author | nipkow |
Tue, 09 Sep 2008 19:33:22 +0200 | |
changeset 28180 | 3f69c3c54478 |
parent 11181 | d04f57b91166 |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
104 | 1 |
%%%THIS DOCUMENTS THE OBSOLETE SIMPLIFIER!!!! |
2 |
\chapter{Simplification} \label{simp-chap} |
|
3 |
\index{simplification|(} |
|
4 |
Object-level rewriting is not primitive in Isabelle. For efficiency, |
|
5 |
perhaps it ought to be. On the other hand, it is difficult to conceive of |
|
6 |
a general mechanism that could accommodate the diversity of rewriting found |
|
7 |
in different logics. Hence rewriting in Isabelle works via resolution, |
|
8 |
using unknowns as place-holders for simplified terms. This chapter |
|
9 |
describes a generic simplification package, the functor~\ttindex{SimpFun}, |
|
10 |
which expects the basic laws of equational logic and returns a suite of |
|
11 |
simplification tactics. The code lives in |
|
12 |
\verb$Provers/simp.ML$. |
|
13 |
||
14 |
This rewriting package is not as general as one might hope (using it for {\tt |
|
15 |
HOL} is not quite as convenient as it could be; rewriting modulo equations is |
|
16 |
not supported~\ldots) but works well for many logics. It performs |
|
17 |
conditional and unconditional rewriting and handles multiple reduction |
|
18 |
relations and local assumptions. It also has a facility for automatic case |
|
19 |
splits by expanding conditionals like {\it if-then-else\/} during rewriting. |
|
20 |
||
21 |
For many of Isabelle's logics ({\tt FOL}, {\tt ZF}, {\tt LCF} and {\tt HOL}) |
|
22 |
the simplifier has been set up already. Hence we start by describing the |
|
23 |
functions provided by the simplifier --- those functions exported by |
|
24 |
\ttindex{SimpFun} through its result signature \ttindex{SIMP} shown in |
|
286 | 25 |
Fig.\ts\ref{SIMP}. |
104 | 26 |
|
27 |
||
28 |
\section{Simplification sets} |
|
29 |
\index{simplification sets} |
|
30 |
The simplification tactics are controlled by {\bf simpsets}, which consist of |
|
31 |
three things: |
|
32 |
\begin{enumerate} |
|
33 |
\item {\bf Rewrite rules}, which are theorems like |
|
34 |
$\Var{m} + succ(\Var{n}) = succ(\Var{m} + \Var{n})$. {\bf Conditional} |
|
35 |
rewrites such as $m<n \Imp m/n = 0$ are permitted. |
|
36 |
\index{rewrite rules} |
|
37 |
||
38 |
\item {\bf Congruence rules}, which typically have the form |
|
39 |
\index{congruence rules} |
|
40 |
\[ \List{\Var{x@1} = \Var{y@1}; \ldots; \Var{x@n} = \Var{y@n}} \Imp |
|
41 |
f(\Var{x@1},\ldots,\Var{x@n}) = f(\Var{y@1},\ldots,\Var{y@n}). |
|
42 |
\] |
|
43 |
||
44 |
\item The {\bf auto-tactic}, which attempts to solve the simplified |
|
45 |
subgoal, say by recognizing it as a tautology. |
|
46 |
\end{enumerate} |
|
47 |
||
48 |
\subsection{Congruence rules} |
|
49 |
Congruence rules enable the rewriter to simplify subterms. Without a |
|
50 |
congruence rule for the function~$g$, no argument of~$g$ can be rewritten. |
|
51 |
Congruence rules can be generalized in the following ways: |
|
52 |
||
53 |
{\bf Additional assumptions} are allowed: |
|
54 |
\[ \List{\Var{P@1} \bimp \Var{Q@1};\; \Var{Q@1} \Imp \Var{P@2} \bimp \Var{Q@2}} |
|
55 |
\Imp (\Var{P@1} \imp \Var{P@2}) \bimp (\Var{Q@1} \imp \Var{Q@2}) |
|
56 |
\] |
|
57 |
This rule assumes $Q@1$, and any rewrite rules it contains, while |
|
1100 | 58 |
simplifying~$P@2$. Such `local' assumptions are effective for rewriting |
104 | 59 |
formulae such as $x=0\imp y+x=y$. |
60 |
||
61 |
{\bf Additional quantifiers} are allowed, typically for binding operators: |
|
62 |
\[ \List{\Forall z. \Var{P}(z) \bimp \Var{Q}(z)} \Imp |
|
63 |
\forall x.\Var{P}(x) \bimp \forall x.\Var{Q}(x) |
|
64 |
\] |
|
65 |
||
66 |
{\bf Different equalities} can be mixed. The following example |
|
67 |
enables the transition from formula rewriting to term rewriting: |
|
68 |
\[ \List{\Var{x@1}=\Var{y@1};\Var{x@2}=\Var{y@2}} \Imp |
|
69 |
(\Var{x@1}=\Var{x@2}) \bimp (\Var{y@1}=\Var{y@2}) |
|
70 |
\] |
|
71 |
\begin{warn} |
|
72 |
It is not necessary to assert a separate congruence rule for each constant, |
|
73 |
provided your logic contains suitable substitution rules. The function {\tt |
|
74 |
mk_congs} derives congruence rules from substitution |
|
75 |
rules~\S\ref{simp-tactics}. |
|
76 |
\end{warn} |
|
77 |
||
78 |
||
79 |
\begin{figure} |
|
80 |
\indexbold{*SIMP} |
|
81 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
82 |
infix 4 addrews addcongs delrews delcongs setauto; |
|
83 |
signature SIMP = |
|
84 |
sig |
|
85 |
type simpset |
|
86 |
val empty_ss : simpset |
|
87 |
val addcongs : simpset * thm list -> simpset |
|
88 |
val addrews : simpset * thm list -> simpset |
|
89 |
val delcongs : simpset * thm list -> simpset |
|
90 |
val delrews : simpset * thm list -> simpset |
|
91 |
val print_ss : simpset -> unit |
|
92 |
val setauto : simpset * (int -> tactic) -> simpset |
|
93 |
val ASM_SIMP_CASE_TAC : simpset -> int -> tactic |
|
94 |
val ASM_SIMP_TAC : simpset -> int -> tactic |
|
95 |
val CASE_TAC : simpset -> int -> tactic |
|
96 |
val SIMP_CASE2_TAC : simpset -> int -> tactic |
|
97 |
val SIMP_THM : simpset -> thm -> thm |
|
98 |
val SIMP_TAC : simpset -> int -> tactic |
|
99 |
val SIMP_CASE_TAC : simpset -> int -> tactic |
|
100 |
val mk_congs : theory -> string list -> thm list |
|
101 |
val mk_typed_congs : theory -> (string*string) list -> thm list |
|
102 |
val tracing : bool ref |
|
103 |
end; |
|
104 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
105 |
\caption{The signature {\tt SIMP}} \label{SIMP} |
|
106 |
\end{figure} |
|
107 |
||
108 |
||
109 |
\subsection{The abstract type {\tt simpset}}\label{simp-simpsets} |
|
110 |
Simpsets are values of the abstract type \ttindexbold{simpset}. They are |
|
111 |
manipulated by the following functions: |
|
112 |
\index{simplification sets|bold} |
|
323 | 113 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 114 |
\item[\ttindexbold{empty_ss}] |
115 |
is the empty simpset. It has no congruence or rewrite rules and its |
|
116 |
auto-tactic always fails. |
|
117 |
||
323 | 118 |
\item[$ss$ \ttindexbold{addcongs} $thms$] |
104 | 119 |
is the simpset~$ss$ plus the congruence rules~$thms$. |
120 |
||
323 | 121 |
\item[$ss$ \ttindexbold{delcongs} $thms$] |
104 | 122 |
is the simpset~$ss$ minus the congruence rules~$thms$. |
123 |
||
323 | 124 |
\item[$ss$ \ttindexbold{addrews} $thms$] |
104 | 125 |
is the simpset~$ss$ plus the rewrite rules~$thms$. |
126 |
||
323 | 127 |
\item[$ss$ \ttindexbold{delrews} $thms$] |
104 | 128 |
is the simpset~$ss$ minus the rewrite rules~$thms$. |
129 |
||
323 | 130 |
\item[$ss$ \ttindexbold{setauto} $tacf$] |
104 | 131 |
is the simpset~$ss$ with $tacf$ for its auto-tactic. |
132 |
||
133 |
\item[\ttindexbold{print_ss} $ss$] |
|
134 |
prints all the congruence and rewrite rules in the simpset~$ss$. |
|
323 | 135 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 136 |
Adding a rule to a simpset already containing it, or deleting one |
137 |
from a simpset not containing it, generates a warning message. |
|
138 |
||
139 |
In principle, any theorem can be used as a rewrite rule. Before adding a |
|
140 |
theorem to a simpset, {\tt addrews} preprocesses the theorem to extract the |
|
141 |
maximum amount of rewriting from it. Thus it need not have the form $s=t$. |
|
142 |
In {\tt FOL} for example, an atomic formula $P$ is transformed into the |
|
143 |
rewrite rule $P \bimp True$. This preprocessing is not fixed but logic |
|
144 |
dependent. The existing logics like {\tt FOL} are fairly clever in this |
|
145 |
respect. For a more precise description see {\tt mk_rew_rules} in |
|
146 |
\S\ref{SimpFun-input}. |
|
147 |
||
148 |
The auto-tactic is applied after simplification to solve a goal. This may |
|
149 |
be the overall goal or some subgoal that arose during conditional |
|
150 |
rewriting. Calling ${\tt auto_tac}~i$ must either solve exactly |
|
151 |
subgoal~$i$ or fail. If it succeeds without reducing the number of |
|
152 |
subgoals by one, havoc and strange exceptions may result. |
|
153 |
A typical auto-tactic is {\tt ares_tac [TrueI]}, which attempts proof by |
|
154 |
assumption and resolution with the theorem $True$. In explicitly typed |
|
155 |
logics, the auto-tactic can be used to solve simple type checking |
|
156 |
obligations. Some applications demand a sophisticated auto-tactic such as |
|
157 |
{\tt fast_tac}, but this could make simplification slow. |
|
158 |
||
159 |
\begin{warn} |
|
160 |
Rewriting never instantiates unknowns in subgoals. (It uses |
|
161 |
\ttindex{match_tac} rather than \ttindex{resolve_tac}.) However, the |
|
162 |
auto-tactic is permitted to instantiate unknowns. |
|
163 |
\end{warn} |
|
164 |
||
165 |
||
166 |
\section{The simplification tactics} \label{simp-tactics} |
|
167 |
\index{simplification!tactics|bold} |
|
168 |
\index{tactics!simplification|bold} |
|
169 |
The actual simplification work is performed by the following tactics. The |
|
170 |
rewriting strategy is strictly bottom up. Conditions in conditional rewrite |
|
171 |
rules are solved recursively before the rewrite rule is applied. |
|
172 |
||
173 |
There are two basic simplification tactics: |
|
323 | 174 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 175 |
\item[\ttindexbold{SIMP_TAC} $ss$ $i$] |
176 |
simplifies subgoal~$i$ using the rules in~$ss$. It may solve the |
|
177 |
subgoal completely if it has become trivial, using the auto-tactic |
|
178 |
(\S\ref{simp-simpsets}). |
|
179 |
||
180 |
\item[\ttindexbold{ASM_SIMP_TAC}] |
|
181 |
is like \verb$SIMP_TAC$, but also uses assumptions as additional |
|
182 |
rewrite rules. |
|
323 | 183 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 184 |
Many logics have conditional operators like {\it if-then-else}. If the |
185 |
simplifier has been set up with such case splits (see~\ttindex{case_splits} |
|
186 |
in \S\ref{SimpFun-input}), there are tactics which automatically alternate |
|
187 |
between simplification and case splitting: |
|
323 | 188 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 189 |
\item[\ttindexbold{SIMP_CASE_TAC}] |
190 |
is like {\tt SIMP_TAC} but also performs automatic case splits. |
|
191 |
More precisely, after each simplification phase the tactic tries to apply a |
|
192 |
theorem in \ttindex{case_splits}. If this succeeds, the tactic calls |
|
193 |
itself recursively on the result. |
|
194 |
||
195 |
\item[\ttindexbold{ASM_SIMP_CASE_TAC}] |
|
196 |
is like {\tt SIMP_CASE_TAC}, but also uses assumptions for |
|
197 |
rewriting. |
|
198 |
||
199 |
\item[\ttindexbold{SIMP_CASE2_TAC}] |
|
200 |
is like {\tt SIMP_CASE_TAC}, but also tries to solve the |
|
201 |
pre-conditions of conditional simplification rules by repeated case splits. |
|
202 |
||
203 |
\item[\ttindexbold{CASE_TAC}] |
|
204 |
tries to break up a goal using a rule in |
|
205 |
\ttindex{case_splits}. |
|
206 |
||
207 |
\item[\ttindexbold{SIMP_THM}] |
|
208 |
simplifies a theorem using assumptions and case splitting. |
|
323 | 209 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 210 |
Finally there are two useful functions for generating congruence |
211 |
rules for constants and free variables: |
|
323 | 212 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 213 |
\item[\ttindexbold{mk_congs} $thy$ $cs$] |
214 |
computes a list of congruence rules, one for each constant in $cs$. |
|
215 |
Remember that the name of an infix constant |
|
216 |
\verb$+$ is \verb$op +$. |
|
217 |
||
218 |
\item[\ttindexbold{mk_typed_congs}] |
|
219 |
computes congruence rules for explicitly typed free variables and |
|
220 |
constants. Its second argument is a list of name and type pairs. Names |
|
221 |
can be either free variables like {\tt P}, or constants like \verb$op =$. |
|
222 |
For example in {\tt FOL}, the pair |
|
223 |
\verb$("f","'a => 'a")$ generates the rule \verb$?x = ?y ==> f(?x) = f(?y)$. |
|
224 |
Such congruence rules are necessary for goals with free variables whose |
|
225 |
arguments need to be rewritten. |
|
323 | 226 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 227 |
Both functions work correctly only if {\tt SimpFun} has been supplied with the |
228 |
necessary substitution rules. The details are discussed in |
|
229 |
\S\ref{SimpFun-input} under {\tt subst_thms}. |
|
230 |
\begin{warn} |
|
231 |
Using the simplifier effectively may take a bit of experimentation. In |
|
232 |
particular it may often happen that simplification stops short of what you |
|
233 |
expected or runs forever. To diagnose these problems, the simplifier can be |
|
234 |
traced. The reference variable \ttindexbold{tracing} controls the output of |
|
235 |
tracing information. |
|
236 |
\index{tracing!of simplification} |
|
237 |
\end{warn} |
|
238 |
||
239 |
||
240 |
\section{Example: using the simplifier} |
|
241 |
\index{simplification!example} |
|
242 |
Assume we are working within {\tt FOL} and that |
|
323 | 243 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
244 |
\item[Nat.thy] is a theory including the constants $0$, $Suc$ and $+$, |
|
245 |
\item[add_0] is the rewrite rule $0+n = n$, |
|
246 |
\item[add_Suc] is the rewrite rule $Suc(m)+n = Suc(m+n)$, |
|
247 |
\item[induct] is the induction rule |
|
104 | 248 |
$\List{P(0); \Forall x. P(x)\Imp P(Suc(x))} \Imp P(n)$. |
323 | 249 |
\item[FOL_ss] is a basic simpset for {\tt FOL}. |
250 |
\end{ttdescription} |
|
104 | 251 |
We generate congruence rules for $Suc$ and for the infix operator~$+$: |
252 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
253 |
val nat_congs = mk_congs Nat.thy ["Suc", "op +"]; |
|
254 |
prths nat_congs; |
|
255 |
{\out ?Xa = ?Ya ==> Suc(?Xa) = Suc(?Ya)} |
|
256 |
{\out [| ?Xa = ?Ya; ?Xb = ?Yb |] ==> ?Xa + ?Xb = ?Ya + ?Yb} |
|
257 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
258 |
We create a simpset for natural numbers by extending~{\tt FOL_ss}: |
|
259 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
260 |
val add_ss = FOL_ss addcongs nat_congs |
|
261 |
addrews [add_0, add_Suc]; |
|
262 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
263 |
Proofs by induction typically involve simplification:\footnote |
|
264 |
{These examples reside on the file {\tt FOL/ex/nat.ML}.} |
|
265 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
266 |
goal Nat.thy "m+0 = m"; |
|
267 |
{\out Level 0} |
|
268 |
{\out m + 0 = m} |
|
269 |
{\out 1. m + 0 = m} |
|
270 |
\ttbreak |
|
271 |
by (res_inst_tac [("n","m")] induct 1); |
|
272 |
{\out Level 1} |
|
273 |
{\out m + 0 = m} |
|
274 |
{\out 1. 0 + 0 = 0} |
|
275 |
{\out 2. !!x. x + 0 = x ==> Suc(x) + 0 = Suc(x)} |
|
276 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
277 |
Simplification solves the first subgoal: |
|
278 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
279 |
by (SIMP_TAC add_ss 1); |
|
280 |
{\out Level 2} |
|
281 |
{\out m + 0 = m} |
|
282 |
{\out 1. !!x. x + 0 = x ==> Suc(x) + 0 = Suc(x)} |
|
283 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
284 |
The remaining subgoal requires \ttindex{ASM_SIMP_TAC} in order to use the |
|
285 |
induction hypothesis as a rewrite rule: |
|
286 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
287 |
by (ASM_SIMP_TAC add_ss 1); |
|
288 |
{\out Level 3} |
|
289 |
{\out m + 0 = m} |
|
290 |
{\out No subgoals!} |
|
291 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
292 |
The next proof is similar. |
|
293 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
294 |
goal Nat.thy "m+Suc(n) = Suc(m+n)"; |
|
295 |
{\out Level 0} |
|
296 |
{\out m + Suc(n) = Suc(m + n)} |
|
297 |
{\out 1. m + Suc(n) = Suc(m + n)} |
|
298 |
\ttbreak |
|
299 |
by (res_inst_tac [("n","m")] induct 1); |
|
300 |
{\out Level 1} |
|
301 |
{\out m + Suc(n) = Suc(m + n)} |
|
302 |
{\out 1. 0 + Suc(n) = Suc(0 + n)} |
|
303 |
{\out 2. !!x. x + Suc(n) = Suc(x + n) ==> Suc(x) + Suc(n) = Suc(Suc(x) + n)} |
|
304 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
305 |
Using the tactical \ttindex{ALLGOALS}, a single command simplifies all the |
|
306 |
subgoals: |
|
307 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
308 |
by (ALLGOALS (ASM_SIMP_TAC add_ss)); |
|
309 |
{\out Level 2} |
|
310 |
{\out m + Suc(n) = Suc(m + n)} |
|
311 |
{\out No subgoals!} |
|
312 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
313 |
Some goals contain free function variables. The simplifier must have |
|
314 |
congruence rules for those function variables, or it will be unable to |
|
315 |
simplify their arguments: |
|
316 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
317 |
val f_congs = mk_typed_congs Nat.thy [("f","nat => nat")]; |
|
318 |
val f_ss = add_ss addcongs f_congs; |
|
319 |
prths f_congs; |
|
320 |
{\out ?Xa = ?Ya ==> f(?Xa) = f(?Ya)} |
|
321 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
322 |
Here is a conjecture to be proved for an arbitrary function~$f$ satisfying |
|
323 |
the law $f(Suc(n)) = Suc(f(n))$: |
|
324 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
325 |
val [prem] = goal Nat.thy |
|
326 |
"(!!n. f(Suc(n)) = Suc(f(n))) ==> f(i+j) = i+f(j)"; |
|
327 |
{\out Level 0} |
|
328 |
{\out f(i + j) = i + f(j)} |
|
329 |
{\out 1. f(i + j) = i + f(j)} |
|
330 |
\ttbreak |
|
331 |
by (res_inst_tac [("n","i")] induct 1); |
|
332 |
{\out Level 1} |
|
333 |
{\out f(i + j) = i + f(j)} |
|
334 |
{\out 1. f(0 + j) = 0 + f(j)} |
|
335 |
{\out 2. !!x. f(x + j) = x + f(j) ==> f(Suc(x) + j) = Suc(x) + f(j)} |
|
336 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
337 |
We simplify each subgoal in turn. The first one is trivial: |
|
338 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
339 |
by (SIMP_TAC f_ss 1); |
|
340 |
{\out Level 2} |
|
341 |
{\out f(i + j) = i + f(j)} |
|
342 |
{\out 1. !!x. f(x + j) = x + f(j) ==> f(Suc(x) + j) = Suc(x) + f(j)} |
|
343 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
344 |
The remaining subgoal requires rewriting by the premise, shown |
|
345 |
below, so we add it to {\tt f_ss}: |
|
346 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
347 |
prth prem; |
|
348 |
{\out f(Suc(?n)) = Suc(f(?n)) [!!n. f(Suc(n)) = Suc(f(n))]} |
|
349 |
by (ASM_SIMP_TAC (f_ss addrews [prem]) 1); |
|
350 |
{\out Level 3} |
|
351 |
{\out f(i + j) = i + f(j)} |
|
352 |
{\out No subgoals!} |
|
353 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
354 |
||
355 |
||
356 |
\section{Setting up the simplifier} \label{SimpFun-input} |
|
357 |
\index{simplification!setting up|bold} |
|
358 |
To set up a simplifier for a new logic, the \ML\ functor |
|
359 |
\ttindex{SimpFun} needs to be supplied with theorems to justify |
|
360 |
rewriting. A rewrite relation must be reflexive and transitive; symmetry |
|
361 |
is not necessary. Hence the package is also applicable to non-symmetric |
|
362 |
relations such as occur in operational semantics. In the sequel, $\gg$ |
|
363 |
denotes some {\bf reduction relation}: a binary relation to be used for |
|
364 |
rewriting. Several reduction relations can be used at once. In {\tt FOL}, |
|
365 |
both $=$ (on terms) and $\bimp$ (on formulae) can be used for rewriting. |
|
366 |
||
367 |
The argument to {\tt SimpFun} is a structure with signature |
|
368 |
\ttindexbold{SIMP_DATA}: |
|
369 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
370 |
signature SIMP_DATA = |
|
371 |
sig |
|
372 |
val case_splits : (thm * string) list |
|
373 |
val dest_red : term -> term * term * term |
|
374 |
val mk_rew_rules : thm -> thm list |
|
375 |
val norm_thms : (thm*thm) list |
|
376 |
val red1 : thm |
|
377 |
val red2 : thm |
|
378 |
val refl_thms : thm list |
|
379 |
val subst_thms : thm list |
|
380 |
val trans_thms : thm list |
|
381 |
end; |
|
382 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
383 |
The components of {\tt SIMP_DATA} need to be instantiated as follows. Many |
|
384 |
of these components are lists, and can be empty. |
|
323 | 385 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 386 |
\item[\ttindexbold{refl_thms}] |
387 |
supplies reflexivity theorems of the form $\Var{x} \gg |
|
388 |
\Var{x}$. They must not have additional premises as, for example, |
|
389 |
$\Var{x}\in\Var{A} \Imp \Var{x} = \Var{x}\in\Var{A}$ in type theory. |
|
390 |
||
391 |
\item[\ttindexbold{trans_thms}] |
|
392 |
supplies transitivity theorems of the form |
|
393 |
$\List{\Var{x}\gg\Var{y}; \Var{y}\gg\Var{z}} \Imp {\Var{x}\gg\Var{z}}$. |
|
394 |
||
395 |
\item[\ttindexbold{red1}] |
|
396 |
is a theorem of the form $\List{\Var{P}\gg\Var{Q}; |
|
397 |
\Var{P}} \Imp \Var{Q}$, where $\gg$ is a relation between formulae, such as |
|
398 |
$\bimp$ in {\tt FOL}. |
|
399 |
||
400 |
\item[\ttindexbold{red2}] |
|
401 |
is a theorem of the form $\List{\Var{P}\gg\Var{Q}; |
|
402 |
\Var{Q}} \Imp \Var{P}$, where $\gg$ is a relation between formulae, such as |
|
403 |
$\bimp$ in {\tt FOL}. |
|
404 |
||
405 |
\item[\ttindexbold{mk_rew_rules}] |
|
406 |
is a function that extracts rewrite rules from theorems. A rewrite rule is |
|
407 |
a theorem of the form $\List{\ldots}\Imp s \gg t$. In its simplest form, |
|
408 |
{\tt mk_rew_rules} maps a theorem $t$ to the singleton list $[t]$. More |
|
409 |
sophisticated versions may do things like |
|
410 |
\[ |
|
411 |
\begin{array}{l@{}r@{\quad\mapsto\quad}l} |
|
412 |
\mbox{create formula rewrites:}& P & [P \bimp True] \\[.5ex] |
|
11181
d04f57b91166
renamed addaltern to addafter, addSaltern to addSafter
oheimb
parents:
9695
diff
changeset
|
413 |
\mbox{remove negations:}& \neg P & [P \bimp False] \\[.5ex] |
104 | 414 |
\mbox{create conditional rewrites:}& P\imp s\gg t & [P\Imp s\gg t] \\[.5ex] |
415 |
\mbox{break up conjunctions:}& |
|
416 |
(s@1 \gg@1 t@1) \conj (s@2 \gg@2 t@2) & [s@1 \gg@1 t@1, s@2 \gg@2 t@2] |
|
417 |
\end{array} |
|
418 |
\] |
|
419 |
The more theorems are turned into rewrite rules, the better. The function |
|
420 |
is used in two places: |
|
421 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
422 |
\item |
|
423 |
$ss$~\ttindex{addrews}~$thms$ applies {\tt mk_rew_rules} to each element of |
|
424 |
$thms$ before adding it to $ss$. |
|
425 |
\item |
|
426 |
simplification with assumptions (as in \ttindex{ASM_SIMP_TAC}) uses |
|
427 |
{\tt mk_rew_rules} to turn assumptions into rewrite rules. |
|
428 |
\end{itemize} |
|
429 |
||
430 |
\item[\ttindexbold{case_splits}] |
|
431 |
supplies expansion rules for case splits. The simplifier is designed |
|
432 |
for rules roughly of the kind |
|
433 |
\[ \Var{P}(if(\Var{Q},\Var{x},\Var{y})) \bimp (\Var{Q} \imp \Var{P}(\Var{x})) |
|
11181
d04f57b91166
renamed addaltern to addafter, addSaltern to addSafter
oheimb
parents:
9695
diff
changeset
|
434 |
\conj (\neg\Var{Q} \imp \Var{P}(\Var{y})) |
104 | 435 |
\] |
436 |
but is insensitive to the form of the right-hand side. Other examples |
|
437 |
include product types, where $split :: |
|
438 |
(\alpha\To\beta\To\gamma)\To\alpha*\beta\To\gamma$: |
|
439 |
\[ \Var{P}(split(\Var{f},\Var{p})) \bimp (\forall a~b. \Var{p} = |
|
440 |
{<}a,b{>} \imp \Var{P}(\Var{f}(a,b))) |
|
441 |
\] |
|
442 |
Each theorem in the list is paired with the name of the constant being |
|
443 |
eliminated, {\tt"if"} and {\tt"split"} in the examples above. |
|
444 |
||
445 |
\item[\ttindexbold{norm_thms}] |
|
446 |
supports an optimization. It should be a list of pairs of rules of the |
|
447 |
form $\Var{x} \gg norm(\Var{x})$ and $norm(\Var{x}) \gg \Var{x}$. These |
|
448 |
introduce and eliminate {\tt norm}, an arbitrary function that should be |
|
449 |
used nowhere else. This function serves to tag subterms that are in normal |
|
450 |
form. Such rules can speed up rewriting significantly! |
|
451 |
||
452 |
\item[\ttindexbold{subst_thms}] |
|
453 |
supplies substitution rules of the form |
|
454 |
\[ \List{\Var{x} \gg \Var{y}; \Var{P}(\Var{x})} \Imp \Var{P}(\Var{y}) \] |
|
455 |
They are used to derive congruence rules via \ttindex{mk_congs} and |
|
456 |
\ttindex{mk_typed_congs}. If $f :: [\tau@1,\cdots,\tau@n]\To\tau$ is a |
|
457 |
constant or free variable, the computation of a congruence rule |
|
458 |
\[\List{\Var{x@1} \gg@1 \Var{y@1}; \ldots; \Var{x@n} \gg@n \Var{y@n}} |
|
459 |
\Imp f(\Var{x@1},\ldots,\Var{x@n}) \gg f(\Var{y@1},\ldots,\Var{y@n}) \] |
|
460 |
requires a reflexivity theorem for some reduction ${\gg} :: |
|
461 |
\alpha\To\alpha\To\sigma$ such that $\tau$ is an instance of $\alpha$. If a |
|
462 |
suitable reflexivity law is missing, no congruence rule for $f$ can be |
|
463 |
generated. Otherwise an $n$-ary congruence rule of the form shown above is |
|
464 |
derived, subject to the availability of suitable substitution laws for each |
|
465 |
argument position. |
|
466 |
||
467 |
A substitution law is suitable for argument $i$ if it |
|
468 |
uses a reduction ${\gg@i} :: \alpha@i\To\alpha@i\To\sigma@i$ such that |
|
469 |
$\tau@i$ is an instance of $\alpha@i$. If a suitable substitution law for |
|
470 |
argument $i$ is missing, the $i^{th}$ premise of the above congruence rule |
|
471 |
cannot be generated and hence argument $i$ cannot be rewritten. In the |
|
472 |
worst case, if there are no suitable substitution laws at all, the derived |
|
473 |
congruence simply degenerates into a reflexivity law. |
|
474 |
||
475 |
\item[\ttindexbold{dest_red}] |
|
476 |
takes reductions apart. Given a term $t$ representing the judgement |
|
477 |
\mbox{$a \gg b$}, \verb$dest_red$~$t$ should return a triple $(c,ta,tb)$ |
|
478 |
where $ta$ and $tb$ represent $a$ and $b$, and $c$ is a term of the form |
|
479 |
\verb$Const(_,_)$, the reduction constant $\gg$. |
|
480 |
||
481 |
Suppose the logic has a coercion function like $Trueprop::o\To prop$, as do |
|
482 |
{\tt FOL} and~{\tt HOL}\@. If $\gg$ is a binary operator (not necessarily |
|
483 |
infix), the following definition does the job: |
|
484 |
\begin{verbatim} |
|
485 |
fun dest_red( _ $ (c $ ta $ tb) ) = (c,ta,tb); |
|
486 |
\end{verbatim} |
|
487 |
The wildcard pattern {\tt_} matches the coercion function. |
|
323 | 488 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 489 |
|
490 |
||
491 |
\section{A sample instantiation} |
|
9695 | 492 |
Here is the instantiation of {\tt SIMP_DATA} for FOL. The code for {\tt |
493 |
mk_rew_rules} is not shown; see the file {\tt FOL/simpdata.ML}. |
|
104 | 494 |
\begin{ttbox} |
495 |
structure FOL_SimpData : SIMP_DATA = |
|
496 |
struct |
|
497 |
val refl_thms = [ \(\Var{x}=\Var{x}\), \(\Var{P}\bimp\Var{P}\) ] |
|
498 |
val trans_thms = [ \(\List{\Var{x}=\Var{y};\Var{y}=\Var{z}}\Imp\Var{x}=\Var{z}\), |
|
499 |
\(\List{\Var{P}\bimp\Var{Q};\Var{Q}\bimp\Var{R}}\Imp\Var{P}\bimp\Var{R}\) ] |
|
500 |
val red1 = \(\List{\Var{P}\bimp\Var{Q}; \Var{P}} \Imp \Var{Q}\) |
|
501 |
val red2 = \(\List{\Var{P}\bimp\Var{Q}; \Var{Q}} \Imp \Var{P}\) |
|
502 |
val mk_rew_rules = ... |
|
503 |
val case_splits = [ \(\Var{P}(if(\Var{Q},\Var{x},\Var{y})) \bimp\) |
|
11181
d04f57b91166
renamed addaltern to addafter, addSaltern to addSafter
oheimb
parents:
9695
diff
changeset
|
504 |
\((\Var{Q} \imp \Var{P}(\Var{x})) \conj (\neg\Var{Q} \imp \Var{P}(\Var{y}))\) ] |
104 | 505 |
val norm_thms = [ (\(\Var{x}=norm(\Var{x})\),\(norm(\Var{x})=\Var{x}\)), |
506 |
(\(\Var{P}\bimp{}NORM(\Var{P}\)), \(NORM(\Var{P})\bimp\Var{P}\)) ] |
|
507 |
val subst_thms = [ \(\List{\Var{x}=\Var{y}; \Var{P}(\Var{x})}\Imp\Var{P}(\Var{y})\) ] |
|
508 |
val dest_red = fn (_ $ (opn $ lhs $ rhs)) => (opn,lhs,rhs) |
|
509 |
end; |
|
510 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
511 |
||
512 |
\index{simplification|)} |