[| a:A; <l,l'>: lleq(A) |] ==> <LCons(a,l), LCons(a,l')>: lleq(A)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
696 |
type_intrs "llist.intrs" |
103 | 697 |
\end{ttbox} |
698 |
Again, {\tt addconsts} declares a constant for $\lleq$ in the parent theory. |
|
130 | 699 |
The domain of $\lleq(A)$ is $\llist(A)\times\llist(A)$. The type-checking |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
700 |
rules include the introduction rules for $\llist(A)$, whose |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
701 |
declaration is discussed below (\S\ref{lists-sec}). |
103 | 702 |
|
703 |
The package returns the introduction rules and the elimination rule, as |
|
130 | 704 |
usual. But instead of induction rules, it returns a coinduction rule. |
103 | 705 |
The rule is too big to display in the usual notation; its conclusion is |
130 | 706 |
$x\in\lleq(A)$ and its premises are $x\in X$, |
707 |
${X\sbs\llist(A)\times\llist(A)}$ and |
|
708 |
\[ \infer*{z=\pair{\LNil,\LNil}\disj \bigl(\exists a\,l\,l'.\, |
|
355 | 709 |
z=\pair{\LCons(a,l),\LCons(a,l')} \conj |
710 |
a\in A \conj\pair{l,l'}\in X\un\lleq(A) \bigr) |
|
711 |
% \begin{array}[t]{@{}l} |
|
712 |
% z=\pair{\LCons(a,l),\LCons(a,l')} \conj a\in A \conj{}\\ |
|
713 |
% \pair{l,l'}\in X\un\lleq(A) \bigr) |
|
714 |
% \end{array} |
|
715 |
}{[z\in X]_z} |
|
103 | 716 |
\] |
130 | 717 |
Thus if $x\in X$, where $X$ is a bisimulation contained in the |
718 |
domain of $\lleq(A)$, then $x\in\lleq(A)$. It is easy to show that |
|
103 | 719 |
$\lleq(A)$ is reflexive: the equality relation is a bisimulation. And |
720 |
$\lleq(A)$ is symmetric: its converse is a bisimulation. But showing that |
|
130 | 721 |
$\lleq(A)$ coincides with the equality relation takes some work. |
103 | 722 |
|
723 |
\subsection{The accessible part of a relation}\label{acc-sec} |
|
724 |
Let $\prec$ be a binary relation on~$D$; in short, $(\prec)\sbs D\times D$. |
|
725 |
The {\bf accessible} or {\bf well-founded} part of~$\prec$, written |
|
726 |
$\acc(\prec)$, is essentially that subset of~$D$ for which $\prec$ admits |
|
727 |
no infinite decreasing chains~\cite{aczel77}. Formally, $\acc(\prec)$ is |
|
728 |
inductively defined to be the least set that contains $a$ if it contains |
|
729 |
all $\prec$-predecessors of~$a$, for $a\in D$. Thus we need an |
|
730 |
introduction rule of the form |
|
731 |
\[ \infer{a\in\acc(\prec)}{\forall y.y\prec a\imp y\in\acc(\prec)} \] |
|
732 |
Paulin-Mohring treats this example in Coq~\cite{paulin92}, but it causes |
|
597 | 733 |
difficulties for other systems. Its premise is not acceptable to the |
734 |
inductive definition package of the Cambridge HOL |
|
735 |
system~\cite{camilleri92}. It is also unacceptable to Isabelle package |
|
736 |
(recall \S\ref{intro-sec}), but fortunately can be transformed into the |
|
737 |
acceptable form $t\in M(R)$. |
|
103 | 738 |
|
739 |
The powerset operator is monotonic, and $t\in\pow(R)$ is equivalent to |
|
740 |
$t\sbs R$. This in turn is equivalent to $\forall y\in t. y\in R$. To |
|
741 |
express $\forall y.y\prec a\imp y\in\acc(\prec)$ we need only find a |
|
742 |
term~$t$ such that $y\in t$ if and only if $y\prec a$. A suitable $t$ is |
|
743 |
the inverse image of~$\{a\}$ under~$\prec$. |
|
744 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
745 |
The theory file below follows this approach. Here $r$ is~$\prec$ and |
130 | 746 |
$\field(r)$ refers to~$D$, the domain of $\acc(r)$. (The field of a |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
747 |
relation is the union of its domain and range.) Finally $r^{-}``\{a\}$ |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
748 |
denotes the inverse image of~$\{a\}$ under~$r$. We supply the theorem {\tt |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
749 |
Pow\_mono}, which asserts that $\pow$ is monotonic. |
103 | 750 |
\begin{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
751 |
Acc = WF + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
752 |
consts acc :: "i=>i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
753 |
inductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
754 |
domains "acc(r)" <= "field(r)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
755 |
intrs |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
756 |
vimage "[| r-``\{a\}: Pow(acc(r)); a: field(r) |] ==> a: acc(r)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
757 |
monos "[Pow_mono]" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
758 |
end |
103 | 759 |
\end{ttbox} |
760 |
The Isabelle theory proceeds to prove facts about $\acc(\prec)$. For |
|
761 |
instance, $\prec$ is well-founded if and only if its field is contained in |
|
762 |
$\acc(\prec)$. |
|
763 |
||
764 |
As mentioned in~\S\ref{basic-ind-sec}, a premise of the form $t\in M(R)$ |
|
765 |
gives rise to an unusual induction hypothesis. Let us examine the |
|
766 |
induction rule, {\tt Acc.induct}: |
|
767 |
\[ \infer{P(x)}{x\in\acc(r) & |
|
768 |
\infer*{P(a)}{[r^{-}``\{a\}\in\pow(\{z\in\acc(r).P(z)\}) & |
|
769 |
a\in\field(r)]_a}} |
|
770 |
\] |
|
771 |
The strange induction hypothesis is equivalent to |
|
772 |
$\forall y. \pair{y,a}\in r\imp y\in\acc(r)\conj P(y)$. |
|
773 |
Therefore the rule expresses well-founded induction on the accessible part |
|
774 |
of~$\prec$. |
|
775 |
||
776 |
The use of inverse image is not essential. The Isabelle package can accept |
|
777 |
introduction rules with arbitrary premises of the form $\forall |
|
778 |
\vec{y}.P(\vec{y})\imp f(\vec{y})\in R$. The premise can be expressed |
|
779 |
equivalently as |
|
130 | 780 |
\[ \{z\in D. P(\vec{y}) \conj z=f(\vec{y})\} \in \pow(R) \] |
103 | 781 |
provided $f(\vec{y})\in D$ for all $\vec{y}$ such that~$P(\vec{y})$. The |
782 |
following section demonstrates another use of the premise $t\in M(R)$, |
|
783 |
where $M=\lst$. |
|
784 |
||
785 |
\subsection{The primitive recursive functions}\label{primrec-sec} |
|
786 |
The primitive recursive functions are traditionally defined inductively, as |
|
787 |
a subset of the functions over the natural numbers. One difficulty is that |
|
788 |
functions of all arities are taken together, but this is easily |
|
789 |
circumvented by regarding them as functions on lists. Another difficulty, |
|
790 |
the notion of composition, is less easily circumvented. |
|
791 |
||
792 |
Here is a more precise definition. Letting $\vec{x}$ abbreviate |
|
793 |
$x_0,\ldots,x_{n-1}$, we can write lists such as $[\vec{x}]$, |
|
794 |
$[y+1,\vec{x}]$, etc. A function is {\bf primitive recursive} if it |
|
795 |
belongs to the least set of functions in $\lst(\nat)\to\nat$ containing |
|
796 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
797 |
\item The {\bf successor} function $\SC$, such that $\SC[y,\vec{x}]=y+1$. |
|
798 |
\item All {\bf constant} functions $\CONST(k)$, such that |
|
799 |
$\CONST(k)[\vec{x}]=k$. |
|
800 |
\item All {\bf projection} functions $\PROJ(i)$, such that |
|
801 |
$\PROJ(i)[\vec{x}]=x_i$ if $0\leq i<n$. |
|
802 |
\item All {\bf compositions} $\COMP(g,[f_0,\ldots,f_{m-1}])$, |
|
803 |
where $g$ and $f_0$, \ldots, $f_{m-1}$ are primitive recursive, |
|
804 |
such that |
|
805 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
806 |
\COMP(g,[f_0,\ldots,f_{m-1}])[\vec{x}] & = & |
|
807 |
g[f_0[\vec{x}],\ldots,f_{m-1}[\vec{x}]]. |
|
808 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
809 |
||
810 |
\item All {\bf recursions} $\PREC(f,g)$, where $f$ and $g$ are primitive |
|
811 |
recursive, such that |
|
812 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
813 |
\PREC(f,g)[0,\vec{x}] & = & f[\vec{x}] \\ |
|
814 |
\PREC(f,g)[y+1,\vec{x}] & = & g[\PREC(f,g)[y,\vec{x}],\, y,\, \vec{x}]. |
|
815 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
816 |
\end{itemize} |
|
817 |
Composition is awkward because it combines not two functions, as is usual, |
|
818 |
but $m+1$ functions. In her proof that Ackermann's function is not |
|
819 |
primitive recursive, Nora Szasz was unable to formalize this definition |
|
820 |
directly~\cite{szasz93}. So she generalized primitive recursion to |
|
821 |
tuple-valued functions. This modified the inductive definition such that |
|
822 |
each operation on primitive recursive functions combined just two functions. |
|
823 |
||
824 |
\begin{figure} |
|
355 | 825 |
\begin{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
826 |
Primrec = List + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
827 |
consts |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
828 |
primrec :: "i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
829 |
SC :: "i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
830 |
\(\vdots\) |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
831 |
defs |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
832 |
SC_def "SC == lam l:list(nat).list_case(0, %x xs.succ(x), l)" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
833 |
\(\vdots\) |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
834 |
inductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
835 |
domains "primrec" <= "list(nat)->nat" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
836 |
intrs |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
837 |
SC "SC : primrec" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
838 |
CONST "k: nat ==> CONST(k) : primrec" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
839 |
PROJ "i: nat ==> PROJ(i) : primrec" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
840 |
COMP "[| g: primrec; fs: list(primrec) |] ==> COMP(g,fs): primrec" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
841 |
PREC "[| f: primrec; g: primrec |] ==> PREC(f,g): primrec" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
842 |
monos "[list_mono]" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
843 |
con_defs "[SC_def,CONST_def,PROJ_def,COMP_def,PREC_def]" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
844 |
type_intrs "nat_typechecks @ list.intrs @ \ttback |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
845 |
\ttback [lam_type, list_case_type, drop_type, map_type, \ttback |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
846 |
\ttback apply_type, rec_type]" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
847 |
end |
355 | 848 |
\end{ttbox} |
103 | 849 |
\hrule |
850 |
\caption{Inductive definition of the primitive recursive functions} |
|
851 |
\label{primrec-fig} |
|
852 |
\end{figure} |
|
853 |
\def\fs{{\it fs}} |
|
854 |
Szasz was using ALF, but Coq and HOL would also have problems accepting |
|
855 |
this definition. Isabelle's package accepts it easily since |
|
856 |
$[f_0,\ldots,f_{m-1}]$ is a list of primitive recursive functions and |
|
857 |
$\lst$ is monotonic. There are five introduction rules, one for each of |
|
355 | 858 |
the five forms of primitive recursive function. Let us examine the one for |
859 |
$\COMP$: |
|
103 | 860 |
\[ \infer{\COMP(g,\fs)\in\primrec}{g\in\primrec & \fs\in\lst(\primrec)} \] |
861 |
The induction rule for $\primrec$ has one case for each introduction rule. |
|
862 |
Due to the use of $\lst$ as a monotone operator, the composition case has |
|
863 |
an unusual induction hypothesis: |
|
864 |
\[ \infer*{P(\COMP(g,\fs))} |
|
130 | 865 |
{[g\in\primrec & \fs\in\lst(\{z\in\primrec.P(z)\})]_{\fs,g}} \] |
103 | 866 |
The hypothesis states that $\fs$ is a list of primitive recursive functions |
867 |
satisfying the induction formula. Proving the $\COMP$ case typically requires |
|
868 |
structural induction on lists, yielding two subcases: either $\fs=\Nil$ or |
|
869 |
else $\fs=\Cons(f,\fs')$, where $f\in\primrec$, $P(f)$, and $\fs'$ is |
|
870 |
another list of primitive recursive functions satisfying~$P$. |
|
871 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
872 |
Figure~\ref{primrec-fig} presents the theory file. Theory {\tt Primrec} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
873 |
defines the constants $\SC$, $\CONST$, etc. These are not constructors of |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
874 |
a new datatype, but functions over lists of numbers. Their definitions, |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
875 |
most of which are omitted, consist of routine list programming. In |
355 | 876 |
Isabelle/ZF, the primitive recursive functions are defined as a subset of |
877 |
the function set $\lst(\nat)\to\nat$. |
|
103 | 878 |
|
355 | 879 |
The Isabelle theory goes on to formalize Ackermann's function and prove |
880 |
that it is not primitive recursive, using the induction rule {\tt |
|
881 |
Primrec.induct}. The proof follows Szasz's excellent account. |
|
103 | 882 |
|
883 |
||
130 | 884 |
\section{Datatypes and codatatypes}\label{data-sec} |
885 |
A (co)datatype definition is a (co)inductive definition with automatically |
|
355 | 886 |
defined constructors and a case analysis operator. The package proves that |
887 |
the case operator inverts the constructors and can prove freeness theorems |
|
103 | 888 |
involving any pair of constructors. |
889 |
||
890 |
||
130 | 891 |
\subsection{Constructors and their domain}\label{univ-sec} |
355 | 892 |
Conceptually, our two forms of definition are distinct. A (co)inductive |
893 |
definition selects a subset of an existing set; a (co)datatype definition |
|
894 |
creates a new set. But the package reduces the latter to the former. A |
|
895 |
set having strong closure properties must serve as the domain of the |
|
896 |
(co)inductive definition. Constructing this set requires some theoretical |
|
897 |
effort, which must be done anyway to show that (co)datatypes exist. It is |
|
898 |
not obvious that standard set theory is suitable for defining codatatypes. |
|
103 | 899 |
|
900 |
Isabelle/ZF defines the standard notion of Cartesian product $A\times B$, |
|
901 |
containing ordered pairs $\pair{a,b}$. Now the $m$-tuple |
|
355 | 902 |
$\pair{x_1,\ldots,x_m}$ is the empty set~$\emptyset$ if $m=0$, simply |
903 |
$x_1$ if $m=1$ and $\pair{x_1,\pair{x_2,\ldots,x_m}}$ if $m\geq2$. |
|
103 | 904 |
Isabelle/ZF also defines the disjoint sum $A+B$, containing injections |
905 |
$\Inl(a)\equiv\pair{0,a}$ and $\Inr(b)\equiv\pair{1,b}$. |
|
906 |
||
355 | 907 |
A datatype constructor $\Con(x_1,\ldots,x_m)$ is defined to be |
908 |
$h(\pair{x_1,\ldots,x_m})$, where $h$ is composed of $\Inl$ and~$\Inr$. |
|
103 | 909 |
In a mutually recursive definition, all constructors for the set~$R_i$ have |
130 | 910 |
the outer form~$h_{in}$, where $h_{in}$ is the injection described |
103 | 911 |
in~\S\ref{mutual-sec}. Further nested injections ensure that the |
912 |
constructors for~$R_i$ are pairwise distinct. |
|
913 |
||
914 |
Isabelle/ZF defines the set $\univ(A)$, which contains~$A$ and |
|
915 |
furthermore contains $\pair{a,b}$, $\Inl(a)$ and $\Inr(b)$ for $a$, |
|
916 |
$b\in\univ(A)$. In a typical datatype definition with set parameters |
|
917 |
$A_1$, \ldots, $A_k$, a suitable domain for all the recursive sets is |
|
918 |
$\univ(A_1\un\cdots\un A_k)$. This solves the problem for |
|
919 |
datatypes~\cite[\S4.2]{paulson-set-II}. |
|
920 |
||
921 |
The standard pairs and injections can only yield well-founded |
|
922 |
constructions. This eases the (manual!) definition of recursive functions |
|
130 | 923 |
over datatypes. But they are unsuitable for codatatypes, which typically |
103 | 924 |
contain non-well-founded objects. |
925 |
||
130 | 926 |
To support codatatypes, Isabelle/ZF defines a variant notion of ordered |
103 | 927 |
pair, written~$\pair{a;b}$. It also defines the corresponding variant |
928 |
notion of Cartesian product $A\otimes B$, variant injections $\QInl(a)$ |
|
355 | 929 |
and~$\QInr(b)$ and variant disjoint sum $A\oplus B$. Finally it defines |
103 | 930 |
the set $\quniv(A)$, which contains~$A$ and furthermore contains |
931 |
$\pair{a;b}$, $\QInl(a)$ and $\QInr(b)$ for $a$, $b\in\quniv(A)$. In a |
|
130 | 932 |
typical codatatype definition with set parameters $A_1$, \ldots, $A_k$, a |
933 |
suitable domain is $\quniv(A_1\un\cdots\un A_k)$. This approach using |
|
355 | 934 |
standard ZF set theory~\cite{paulson-final} is an alternative to adopting |
935 |
Aczel's Anti-Foundation Axiom~\cite{aczel88}. |
|
103 | 936 |
|
937 |
\subsection{The case analysis operator} |
|
130 | 938 |
The (co)datatype package automatically defines a case analysis operator, |
179 | 939 |
called {\tt$R$\_case}. A mutually recursive definition still has only one |
940 |
operator, whose name combines those of the recursive sets: it is called |
|
941 |
{\tt$R_1$\_\ldots\_$R_n$\_case}. The case operator is analogous to those |
|
942 |
for products and sums. |
|
103 | 943 |
|
944 |
Datatype definitions employ standard products and sums, whose operators are |
|
945 |
$\split$ and $\case$ and satisfy the equations |
|
946 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
947 |
\split(f,\pair{x,y}) & = & f(x,y) \\ |
|
948 |
\case(f,g,\Inl(x)) & = & f(x) \\ |
|
949 |
\case(f,g,\Inr(y)) & = & g(y) |
|
950 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
951 |
Suppose the datatype has $k$ constructors $\Con_1$, \ldots,~$\Con_k$. Then |
|
952 |
its case operator takes $k+1$ arguments and satisfies an equation for each |
|
953 |
constructor: |
|
954 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
955 |
R\hbox{\_case}(f_1,\ldots,f_k, {\tt Con}_i(\vec{x})) & = & f_i(\vec{x}), |
|
956 |
\qquad i = 1, \ldots, k |
|
957 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
130 | 958 |
The case operator's definition takes advantage of Isabelle's representation |
959 |
of syntax in the typed $\lambda$-calculus; it could readily be adapted to a |
|
960 |
theorem prover for higher-order logic. If $f$ and~$g$ have meta-type |
|
961 |
$i\To i$ then so do $\split(f)$ and |
|
962 |
$\case(f,g)$. This works because $\split$ and $\case$ operate on their last |
|
963 |
argument. They are easily combined to make complex case analysis |
|
103 | 964 |
operators. Here are two examples: |
965 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
966 |
\item $\split(\lambda x.\split(f(x)))$ performs case analysis for |
|
967 |
$A\times (B\times C)$, as is easily verified: |
|
968 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
969 |
\split(\lambda x.\split(f(x)), \pair{a,b,c}) |
|
970 |
& = & (\lambda x.\split(f(x))(a,\pair{b,c}) \\ |
|
971 |
& = & \split(f(a), \pair{b,c}) \\ |
|
972 |
& = & f(a,b,c) |
|
973 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
974 |
||
975 |
\item $\case(f,\case(g,h))$ performs case analysis for $A+(B+C)$; let us |
|
976 |
verify one of the three equations: |
|
977 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
978 |
\case(f,\case(g,h), \Inr(\Inl(b))) |
|
979 |
& = & \case(g,h,\Inl(b)) \\ |
|
980 |
& = & g(b) |
|
981 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
982 |
\end{itemize} |
|
130 | 983 |
Codatatype definitions are treated in precisely the same way. They express |
103 | 984 |
case operators using those for the variant products and sums, namely |
985 |
$\qsplit$ and~$\qcase$. |
|
986 |
||
355 | 987 |
\medskip |
103 | 988 |
|
355 | 989 |
\ifCADE The package has processed all the datatypes discussed in |
990 |
my earlier paper~\cite{paulson-set-II} and the codatatype of lazy lists. |
|
991 |
Space limitations preclude discussing these examples here, but they are |
|
992 |
distributed with Isabelle. \typeout{****Omitting datatype examples from |
|
993 |
CADE version!} \else |
|
103 | 994 |
|
995 |
To see how constructors and the case analysis operator are defined, let us |
|
996 |
examine some examples. These include lists and trees/forests, which I have |
|
997 |
discussed extensively in another paper~\cite{paulson-set-II}. |
|
998 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
999 |
|
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1000 |
\subsection{Example: lists and lazy lists}\label{lists-sec} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1001 |
Here is a theory file that declares the datatype of lists: |
103 | 1002 |
\begin{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1003 |
List = Univ + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1004 |
consts list :: "i=>i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1005 |
datatype "list(A)" = Nil | Cons ("a:A", "l: list(A)") |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1006 |
end |
103 | 1007 |
\end{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1008 |
And here is the theory file that declares the codatatype of lazy lists: |
103 | 1009 |
\begin{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1010 |
LList = QUniv + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1011 |
consts llist :: "i=>i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1012 |
codatatype "llist(A)" = LNil | LCons ("a: A", "l: llist(A)") |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1013 |
end |
103 | 1014 |
\end{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1015 |
They highlight the (many) similarities and (few) differences between |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1016 |
datatype and codatatype definitions.\footnote{The real theory files contain |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1017 |
many more declarations, mainly of functions over lists; the declaration |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1018 |
of lazy lists is followed by the coinductive definition of lazy list |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1019 |
equality.} |
103 | 1020 |
|
1021 |
Each form of list has two constructors, one for the empty list and one for |
|
1022 |
adding an element to a list. Each takes a parameter, defining the set of |
|
1023 |
lists over a given set~$A$. Each uses the appropriate domain from a |
|
1024 |
Isabelle/ZF theory: |
|
1025 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1026 |
\item $\lst(A)$ requires the parent theory {\tt Univ}. The package |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1027 |
automatically uses the domain $\univ(A)$ (the default choice can be |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1028 |
overridden). |
103 | 1029 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1030 |
\item $\llist(A)$ requires the parent theory {\tt QUniv}. The package |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1031 |
automatically uses the domain $\quniv(A)$. |
103 | 1032 |
\end{itemize} |
1033 |
||
130 | 1034 |
Since $\lst(A)$ is a datatype, it enjoys a structural induction rule, {\tt |
1035 |
List.induct}: |
|
103 | 1036 |
\[ \infer{P(x)}{x\in\lst(A) & P(\Nil) |
1037 |
& \infer*{P(\Cons(a,l))}{[a\in A & l\in\lst(A) & P(l)]_{a,l}} } |
|
1038 |
\] |
|
1039 |
Induction and freeness yield the law $l\not=\Cons(a,l)$. To strengthen this, |
|
1040 |
Isabelle/ZF defines the rank of a set and proves that the standard pairs and |
|
1041 |
injections have greater rank than their components. An immediate consequence, |
|
1042 |
which justifies structural recursion on lists \cite[\S4.3]{paulson-set-II}, |
|
1043 |
is |
|
1044 |
\[ \rank(l) < \rank(\Cons(a,l)). \] |
|
1045 |
||
130 | 1046 |
Since $\llist(A)$ is a codatatype, it has no induction rule. Instead it has |
1047 |
the coinduction rule shown in \S\ref{coind-sec}. Since variant pairs and |
|
103 | 1048 |
injections are monotonic and need not have greater rank than their |
1049 |
components, fixedpoint operators can create cyclic constructions. For |
|
1050 |
example, the definition |
|
1051 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1052 |
\lconst(a) & \equiv & \lfp(\univ(a), \lambda l. \LCons(a,l)) |
|
1053 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1054 |
yields $\lconst(a) = \LCons(a,\lconst(a))$. |
|
1055 |
||
1056 |
\medskip |
|
1057 |
It may be instructive to examine the definitions of the constructors and |
|
1058 |
case operator for $\lst(A)$. The definitions for $\llist(A)$ are similar. |
|
1059 |
The list constructors are defined as follows: |
|
1060 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1061 |
\Nil & = & \Inl(\emptyset) \\ |
|
1062 |
\Cons(a,l) & = & \Inr(\pair{a,l}) |
|
1063 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1064 |
The operator $\lstcase$ performs case analysis on these two alternatives: |
|
1065 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1066 |
\lstcase(c,h) & \equiv & \case(\lambda u.c, \split(h)) |
|
1067 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1068 |
Let us verify the two equations: |
|
1069 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1070 |
\lstcase(c, h, \Nil) & = & |
|
1071 |
\case(\lambda u.c, \split(h), \Inl(\emptyset)) \\ |
|
1072 |
& = & (\lambda u.c)(\emptyset) \\ |
|
130 | 1073 |
& = & c\\[1ex] |
103 | 1074 |
\lstcase(c, h, \Cons(x,y)) & = & |
1075 |
\case(\lambda u.c, \split(h), \Inr(\pair{x,y})) \\ |
|
1076 |
& = & \split(h, \pair{x,y}) \\ |
|
130 | 1077 |
& = & h(x,y) |
103 | 1078 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
1079 |
||
1080 |
||
1081 |
\subsection{Example: mutual recursion} |
|
130 | 1082 |
In mutually recursive trees and forests~\cite[\S4.5]{paulson-set-II}, trees |
103 | 1083 |
have the one constructor $\Tcons$, while forests have the two constructors |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1084 |
$\Fnil$ and~$\Fcons$: |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1085 |
\begin{ttbox} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1086 |
TF = List + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1087 |
consts tree, forest, tree_forest :: "i=>i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1088 |
datatype "tree(A)" = Tcons ("a: A", "f: forest(A)") |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1089 |
and "forest(A)" = Fnil | Fcons ("t: tree(A)", "f: forest(A)") |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1090 |
end |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1091 |
\end{ttbox} |
103 | 1092 |
The three introduction rules define the mutual recursion. The |
1093 |
distinguishing feature of this example is its two induction rules. |
|
1094 |
||
1095 |
The basic induction rule is called {\tt TF.induct}: |
|
1096 |
\[ \infer{P(x)}{x\in\TF(A) & |
|
1097 |
\infer*{P(\Tcons(a,f))} |
|
1098 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} a\in A \\ |
|
1099 |
f\in\forest(A) \\ P(f) |
|
1100 |
\end{array} |
|
1101 |
\right]_{a,f}} |
|
1102 |
& P(\Fnil) |
|
130 | 1103 |
& \infer*{P(\Fcons(t,f))} |
103 | 1104 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} t\in\tree(A) \\ P(t) \\ |
1105 |
f\in\forest(A) \\ P(f) |
|
1106 |
\end{array} |
|
1107 |
\right]_{t,f}} } |
|
1108 |
\] |
|
1109 |
This rule establishes a single predicate for $\TF(A)$, the union of the |
|
1110 |
recursive sets. |
|
1111 |
||
1112 |
Although such reasoning is sometimes useful |
|
1113 |
\cite[\S4.5]{paulson-set-II}, a proper mutual induction rule should establish |
|
1114 |
separate predicates for $\tree(A)$ and $\forest(A)$. The package calls this |
|
1115 |
rule {\tt TF.mutual\_induct}. Observe the usage of $P$ and $Q$ in the |
|
1116 |
induction hypotheses: |
|
1117 |
\[ \infer{(\forall z. z\in\tree(A)\imp P(z)) \conj |
|
1118 |
(\forall z. z\in\forest(A)\imp Q(z))} |
|
1119 |
{\infer*{P(\Tcons(a,f))} |
|
1120 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} a\in A \\ |
|
1121 |
f\in\forest(A) \\ Q(f) |
|
1122 |
\end{array} |
|
1123 |
\right]_{a,f}} |
|
1124 |
& Q(\Fnil) |
|
130 | 1125 |
& \infer*{Q(\Fcons(t,f))} |
103 | 1126 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} t\in\tree(A) \\ P(t) \\ |
1127 |
f\in\forest(A) \\ Q(f) |
|
1128 |
\end{array} |
|
1129 |
\right]_{t,f}} } |
|
1130 |
\] |
|
1131 |
As mentioned above, the package does not define a structural recursion |
|
1132 |
operator. I have described elsewhere how this is done |
|
1133 |
\cite[\S4.5]{paulson-set-II}. |
|
1134 |
||
1135 |
Both forest constructors have the form $\Inr(\cdots)$, |
|
1136 |
while the tree constructor has the form $\Inl(\cdots)$. This pattern would |
|
1137 |
hold regardless of how many tree or forest constructors there were. |
|
1138 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1139 |
\Tcons(a,l) & = & \Inl(\pair{a,l}) \\ |
|
1140 |
\Fnil & = & \Inr(\Inl(\emptyset)) \\ |
|
1141 |
\Fcons(a,l) & = & \Inr(\Inr(\pair{a,l})) |
|
1142 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1143 |
There is only one case operator; it works on the union of the trees and |
|
1144 |
forests: |
|
1145 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1146 |
{\tt tree\_forest\_case}(f,c,g) & \equiv & |
|
1147 |
\case(\split(f),\, \case(\lambda u.c, \split(g))) |
|
1148 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1149 |
||
1150 |
||
1151 |
\subsection{A four-constructor datatype} |
|
1152 |
Finally let us consider a fairly general datatype. It has four |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1153 |
constructors $\Con_0$, \ldots, $\Con_3$, with the corresponding arities. |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1154 |
\begin{ttbox} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1155 |
Data = Univ + |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1156 |
consts data :: "[i,i] => i" |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1157 |
datatype "data(A,B)" = Con0 |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1158 |
| Con1 ("a: A") |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1159 |
| Con2 ("a: A", "b: B") |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1160 |
| Con3 ("a: A", "b: B", "d: data(A,B)") |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1161 |
end |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1162 |
\end{ttbox} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1163 |
Because this datatype has two set parameters, $A$ and~$B$, the package |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1164 |
automatically supplies $\univ(A\un B)$ as its domain. The structural |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1165 |
induction rule has four minor premises, one per constructor: |
103 | 1166 |
\[ \infer{P(x)}{x\in\data(A,B) & |
1167 |
P(\Con_0) & |
|
1168 |
\infer*{P(\Con_1(a))}{[a\in A]_a} & |
|
1169 |
\infer*{P(\Con_2(a,b))} |
|
1170 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} a\in A \\ b\in B \end{array} |
|
1171 |
\right]_{a,b}} & |
|
1172 |
\infer*{P(\Con_3(a,b,d))} |
|
1173 |
{\left[\begin{array}{l} a\in A \\ b\in B \\ |
|
1174 |
d\in\data(A,B) \\ P(d) |
|
1175 |
\end{array} |
|
1176 |
\right]_{a,b,d}} } |
|
1177 |
\] |
|
1178 |
||
1179 |
The constructor definitions are |
|
1180 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1181 |
\Con_0 & = & \Inl(\Inl(\emptyset)) \\ |
|
1182 |
\Con_1(a) & = & \Inl(\Inr(a)) \\ |
|
1183 |
\Con_2(a,b) & = & \Inr(\Inl(\pair{a,b})) \\ |
|
1184 |
\Con_3(a,b,c) & = & \Inr(\Inr(\pair{a,b,c})). |
|
1185 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1186 |
The case operator is |
|
1187 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1188 |
{\tt data\_case}(f_0,f_1,f_2,f_3) & \equiv & |
|
1189 |
\case(\begin{array}[t]{@{}l} |
|
1190 |
\case(\lambda u.f_0,\; f_1),\, \\ |
|
1191 |
\case(\split(f_2),\; \split(\lambda v.\split(f_3(v)))) ) |
|
1192 |
\end{array} |
|
1193 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1194 |
This may look cryptic, but the case equations are trivial to verify. |
|
1195 |
||
1196 |
In the constructor definitions, the injections are balanced. A more naive |
|
1197 |
approach is to define $\Con_3(a,b,c)$ as |
|
1198 |
$\Inr(\Inr(\Inr(\pair{a,b,c})))$; instead, each constructor has two |
|
1199 |
injections. The difference here is small. But the ZF examples include a |
|
1200 |
60-element enumeration type, where each constructor has 5 or~6 injections. |
|
1201 |
The naive approach would require 1 to~59 injections; the definitions would be |
|
1202 |
quadratic in size. It is like the difference between the binary and unary |
|
1203 |
numeral systems. |
|
1204 |
||
130 | 1205 |
The result structure contains the case operator and constructor definitions as |
1206 |
the theorem list \verb|con_defs|. It contains the case equations, such as |
|
103 | 1207 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
1208 |
{\tt data\_case}(f_0,f_1,f_2,f_3,\Con_3(a,b,c)) & = & f_3(a,b,c), |
|
1209 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1210 |
as the theorem list \verb|case_eqns|. There is one equation per constructor. |
|
1211 |
||
1212 |
\subsection{Proving freeness theorems} |
|
1213 |
There are two kinds of freeness theorems: |
|
1214 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
1215 |
\item {\bf injectiveness} theorems, such as |
|
1216 |
\[ \Con_2(a,b) = \Con_2(a',b') \bimp a=a' \conj b=b' \] |
|
1217 |
||
1218 |
\item {\bf distinctness} theorems, such as |
|
1219 |
\[ \Con_1(a) \not= \Con_2(a',b') \] |
|
1220 |
\end{itemize} |
|
1221 |
Since the number of such theorems is quadratic in the number of constructors, |
|
1222 |
the package does not attempt to prove them all. Instead it returns tools for |
|
1223 |
proving desired theorems --- either explicitly or `on the fly' during |
|
1224 |
simplification or classical reasoning. |
|
1225 |
||
1226 |
The theorem list \verb|free_iffs| enables the simplifier to perform freeness |
|
1227 |
reasoning. This works by incremental unfolding of constructors that appear in |
|
1228 |
equations. The theorem list contains logical equivalences such as |
|
1229 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
|
1230 |
\Con_0=c & \bimp & c=\Inl(\Inl(\emptyset)) \\ |
|
1231 |
\Con_1(a)=c & \bimp & c=\Inl(\Inr(a)) \\ |
|
1232 |
& \vdots & \\ |
|
1233 |
\Inl(a)=\Inl(b) & \bimp & a=b \\ |
|
130 | 1234 |
\Inl(a)=\Inr(b) & \bimp & {\tt False} \\ |
103 | 1235 |
\pair{a,b} = \pair{a',b'} & \bimp & a=a' \conj b=b' |
1236 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1237 |
For example, these rewrite $\Con_1(a)=\Con_1(b)$ to $a=b$ in four steps. |
|
1238 |
||
1239 |
The theorem list \verb|free_SEs| enables the classical |
|
1240 |
reasoner to perform similar replacements. It consists of elimination rules |
|
355 | 1241 |
to replace $\Con_0=c$ by $c=\Inl(\Inl(\emptyset))$ and so forth, in the |
103 | 1242 |
assumptions. |
1243 |
||
1244 |
Such incremental unfolding combines freeness reasoning with other proof |
|
1245 |
steps. It has the unfortunate side-effect of unfolding definitions of |
|
1246 |
constructors in contexts such as $\exists x.\Con_1(a)=x$, where they should |
|
1247 |
be left alone. Calling the Isabelle tactic {\tt fold\_tac con\_defs} |
|
1248 |
restores the defined constants. |
|
1249 |
\fi %CADE |
|
1250 |
||
355 | 1251 |
\section{Related work}\label{related} |
1252 |
The use of least fixedpoints to express inductive definitions seems |
|
1253 |
obvious. Why, then, has this technique so seldom been implemented? |
|
1254 |
||
1255 |
Most automated logics can only express inductive definitions by asserting |
|
1256 |
new axioms. Little would be left of Boyer and Moore's logic~\cite{bm79} if |
|
1257 |
their shell principle were removed. With ALF the situation is more |
|
1258 |
complex; earlier versions of Martin-L\"of's type theory could (using |
|
1259 |
wellordering types) express datatype definitions, but the version |
|
1260 |
underlying ALF requires new rules for each definition~\cite{dybjer91}. |
|
1261 |
With Coq the situation is subtler still; its underlying Calculus of |
|
1262 |
Constructions can express inductive definitions~\cite{huet88}, but cannot |
|
1263 |
quite handle datatype definitions~\cite{paulin92}. It seems that |
|
1264 |
researchers tried hard to circumvent these problems before finally |
|
1265 |
extending the Calculus with rule schemes for strictly positive operators. |
|
1266 |
||
1267 |
Higher-order logic can express inductive definitions through quantification |
|
1268 |
over unary predicates. The following formula expresses that~$i$ belongs to the |
|
1269 |
least set containing~0 and closed under~$\succ$: |
|
1270 |
\[ \forall P. P(0)\conj (\forall x.P(x)\imp P(\succ(x))) \imp P(i) \] |
|
1271 |
This technique can be used to prove the Knaster-Tarski Theorem, but it is |
|
597 | 1272 |
little used in the Cambridge HOL system. Melham~\cite{melham89} clearly |
1273 |
describes the development. The natural numbers are defined as shown above, |
|
1274 |
but lists are defined as functions over the natural numbers. Unlabelled |
|
355 | 1275 |
trees are defined using G\"odel numbering; a labelled tree consists of an |
1276 |
unlabelled tree paired with a list of labels. Melham's datatype package |
|
1277 |
expresses the user's datatypes in terms of labelled trees. It has been |
|
597 | 1278 |
highly successful, but a fixedpoint approach might have yielded greater |
355 | 1279 |
functionality with less effort. |
1280 |
||
1281 |
Melham's inductive definition package~\cite{camilleri92} uses |
|
1282 |
quantification over predicates, which is implicitly a fixedpoint approach. |
|
1283 |
Instead of formalizing the notion of monotone function, it requires |
|
1284 |
definitions to consist of finitary rules, a syntactic form that excludes |
|
1285 |
many monotone inductive definitions. |
|
1286 |
||
1287 |
The earliest use of least fixedpoints is probably Robin Milner's datatype |
|
1288 |
package for Edinburgh LCF~\cite{milner-ind}. Brian Monahan extended this |
|
1289 |
package considerably~\cite{monahan84}, as did I in unpublished |
|
1290 |
work.\footnote{The datatype package described in my LCF |
|
1291 |
book~\cite{paulson87} does {\it not\/} make definitions, but merely |
|
597 | 1292 |
asserts axioms.} |
355 | 1293 |
LCF is a first-order logic of domain theory; the relevant fixedpoint |
1294 |
theorem is not Knaster-Tarski but concerns fixedpoints of continuous |
|
1295 |
functions over domains. LCF is too weak to express recursive predicates. |
|
597 | 1296 |
Thus it would appear that the Isabelle package is the first to be based |
355 | 1297 |
on the Knaster-Tarski Theorem. |
1298 |
||
1299 |
||
103 | 1300 |
\section{Conclusions and future work} |
355 | 1301 |
Higher-order logic and set theory are both powerful enough to express |
1302 |
inductive definitions. A growing number of theorem provers implement one |
|
1303 |
of these~\cite{IMPS,saaltink-fme}. The easiest sort of inductive |
|
1304 |
definition package to write is one that asserts new axioms, not one that |
|
1305 |
makes definitions and proves theorems about them. But asserting axioms |
|
1306 |
could introduce unsoundness. |
|
1307 |
||
1308 |
The fixedpoint approach makes it fairly easy to implement a package for |
|
1309 |
(co)inductive definitions that does not assert axioms. It is efficient: it |
|
103 | 1310 |
processes most definitions in seconds and even a 60-constructor datatype |
1311 |
requires only two minutes. It is also simple: the package consists of |
|
1312 |
under 1100 lines (35K bytes) of Standard ML code. The first working |
|
1313 |
version took under a week to code. |
|
1314 |
||
355 | 1315 |
In set theory, care is required to ensure that the inductive definition |
1316 |
yields a set (rather than a proper class). This problem is inherent to set |
|
1317 |
theory, whether or not the Knaster-Tarski Theorem is employed. We must |
|
1318 |
exhibit a bounding set (called a domain above). For inductive definitions, |
|
1319 |
this is often trivial. For datatype definitions, I have had to formalize |
|
597 | 1320 |
much set theory. To justify infinitely branching datatype definitions, I |
1321 |
have had to develop a theory of cardinal arithmetic, such as the theorem |
|
1322 |
that if $\kappa$ is an infinite cardinal and $|X(\alpha)| \le \kappa$ for |
|
1323 |
all $\alpha<\kappa$ then $|\union\sb{\alpha<\kappa} X(\alpha)| \le \kappa$. |
|
1324 |
The need for such efforts is not a drawback of the fixedpoint |
|
355 | 1325 |
approach, for the alternative is to take such definitions on faith. |
103 | 1326 |
|
355 | 1327 |
The approach is not restricted to set theory. It should be suitable for |
1328 |
any logic that has some notion of set and the Knaster-Tarski Theorem. I |
|
597 | 1329 |
have ported the (co)inductive definition package from Isabelle/ZF to |
1330 |
Isabelle/HOL (higher-order logic). I hope to port the (co)datatype package |
|
1331 |
later. HOL represents sets by unary predicates; defining the corresponding |
|
1332 |
types may cause complications. |
|
103 | 1333 |
|
1334 |
||
355 | 1335 |
\bibliographystyle{springer} |
1197 | 1336 |
\bibliography{string-abbrv,atp,theory,funprog,isabelle,crossref} |
103 | 1337 |
%%%%%\doendnotes |
1338 |
||
1339 |
\ifCADE\typeout{****Omitting appendices from CADE version!} |
|
1340 |
\else |
|
1341 |
\newpage |
|
1342 |
\appendix |
|
130 | 1343 |
\section{Inductive and coinductive definitions: users guide} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1344 |
A theory file may contain any number of inductive and coinductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1345 |
definitions. They may be intermixed with other declarations; in |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1346 |
particular, the (co)inductive sets {\bf must} be declared separately as |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1347 |
constants, and may have mixfix syntax or be subject to syntax translations. |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1348 |
|
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1349 |
Each (co)inductive definition adds definitions to the theory and also |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1350 |
proves some theorems. Each definition creates an ML structure, which is a |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1351 |
substructure of the main theory structure. |
103 | 1352 |
|
1353 |
\subsection{The result structure} |
|
1354 |
Many of the result structure's components have been discussed |
|
1355 |
in~\S\ref{basic-sec}; others are self-explanatory. |
|
1356 |
\begin{description} |
|
1357 |
\item[\tt thy] is the new theory containing the recursive sets. |
|
1358 |
||
1359 |
\item[\tt defs] is the list of definitions of the recursive sets. |
|
1360 |
||
1361 |
\item[\tt bnd\_mono] is a monotonicity theorem for the fixedpoint operator. |
|
1362 |
||
1363 |
\item[\tt unfold] is a fixedpoint equation for the recursive set (the union of |
|
1364 |
the recursive sets, in the case of mutual recursion). |
|
1365 |
||
1366 |
\item[\tt dom\_subset] is a theorem stating inclusion in the domain. |
|
1367 |
||
1368 |
\item[\tt intrs] is the list of introduction rules, now proved as theorems, for |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1369 |
the recursive sets. The rules are also available individually, using the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1370 |
names given them in the theory file. |
103 | 1371 |
|
1372 |
\item[\tt elim] is the elimination rule. |
|
1373 |
||
1374 |
\item[\tt mk\_cases] is a function to create simplified instances of {\tt |
|
1375 |
elim}, using freeness reasoning on some underlying datatype. |
|
1376 |
\end{description} |
|
1377 |
||
1378 |
For an inductive definition, the result structure contains two induction rules, |
|
130 | 1379 |
{\tt induct} and \verb|mutual_induct|. For a coinductive definition, it |
1380 |
contains the rule \verb|coinduct|. |
|
1381 |
||
1382 |
Figure~\ref{def-result-fig} summarizes the two result signatures, |
|
1383 |
specifying the types of all these components. |
|
103 | 1384 |
|
1385 |
\begin{figure} |
|
1386 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
1387 |
sig |
|
1388 |
val thy : theory |
|
1389 |
val defs : thm list |
|
1390 |
val bnd_mono : thm |
|
1391 |
val unfold : thm |
|
1392 |
val dom_subset : thm |
|
1393 |
val intrs : thm list |
|
1394 |
val elim : thm |
|
1395 |
val mk_cases : thm list -> string -> thm |
|
1396 |
{\it(Inductive definitions only)} |
|
1397 |
val induct : thm |
|
1398 |
val mutual_induct: thm |
|
130 | 1399 |
{\it(Coinductive definitions only)} |
1400 |
val coinduct : thm |
|
103 | 1401 |
end |
1402 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
1403 |
\hrule |
|
130 | 1404 |
\caption{The result of a (co)inductive definition} \label{def-result-fig} |
103 | 1405 |
\end{figure} |
1406 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1407 |
\subsection{The syntax of a (co)inductive definition} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1408 |
An inductive definition has the form |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1409 |
\begin{ttbox} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1410 |
inductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1411 |
domains {\it domain declarations} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1412 |
intrs {\it introduction rules} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1413 |
monos {\it monotonicity theorems} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1414 |
con_defs {\it constructor definitions} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1415 |
type_intrs {\it introduction rules for type-checking} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1416 |
type_elims {\it elimination rules for type-checking} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1417 |
\end{ttbox} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1418 |
A coinductive definition is identical save that it starts with the keyword |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1419 |
{\tt coinductive}. |
103 | 1420 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1421 |
The {\tt monos}, {\tt con\_defs}, {\tt type\_intrs} and {\tt type\_elims} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1422 |
sections are optional. If present, each is specified as a string, which |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1423 |
must be a valid ML expression of type {\tt thm list}. It is simply |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1424 |
inserted into the {\tt .thy.ML} file; if it is ill-formed, it will trigger |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1425 |
ML error messages. You can then inspect the file on your directory. |
103 | 1426 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1427 |
\begin{description} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1428 |
\item[\it domain declarations] consist of one or more items of the form |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1429 |
{\it string\/}~{\tt <=}~{\it string}, associating each recursive set with |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1430 |
its domain. |
103 | 1431 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1432 |
\item[\it introduction rules] specify one or more introduction rules in |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1433 |
the form {\it ident\/}~{\it string}, where the identifier gives the name of |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1434 |
the rule in the result structure. |
103 | 1435 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1436 |
\item[\it monotonicity theorems] are required for each operator applied to |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1437 |
a recursive set in the introduction rules. There {\bf must} be a theorem |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1438 |
of the form $A\sbs B\Imp M(A)\sbs M(B)$, for each premise $t\in M(R_i)$ |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1439 |
in an introduction rule! |
103 | 1440 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1441 |
\item[\it constructor definitions] contain definitions of constants |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1442 |
appearing in the introduction rules. The (co)datatype package supplies |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1443 |
the constructors' definitions here. Most (co)inductive definitions omit |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1444 |
this section; one exception is the primitive recursive functions example |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1445 |
(\S\ref{primrec-sec}). |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1446 |
|
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1447 |
\item[\it type\_intrs] consists of introduction rules for type-checking the |
103 | 1448 |
definition, as discussed in~\S\ref{basic-sec}. They are applied using |
1449 |
depth-first search; you can trace the proof by setting |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1450 |
|
103 | 1451 |
\verb|trace_DEPTH_FIRST := true|. |
1452 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1453 |
\item[\it type\_elims] consists of elimination rules for type-checking the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1454 |
definition. They are presumed to be `safe' and are applied as much as |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1455 |
possible, prior to the {\tt type\_intrs} search. |
103 | 1456 |
\end{description} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1457 |
|
103 | 1458 |
The package has a few notable restrictions: |
1459 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1460 |
\item The theory must separately declare the recursive sets as |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1461 |
constants. |
103 | 1462 |
|
1463 |
\item The names of the recursive sets must be identifiers, not infix |
|
1464 |
operators. |
|
1465 |
||
1466 |
\item Side-conditions must not be conjunctions. However, an introduction rule |
|
1467 |
may contain any number of side-conditions. |
|
597 | 1468 |
|
1469 |
\item Side-conditions of the form $x=t$, where the variable~$x$ does not |
|
1470 |
occur in~$t$, will be substituted through the rule \verb|mutual_induct|. |
|
103 | 1471 |
\end{itemize} |
1472 |
||
1473 |
||
130 | 1474 |
\section{Datatype and codatatype definitions: users guide} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1475 |
This section explains how to include (co)datatype declarations in a theory |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1476 |
file. |
103 | 1477 |
|
1478 |
||
1479 |
\subsection{The result structure} |
|
130 | 1480 |
The result structure extends that of (co)inductive definitions |
103 | 1481 |
(Figure~\ref{def-result-fig}) with several additional items: |
1482 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
1483 |
val con_defs : thm list |
|
1484 |
val case_eqns : thm list |
|
1485 |
val free_iffs : thm list |
|
1486 |
val free_SEs : thm list |
|
1487 |
val mk_free : string -> thm |
|
1488 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
1489 |
Most of these have been discussed in~\S\ref{data-sec}. Here is a summary: |
|
1490 |
\begin{description} |
|
1491 |
\item[\tt con\_defs] is a list of definitions: the case operator followed by |
|
1492 |
the constructors. This theorem list can be supplied to \verb|mk_cases|, for |
|
1493 |
example. |
|
1494 |
||
1495 |
\item[\tt case\_eqns] is a list of equations, stating that the case operator |
|
1496 |
inverts each constructor. |
|
1497 |
||
1498 |
\item[\tt free\_iffs] is a list of logical equivalences to perform freeness |
|
1499 |
reasoning by rewriting. A typical application has the form |
|
1500 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
1501 |
by (asm_simp_tac (ZF_ss addsimps free_iffs) 1); |
|
1502 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
1503 |
||
1504 |
\item[\tt free\_SEs] is a list of `safe' elimination rules to perform freeness |
|
1505 |
reasoning. It can be supplied to \verb|eresolve_tac| or to the classical |
|
1506 |
reasoner: |
|
1507 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
1508 |
by (fast_tac (ZF_cs addSEs free_SEs) 1); |
|
1509 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
1510 |
||
1511 |
\item[\tt mk\_free] is a function to prove freeness properties, specified as |
|
1512 |
strings. The theorems can be expressed in various forms, such as logical |
|
1513 |
equivalences or elimination rules. |
|
1514 |
\end{description} |
|
1515 |
||
1516 |
The result structure also inherits everything from the underlying |
|
130 | 1517 |
(co)inductive definition, such as the introduction rules, elimination rule, |
179 | 1518 |
and (co)induction rule. |
103 | 1519 |
|
1520 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1521 |
\subsection{The syntax of a (co)datatype definition} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1522 |
A datatype definition has the form |
103 | 1523 |
\begin{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1524 |
datatype <={\it domain} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1525 |
{\it datatype declaration} and {\it datatype declaration} and \ldots |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1526 |
monos {\it monotonicity theorems} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1527 |
type_intrs {\it introduction rules for type-checking} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1528 |
type_elims {\it elimination rules for type-checking} |
103 | 1529 |
\end{ttbox} |
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1530 |
A codatatype definition is identical save that it starts with the keyword |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1531 |
{\tt codatatype}. The syntax is rather complicated; please consult the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1532 |
examples above (\S\ref{lists-sec}) and the theory files on the ZF source |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1533 |
directory. |
103 | 1534 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1535 |
The {\tt monos}, {\tt type\_intrs} and {\tt type\_elims} sections are |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1536 |
optional. They are treated like their counterparts in a (co)inductive |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1537 |
definition, as described above. The package supplements your type-checking |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1538 |
rules (if any) with additional ones that should cope with any |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1539 |
finitely-branching (co)datatype definition. |
103 | 1540 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1541 |
\begin{description} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1542 |
\item[\it domain] specifies a single domain to use for all the mutually |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1543 |
recursive (co)datatypes. If it (and the preceeding~{\tt <=}) are |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1544 |
omitted, the package supplies a domain automatically. Suppose the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1545 |
definition involves the set parameters $A_1$, \ldots, $A_k$. Then |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1546 |
$\univ(A_1\un\cdots\un A_k)$ is used for a datatype definition and |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1547 |
$\quniv(A_1\un\cdots\un A_k)$ is used for a codatatype definition. |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1548 |
|
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1549 |
These choices should work for all finitely-branching (co)datatype |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1550 |
definitions. For examples of infinitely-branching datatype |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1551 |
definitions, see the file {\tt ZF/ex/Brouwer.thy}. |
103 | 1552 |
|
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1553 |
\item[\it datatype declaration] has the form |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1554 |
\begin{quote} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1555 |
{\it string\/} {\tt =} {\it constructor} {\tt|} {\it constructor} {\tt|} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1556 |
\ldots |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1557 |
\end{quote} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1558 |
The {\it string\/} is the datatype, say {\tt"list(A)"}. Each |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1559 |
{\it constructor\/} has the form |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1560 |
\begin{quote} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1561 |
{\it name\/} {\tt(} {\it premise} {\tt,} {\it premise} {\tt,} \ldots {\tt)} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1562 |
{\it mixfix\/} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1563 |
\end{quote} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1564 |
The {\it name\/} specifies a new constructor while the {\it premises\/} its |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1565 |
typing conditions. The optional {\it mixfix\/} phrase may give |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1566 |
the constructor infix, for example. |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1567 |
|
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1568 |
Mutually recursive {\it datatype declarations\/} are separated by the |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1569 |
keyword~{\tt and}. |
103 | 1570 |
\end{description} |
1571 |
||
584
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1572 |
\paragraph*{Note.} |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1573 |
In the definitions of the constructors, the right-hand sides may overlap. |
5b1a0e50c79a
documentation of theory sections (co)inductive and (co)datatype
lcp
parents:
497
diff
changeset
|
1574 |
For instance, the datatype of combinators has constructors defined by |
103 | 1575 |
\begin{eqnarray*} |
1576 |
{\tt K} & \equiv & \Inl(\emptyset) \\ |
|
1577 |
{\tt S} & \equiv & \Inr(\Inl(\emptyset)) \\ |
|
1578 |
p{\tt\#}q & \equiv & \Inr(\Inl(\pair{p,q})) |
|
1579 |
\end{eqnarray*} |
|
1580 |
Unlike in previous versions of Isabelle, \verb|fold_tac| now ensures that the |
|
1581 |
longest right-hand sides are folded first. |
|
1582 |
||
1583 |
\fi |
|
1584 |
\end{document} |