author | paulson |
Wed, 20 Mar 1996 18:42:31 +0100 | |
changeset 1593 | 69ed69a9c32a |
parent 1590 | 1547174673e1 |
child 1846 | 763f08fb194f |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
104 | 1 |
%% $Id$ |
2 |
\chapter{Theorems and Forward Proof} |
|
3 |
\index{theorems|(} |
|
326 | 4 |
|
104 | 5 |
Theorems, which represent the axioms, theorems and rules of object-logics, |
326 | 6 |
have type \mltydx{thm}. This chapter begins by describing operations that |
7 |
print theorems and that join them in forward proof. Most theorem |
|
8 |
operations are intended for advanced applications, such as programming new |
|
9 |
proof procedures. Many of these operations refer to signatures, certified |
|
10 |
terms and certified types, which have the \ML{} types {\tt Sign.sg}, {\tt |
|
11 |
Sign.cterm} and {\tt Sign.ctyp} and are discussed in |
|
104 | 12 |
Chapter~\ref{theories}. Beginning users should ignore such complexities |
13 |
--- and skip all but the first section of this chapter. |
|
14 |
||
15 |
The theorem operations do not print error messages. Instead, they raise |
|
326 | 16 |
exception~\xdx{THM}\@. Use \ttindex{print_exn} to display |
104 | 17 |
exceptions nicely: |
18 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
19 |
allI RS mp handle e => print_exn e; |
|
20 |
{\out Exception THM raised:} |
|
21 |
{\out RSN: no unifiers -- premise 1} |
|
22 |
{\out (!!x. ?P(x)) ==> ALL x. ?P(x)} |
|
23 |
{\out [| ?P --> ?Q; ?P |] ==> ?Q} |
|
24 |
{\out} |
|
25 |
{\out uncaught exception THM} |
|
26 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
27 |
||
28 |
||
29 |
\section{Basic operations on theorems} |
|
30 |
\subsection{Pretty-printing a theorem} |
|
326 | 31 |
\index{theorems!printing of} |
104 | 32 |
\begin{ttbox} |
326 | 33 |
prth : thm -> thm |
34 |
prths : thm list -> thm list |
|
35 |
prthq : thm Sequence.seq -> thm Sequence.seq |
|
36 |
print_thm : thm -> unit |
|
37 |
print_goals : int -> thm -> unit |
|
38 |
string_of_thm : thm -> string |
|
104 | 39 |
\end{ttbox} |
326 | 40 |
The first three commands are for interactive use. They are identity |
41 |
functions that display, then return, their argument. The \ML{} identifier |
|
42 |
{\tt it} will refer to the value just displayed. |
|
43 |
||
44 |
The others are for use in programs. Functions with result type {\tt unit} |
|
45 |
are convenient for imperative programming. |
|
46 |
||
47 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
|
104 | 48 |
\item[\ttindexbold{prth} {\it thm}] |
49 |
prints {\it thm\/} at the terminal. |
|
50 |
||
51 |
\item[\ttindexbold{prths} {\it thms}] |
|
52 |
prints {\it thms}, a list of theorems. |
|
53 |
||
54 |
\item[\ttindexbold{prthq} {\it thmq}] |
|
55 |
prints {\it thmq}, a sequence of theorems. It is useful for inspecting |
|
56 |
the output of a tactic. |
|
57 |
||
58 |
\item[\ttindexbold{print_thm} {\it thm}] |
|
59 |
prints {\it thm\/} at the terminal. |
|
60 |
||
61 |
\item[\ttindexbold{print_goals} {\it limit\/} {\it thm}] |
|
62 |
prints {\it thm\/} in goal style, with the premises as subgoals. It prints |
|
63 |
at most {\it limit\/} subgoals. The subgoal module calls {\tt print_goals} |
|
64 |
to display proof states. |
|
65 |
||
66 |
\item[\ttindexbold{string_of_thm} {\it thm}] |
|
67 |
converts {\it thm\/} to a string. |
|
326 | 68 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 69 |
|
70 |
||
326 | 71 |
\subsection{Forward proof: joining rules by resolution} |
72 |
\index{theorems!joining by resolution} |
|
73 |
\index{resolution}\index{forward proof} |
|
104 | 74 |
\begin{ttbox} |
75 |
RSN : thm * (int * thm) -> thm \hfill{\bf infix} |
|
76 |
RS : thm * thm -> thm \hfill{\bf infix} |
|
77 |
MRS : thm list * thm -> thm \hfill{\bf infix} |
|
78 |
RLN : thm list * (int * thm list) -> thm list \hfill{\bf infix} |
|
79 |
RL : thm list * thm list -> thm list \hfill{\bf infix} |
|
326 | 80 |
MRL : thm list list * thm list -> thm list \hfill{\bf infix} |
104 | 81 |
\end{ttbox} |
326 | 82 |
Joining rules together is a simple way of deriving new rules. These |
876 | 83 |
functions are especially useful with destruction rules. To store |
84 |
the result in the theorem database, use \ttindex{bind_thm} |
|
85 |
(\S\ref{ExtractingAndStoringTheProvedTheorem}). |
|
326 | 86 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 87 |
\item[\tt$thm@1$ RSN $(i,thm@2)$] \indexbold{*RSN} |
326 | 88 |
resolves the conclusion of $thm@1$ with the $i$th premise of~$thm@2$. |
89 |
Unless there is precisely one resolvent it raises exception |
|
90 |
\xdx{THM}; in that case, use {\tt RLN}. |
|
104 | 91 |
|
92 |
\item[\tt$thm@1$ RS $thm@2$] \indexbold{*RS} |
|
93 |
abbreviates \hbox{\tt$thm@1$ RSN $(1,thm@2)$}. Thus, it resolves the |
|
94 |
conclusion of $thm@1$ with the first premise of~$thm@2$. |
|
95 |
||
96 |
\item[\tt {$[thm@1,\ldots,thm@n]$} MRS $thm$] \indexbold{*MRS} |
|
332 | 97 |
uses {\tt RSN} to resolve $thm@i$ against premise~$i$ of $thm$, for |
104 | 98 |
$i=n$, \ldots,~1. This applies $thm@n$, \ldots, $thm@1$ to the first $n$ |
99 |
premises of $thm$. Because the theorems are used from right to left, it |
|
100 |
does not matter if the $thm@i$ create new premises. {\tt MRS} is useful |
|
101 |
for expressing proof trees. |
|
102 |
||
151 | 103 |
\item[\tt$thms@1$ RLN $(i,thms@2)$] \indexbold{*RLN} |
326 | 104 |
joins lists of theorems. For every $thm@1$ in $thms@1$ and $thm@2$ in |
105 |
$thms@2$, it resolves the conclusion of $thm@1$ with the $i$th premise |
|
106 |
of~$thm@2$, accumulating the results. |
|
104 | 107 |
|
151 | 108 |
\item[\tt$thms@1$ RL $thms@2$] \indexbold{*RL} |
109 |
abbreviates \hbox{\tt$thms@1$ RLN $(1,thms@2)$}. |
|
104 | 110 |
|
111 |
\item[\tt {$[thms@1,\ldots,thms@n]$} MRL $thms$] \indexbold{*MRL} |
|
112 |
is analogous to {\tt MRS}, but combines theorem lists rather than theorems. |
|
113 |
It too is useful for expressing proof trees. |
|
326 | 114 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 115 |
|
116 |
||
117 |
\subsection{Expanding definitions in theorems} |
|
326 | 118 |
\index{meta-rewriting!in theorems} |
104 | 119 |
\begin{ttbox} |
120 |
rewrite_rule : thm list -> thm -> thm |
|
121 |
rewrite_goals_rule : thm list -> thm -> thm |
|
122 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 123 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 124 |
\item[\ttindexbold{rewrite_rule} {\it defs} {\it thm}] |
125 |
unfolds the {\it defs} throughout the theorem~{\it thm}. |
|
126 |
||
127 |
\item[\ttindexbold{rewrite_goals_rule} {\it defs} {\it thm}] |
|
128 |
unfolds the {\it defs} in the premises of~{\it thm}, but leaves the |
|
129 |
conclusion unchanged. This rule underlies \ttindex{rewrite_goals_tac}, but |
|
130 |
serves little purpose in forward proof. |
|
326 | 131 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 132 |
|
133 |
||
326 | 134 |
\subsection{Instantiating a theorem} |
135 |
\index{instantiation} |
|
286 | 136 |
\begin{ttbox} |
104 | 137 |
read_instantiate : (string*string)list -> thm -> thm |
138 |
read_instantiate_sg : Sign.sg -> (string*string)list -> thm -> thm |
|
139 |
cterm_instantiate : (Sign.cterm*Sign.cterm)list -> thm -> thm |
|
140 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
141 |
These meta-rules instantiate type and term unknowns in a theorem. They are |
|
142 |
occasionally useful. They can prevent difficulties with higher-order |
|
143 |
unification, and define specialized versions of rules. |
|
326 | 144 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 145 |
\item[\ttindexbold{read_instantiate} {\it insts} {\it thm}] |
146 |
processes the instantiations {\it insts} and instantiates the rule~{\it |
|
147 |
thm}. The processing of instantiations is described |
|
326 | 148 |
in \S\ref{res_inst_tac}, under {\tt res_inst_tac}. |
104 | 149 |
|
150 |
Use {\tt res_inst_tac}, not {\tt read_instantiate}, to instantiate a rule |
|
151 |
and refine a particular subgoal. The tactic allows instantiation by the |
|
152 |
subgoal's parameters, and reads the instantiations using the signature |
|
326 | 153 |
associated with the proof state. |
154 |
||
155 |
Use {\tt read_instantiate_sg} below if {\it insts\/} appears to be treated |
|
156 |
incorrectly. |
|
104 | 157 |
|
326 | 158 |
\item[\ttindexbold{read_instantiate_sg} {\it sg} {\it insts} {\it thm}] |
159 |
resembles \hbox{\tt read_instantiate {\it insts} {\it thm}}, but reads |
|
160 |
the instantiations under signature~{\it sg}. This is necessary to |
|
161 |
instantiate a rule from a general theory, such as first-order logic, |
|
162 |
using the notation of some specialized theory. Use the function {\tt |
|
163 |
sign_of} to get a theory's signature. |
|
104 | 164 |
|
165 |
\item[\ttindexbold{cterm_instantiate} {\it ctpairs} {\it thm}] |
|
166 |
is similar to {\tt read_instantiate}, but the instantiations are provided |
|
167 |
as pairs of certified terms, not as strings to be read. |
|
326 | 168 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 169 |
|
170 |
||
866
2d3d020eef11
added documentation of bind_thm, qed, qed_goal, get_thm, thms_of
clasohm
parents:
332
diff
changeset
|
171 |
\subsection{Miscellaneous forward rules}\label{MiscellaneousForwardRules} |
326 | 172 |
\index{theorems!standardizing} |
104 | 173 |
\begin{ttbox} |
332 | 174 |
standard : thm -> thm |
175 |
zero_var_indexes : thm -> thm |
|
176 |
make_elim : thm -> thm |
|
104 | 177 |
rule_by_tactic : tactic -> thm -> thm |
178 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 179 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 180 |
\item[\ttindexbold{standard} $thm$] |
181 |
puts $thm$ into the standard form of object-rules. It discharges all |
|
332 | 182 |
meta-assumptions, replaces free variables by schematic variables, and |
104 | 183 |
renames schematic variables to have subscript zero. |
184 |
||
185 |
\item[\ttindexbold{zero_var_indexes} $thm$] |
|
186 |
makes all schematic variables have subscript zero, renaming them to avoid |
|
187 |
clashes. |
|
188 |
||
189 |
\item[\ttindexbold{make_elim} $thm$] |
|
190 |
\index{rules!converting destruction to elimination} |
|
191 |
converts $thm$, a destruction rule of the form $\List{P@1;\ldots;P@m}\Imp |
|
192 |
Q$, to the elimination rule $\List{P@1; \ldots; P@m; Q\Imp R}\Imp R$. This |
|
193 |
is the basis for destruct-resolution: {\tt dresolve_tac}, etc. |
|
194 |
||
195 |
\item[\ttindexbold{rule_by_tactic} {\it tac} {\it thm}] |
|
196 |
applies {\it tac\/} to the {\it thm}, freezing its variables first, then |
|
197 |
yields the proof state returned by the tactic. In typical usage, the |
|
198 |
{\it thm\/} represents an instance of a rule with several premises, some |
|
199 |
with contradictory assumptions (because of the instantiation). The |
|
200 |
tactic proves those subgoals and does whatever else it can, and returns |
|
201 |
whatever is left. |
|
326 | 202 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 203 |
|
204 |
||
205 |
\subsection{Taking a theorem apart} |
|
326 | 206 |
\index{theorems!taking apart} |
104 | 207 |
\index{flex-flex constraints} |
208 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
209 |
concl_of : thm -> term |
|
210 |
prems_of : thm -> term list |
|
211 |
nprems_of : thm -> int |
|
212 |
tpairs_of : thm -> (term*term)list |
|
213 |
stamps_of_thy : thm -> string ref list |
|
866
2d3d020eef11
added documentation of bind_thm, qed, qed_goal, get_thm, thms_of
clasohm
parents:
332
diff
changeset
|
214 |
theory_of_thm : thm -> theory |
286 | 215 |
dest_state : thm*int -> (term*term)list*term list*term*term |
1590 | 216 |
rep_thm : thm -> \{prop: term, hyps: term list, |
217 |
maxidx: int, der: deriv, sign: Sign.sg\} |
|
104 | 218 |
\end{ttbox} |
326 | 219 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 220 |
\item[\ttindexbold{concl_of} $thm$] |
221 |
returns the conclusion of $thm$ as a term. |
|
222 |
||
223 |
\item[\ttindexbold{prems_of} $thm$] |
|
224 |
returns the premises of $thm$ as a list of terms. |
|
225 |
||
226 |
\item[\ttindexbold{nprems_of} $thm$] |
|
286 | 227 |
returns the number of premises in $thm$, and is equivalent to {\tt |
228 |
length(prems_of~$thm$)}. |
|
104 | 229 |
|
230 |
\item[\ttindexbold{tpairs_of} $thm$] |
|
231 |
returns the flex-flex constraints of $thm$. |
|
232 |
||
233 |
\item[\ttindexbold{stamps_of_thm} $thm$] |
|
332 | 234 |
returns the \rmindex{stamps} of the signature associated with~$thm$. |
104 | 235 |
|
866
2d3d020eef11
added documentation of bind_thm, qed, qed_goal, get_thm, thms_of
clasohm
parents:
332
diff
changeset
|
236 |
\item[\ttindexbold{theory_of_thm} $thm$] |
2d3d020eef11
added documentation of bind_thm, qed, qed_goal, get_thm, thms_of
clasohm
parents:
332
diff
changeset
|
237 |
returns the theory associated with $thm$. |
2d3d020eef11
added documentation of bind_thm, qed, qed_goal, get_thm, thms_of
clasohm
parents:
332
diff
changeset
|
238 |
|
104 | 239 |
\item[\ttindexbold{dest_state} $(thm,i)$] |
240 |
decomposes $thm$ as a tuple containing a list of flex-flex constraints, a |
|
241 |
list of the subgoals~1 to~$i-1$, subgoal~$i$, and the rest of the theorem |
|
242 |
(this will be an implication if there are more than $i$ subgoals). |
|
243 |
||
244 |
\item[\ttindexbold{rep_thm} $thm$] |
|
245 |
decomposes $thm$ as a record containing the statement of~$thm$, its list of |
|
332 | 246 |
meta-assumptions, the maximum subscript of its unknowns, and its signature. |
326 | 247 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 248 |
|
249 |
||
250 |
\subsection{Tracing flags for unification} |
|
326 | 251 |
\index{tracing!of unification} |
104 | 252 |
\begin{ttbox} |
253 |
Unify.trace_simp : bool ref \hfill{\bf initially false} |
|
254 |
Unify.trace_types : bool ref \hfill{\bf initially false} |
|
255 |
Unify.trace_bound : int ref \hfill{\bf initially 10} |
|
256 |
Unify.search_bound : int ref \hfill{\bf initially 20} |
|
257 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
258 |
Tracing the search may be useful when higher-order unification behaves |
|
259 |
unexpectedly. Letting {\tt res_inst_tac} circumvent the problem is easier, |
|
260 |
though. |
|
326 | 261 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
262 |
\item[Unify.trace_simp := true;] |
|
104 | 263 |
causes tracing of the simplification phase. |
264 |
||
326 | 265 |
\item[Unify.trace_types := true;] |
104 | 266 |
generates warnings of incompleteness, when unification is not considering |
267 |
all possible instantiations of type unknowns. |
|
268 |
||
326 | 269 |
\item[Unify.trace_bound := $n$;] |
104 | 270 |
causes unification to print tracing information once it reaches depth~$n$. |
271 |
Use $n=0$ for full tracing. At the default value of~10, tracing |
|
272 |
information is almost never printed. |
|
273 |
||
326 | 274 |
\item[Unify.search_bound := $n$;] |
104 | 275 |
causes unification to limit its search to depth~$n$. Because of this |
276 |
bound, higher-order unification cannot return an infinite sequence, though |
|
277 |
it can return a very long one. The search rarely approaches the default |
|
278 |
value of~20. If the search is cut off, unification prints {\tt |
|
279 |
***Unification bound exceeded}. |
|
326 | 280 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 281 |
|
282 |
||
283 |
\section{Primitive meta-level inference rules} |
|
284 |
\index{meta-rules|(} |
|
285 |
These implement the meta-logic in {\sc lcf} style, as functions from theorems |
|
286 |
to theorems. They are, rarely, useful for deriving results in the pure |
|
287 |
theory. Mainly, they are included for completeness, and most users should |
|
326 | 288 |
not bother with them. The meta-rules raise exception \xdx{THM} to signal |
104 | 289 |
malformed premises, incompatible signatures and similar errors. |
290 |
||
326 | 291 |
\index{meta-assumptions} |
104 | 292 |
The meta-logic uses natural deduction. Each theorem may depend on |
332 | 293 |
meta-level assumptions. Certain rules, such as $({\Imp}I)$, |
104 | 294 |
discharge assumptions; in most other rules, the conclusion depends on all |
295 |
of the assumptions of the premises. Formally, the system works with |
|
296 |
assertions of the form |
|
297 |
\[ \phi \quad [\phi@1,\ldots,\phi@n], \] |
|
332 | 298 |
where $\phi@1$,~\ldots,~$\phi@n$ are the assumptions. Do not confuse |
104 | 299 |
meta-level assumptions with the object-level assumptions in a subgoal, |
300 |
which are represented in the meta-logic using~$\Imp$. |
|
301 |
||
302 |
Each theorem has a signature. Certified terms have a signature. When a |
|
303 |
rule takes several premises and certified terms, it merges the signatures |
|
304 |
to make a signature for the conclusion. This fails if the signatures are |
|
305 |
incompatible. |
|
306 |
||
326 | 307 |
\index{meta-implication} |
332 | 308 |
The {\bf implication} rules are $({\Imp}I)$ |
104 | 309 |
and $({\Imp}E)$: |
310 |
\[ \infer[({\Imp}I)]{\phi\Imp \psi}{\infer*{\psi}{[\phi]}} \qquad |
|
311 |
\infer[({\Imp}E)]{\psi}{\phi\Imp \psi & \phi} \] |
|
312 |
||
326 | 313 |
\index{meta-equality} |
104 | 314 |
Equality of truth values means logical equivalence: |
315 |
\[ \infer[({\equiv}I)]{\phi\equiv\psi}{\infer*{\psi}{[\phi]} & |
|
286 | 316 |
\infer*{\phi}{[\psi]}} |
104 | 317 |
\qquad |
318 |
\infer[({\equiv}E)]{\psi}{\phi\equiv \psi & \phi} \] |
|
319 |
||
332 | 320 |
The {\bf equality} rules are reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity: |
104 | 321 |
\[ {a\equiv a}\,(refl) \qquad |
322 |
\infer[(sym)]{b\equiv a}{a\equiv b} \qquad |
|
323 |
\infer[(trans)]{a\equiv c}{a\equiv b & b\equiv c} \] |
|
324 |
||
326 | 325 |
\index{lambda calc@$\lambda$-calculus} |
104 | 326 |
The $\lambda$-conversions are $\alpha$-conversion, $\beta$-conversion, and |
327 |
extensionality:\footnote{$\alpha$-conversion holds if $y$ is not free |
|
328 |
in~$a$; $(ext)$ holds if $x$ is not free in the assumptions, $f$, or~$g$.} |
|
329 |
\[ {(\lambda x.a) \equiv (\lambda y.a[y/x])} \qquad |
|
330 |
{((\lambda x.a)(b)) \equiv a[b/x]} \qquad |
|
331 |
\infer[(ext)]{f\equiv g}{f(x) \equiv g(x)} \] |
|
332 |
||
332 | 333 |
The {\bf abstraction} and {\bf combination} rules let conversions be |
334 |
applied to subterms:\footnote{Abstraction holds if $x$ is not free in the |
|
104 | 335 |
assumptions.} |
336 |
\[ \infer[(abs)]{(\lambda x.a) \equiv (\lambda x.b)}{a\equiv b} \qquad |
|
337 |
\infer[(comb)]{f(a)\equiv g(b)}{f\equiv g & a\equiv b} \] |
|
338 |
||
326 | 339 |
\index{meta-quantifiers} |
332 | 340 |
The {\bf universal quantification} rules are $(\Forall I)$ and $(\Forall |
104 | 341 |
E)$:\footnote{$(\Forall I)$ holds if $x$ is not free in the assumptions.} |
342 |
\[ \infer[(\Forall I)]{\Forall x.\phi}{\phi} \qquad |
|
286 | 343 |
\infer[(\Forall E)]{\phi[b/x]}{\Forall x.\phi} \] |
104 | 344 |
|
345 |
||
326 | 346 |
\subsection{Assumption rule} |
347 |
\index{meta-assumptions} |
|
104 | 348 |
\begin{ttbox} |
349 |
assume: Sign.cterm -> thm |
|
350 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 351 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 352 |
\item[\ttindexbold{assume} $ct$] |
332 | 353 |
makes the theorem \(\phi \;[\phi]\), where $\phi$ is the value of~$ct$. |
104 | 354 |
The rule checks that $ct$ has type $prop$ and contains no unknowns, which |
332 | 355 |
are not allowed in assumptions. |
326 | 356 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 357 |
|
326 | 358 |
\subsection{Implication rules} |
359 |
\index{meta-implication} |
|
104 | 360 |
\begin{ttbox} |
361 |
implies_intr : Sign.cterm -> thm -> thm |
|
362 |
implies_intr_list : Sign.cterm list -> thm -> thm |
|
363 |
implies_intr_hyps : thm -> thm |
|
364 |
implies_elim : thm -> thm -> thm |
|
365 |
implies_elim_list : thm -> thm list -> thm |
|
366 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 367 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 368 |
\item[\ttindexbold{implies_intr} $ct$ $thm$] |
369 |
is $({\Imp}I)$, where $ct$ is the assumption to discharge, say~$\phi$. It |
|
332 | 370 |
maps the premise~$\psi$ to the conclusion $\phi\Imp\psi$, removing all |
371 |
occurrences of~$\phi$ from the assumptions. The rule checks that $ct$ has |
|
372 |
type $prop$. |
|
104 | 373 |
|
374 |
\item[\ttindexbold{implies_intr_list} $cts$ $thm$] |
|
375 |
applies $({\Imp}I)$ repeatedly, on every element of the list~$cts$. |
|
376 |
||
377 |
\item[\ttindexbold{implies_intr_hyps} $thm$] |
|
332 | 378 |
applies $({\Imp}I)$ to discharge all the hypotheses (assumptions) of~$thm$. |
379 |
It maps the premise $\phi \; [\phi@1,\ldots,\phi@n]$ to the conclusion |
|
104 | 380 |
$\List{\phi@1,\ldots,\phi@n}\Imp\phi$. |
381 |
||
382 |
\item[\ttindexbold{implies_elim} $thm@1$ $thm@2$] |
|
383 |
applies $({\Imp}E)$ to $thm@1$ and~$thm@2$. It maps the premises $\phi\Imp |
|
384 |
\psi$ and $\phi$ to the conclusion~$\psi$. |
|
385 |
||
386 |
\item[\ttindexbold{implies_elim_list} $thm$ $thms$] |
|
387 |
applies $({\Imp}E)$ repeatedly to $thm$, using each element of~$thms$ in |
|
151 | 388 |
turn. It maps the premises $\List{\phi@1,\ldots,\phi@n}\Imp\psi$ and |
104 | 389 |
$\phi@1$,\ldots,$\phi@n$ to the conclusion~$\psi$. |
326 | 390 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 391 |
|
326 | 392 |
\subsection{Logical equivalence rules} |
393 |
\index{meta-equality} |
|
104 | 394 |
\begin{ttbox} |
326 | 395 |
equal_intr : thm -> thm -> thm |
396 |
equal_elim : thm -> thm -> thm |
|
104 | 397 |
\end{ttbox} |
326 | 398 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 399 |
\item[\ttindexbold{equal_intr} $thm@1$ $thm@2$] |
332 | 400 |
applies $({\equiv}I)$ to $thm@1$ and~$thm@2$. It maps the premises~$\psi$ |
401 |
and~$\phi$ to the conclusion~$\phi\equiv\psi$; the assumptions are those of |
|
402 |
the first premise with~$\phi$ removed, plus those of |
|
403 |
the second premise with~$\psi$ removed. |
|
104 | 404 |
|
405 |
\item[\ttindexbold{equal_elim} $thm@1$ $thm@2$] |
|
406 |
applies $({\equiv}E)$ to $thm@1$ and~$thm@2$. It maps the premises |
|
407 |
$\phi\equiv\psi$ and $\phi$ to the conclusion~$\psi$. |
|
326 | 408 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 409 |
|
410 |
||
411 |
\subsection{Equality rules} |
|
326 | 412 |
\index{meta-equality} |
104 | 413 |
\begin{ttbox} |
414 |
reflexive : Sign.cterm -> thm |
|
415 |
symmetric : thm -> thm |
|
416 |
transitive : thm -> thm -> thm |
|
417 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 418 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 419 |
\item[\ttindexbold{reflexive} $ct$] |
151 | 420 |
makes the theorem \(ct\equiv ct\). |
104 | 421 |
|
422 |
\item[\ttindexbold{symmetric} $thm$] |
|
423 |
maps the premise $a\equiv b$ to the conclusion $b\equiv a$. |
|
424 |
||
425 |
\item[\ttindexbold{transitive} $thm@1$ $thm@2$] |
|
426 |
maps the premises $a\equiv b$ and $b\equiv c$ to the conclusion~${a\equiv c}$. |
|
326 | 427 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 428 |
|
429 |
||
430 |
\subsection{The $\lambda$-conversion rules} |
|
326 | 431 |
\index{lambda calc@$\lambda$-calculus} |
104 | 432 |
\begin{ttbox} |
433 |
beta_conversion : Sign.cterm -> thm |
|
434 |
extensional : thm -> thm |
|
435 |
abstract_rule : string -> Sign.cterm -> thm -> thm |
|
436 |
combination : thm -> thm -> thm |
|
437 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 438 |
There is no rule for $\alpha$-conversion because Isabelle regards |
439 |
$\alpha$-convertible theorems as equal. |
|
440 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
|
104 | 441 |
\item[\ttindexbold{beta_conversion} $ct$] |
442 |
makes the theorem $((\lambda x.a)(b)) \equiv a[b/x]$, where $ct$ is the |
|
443 |
term $(\lambda x.a)(b)$. |
|
444 |
||
445 |
\item[\ttindexbold{extensional} $thm$] |
|
446 |
maps the premise $f(x) \equiv g(x)$ to the conclusion $f\equiv g$. |
|
447 |
Parameter~$x$ is taken from the premise. It may be an unknown or a free |
|
332 | 448 |
variable (provided it does not occur in the assumptions); it must not occur |
104 | 449 |
in $f$ or~$g$. |
450 |
||
451 |
\item[\ttindexbold{abstract_rule} $v$ $x$ $thm$] |
|
452 |
maps the premise $a\equiv b$ to the conclusion $(\lambda x.a) \equiv |
|
453 |
(\lambda x.b)$, abstracting over all occurrences (if any!) of~$x$. |
|
454 |
Parameter~$x$ is supplied as a cterm. It may be an unknown or a free |
|
332 | 455 |
variable (provided it does not occur in the assumptions). In the |
104 | 456 |
conclusion, the bound variable is named~$v$. |
457 |
||
458 |
\item[\ttindexbold{combination} $thm@1$ $thm@2$] |
|
459 |
maps the premises $f\equiv g$ and $a\equiv b$ to the conclusion~$f(a)\equiv |
|
460 |
g(b)$. |
|
326 | 461 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 462 |
|
463 |
||
326 | 464 |
\subsection{Forall introduction rules} |
465 |
\index{meta-quantifiers} |
|
104 | 466 |
\begin{ttbox} |
467 |
forall_intr : Sign.cterm -> thm -> thm |
|
468 |
forall_intr_list : Sign.cterm list -> thm -> thm |
|
469 |
forall_intr_frees : thm -> thm |
|
470 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
471 |
||
326 | 472 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 473 |
\item[\ttindexbold{forall_intr} $x$ $thm$] |
474 |
applies $({\Forall}I)$, abstracting over all occurrences (if any!) of~$x$. |
|
475 |
The rule maps the premise $\phi$ to the conclusion $\Forall x.\phi$. |
|
476 |
Parameter~$x$ is supplied as a cterm. It may be an unknown or a free |
|
332 | 477 |
variable (provided it does not occur in the assumptions). |
104 | 478 |
|
479 |
\item[\ttindexbold{forall_intr_list} $xs$ $thm$] |
|
480 |
applies $({\Forall}I)$ repeatedly, on every element of the list~$xs$. |
|
481 |
||
482 |
\item[\ttindexbold{forall_intr_frees} $thm$] |
|
483 |
applies $({\Forall}I)$ repeatedly, generalizing over all the free variables |
|
484 |
of the premise. |
|
326 | 485 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 486 |
|
487 |
||
326 | 488 |
\subsection{Forall elimination rules} |
104 | 489 |
\begin{ttbox} |
490 |
forall_elim : Sign.cterm -> thm -> thm |
|
491 |
forall_elim_list : Sign.cterm list -> thm -> thm |
|
492 |
forall_elim_var : int -> thm -> thm |
|
493 |
forall_elim_vars : int -> thm -> thm |
|
494 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
495 |
||
326 | 496 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 497 |
\item[\ttindexbold{forall_elim} $ct$ $thm$] |
498 |
applies $({\Forall}E)$, mapping the premise $\Forall x.\phi$ to the conclusion |
|
499 |
$\phi[ct/x]$. The rule checks that $ct$ and $x$ have the same type. |
|
500 |
||
501 |
\item[\ttindexbold{forall_elim_list} $cts$ $thm$] |
|
502 |
applies $({\Forall}E)$ repeatedly, on every element of the list~$cts$. |
|
503 |
||
504 |
\item[\ttindexbold{forall_elim_var} $k$ $thm$] |
|
505 |
applies $({\Forall}E)$, mapping the premise $\Forall x.\phi$ to the conclusion |
|
506 |
$\phi[\Var{x@k}/x]$. Thus, it replaces the outermost $\Forall$-bound |
|
507 |
variable by an unknown having subscript~$k$. |
|
508 |
||
509 |
\item[\ttindexbold{forall_elim_vars} $ks$ $thm$] |
|
510 |
applies {\tt forall_elim_var} repeatedly, for every element of the list~$ks$. |
|
326 | 511 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 512 |
|
326 | 513 |
\subsection{Instantiation of unknowns} |
514 |
\index{instantiation} |
|
104 | 515 |
\begin{ttbox} |
286 | 516 |
instantiate: (indexname*Sign.ctyp)list * |
517 |
(Sign.cterm*Sign.cterm)list -> thm -> thm |
|
104 | 518 |
\end{ttbox} |
326 | 519 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
520 |
\item[\ttindexbold{instantiate} ($tyinsts$, $insts$) $thm$] |
|
521 |
simultaneously substitutes types for type unknowns (the |
|
104 | 522 |
$tyinsts$) and terms for term unknowns (the $insts$). Instantiations are |
523 |
given as $(v,t)$ pairs, where $v$ is an unknown and $t$ is a term (of the |
|
524 |
same type as $v$) or a type (of the same sort as~$v$). All the unknowns |
|
525 |
must be distinct. The rule normalizes its conclusion. |
|
326 | 526 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 527 |
|
528 |
||
326 | 529 |
\subsection{Freezing/thawing type unknowns} |
530 |
\index{type unknowns!freezing/thawing of} |
|
104 | 531 |
\begin{ttbox} |
532 |
freezeT: thm -> thm |
|
533 |
varifyT: thm -> thm |
|
534 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 535 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 536 |
\item[\ttindexbold{freezeT} $thm$] |
537 |
converts all the type unknowns in $thm$ to free type variables. |
|
538 |
||
539 |
\item[\ttindexbold{varifyT} $thm$] |
|
540 |
converts all the free type variables in $thm$ to type unknowns. |
|
326 | 541 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 542 |
|
543 |
||
544 |
\section{Derived rules for goal-directed proof} |
|
545 |
Most of these rules have the sole purpose of implementing particular |
|
546 |
tactics. There are few occasions for applying them directly to a theorem. |
|
547 |
||
548 |
\subsection{Proof by assumption} |
|
326 | 549 |
\index{meta-assumptions} |
104 | 550 |
\begin{ttbox} |
551 |
assumption : int -> thm -> thm Sequence.seq |
|
552 |
eq_assumption : int -> thm -> thm |
|
553 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 554 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 555 |
\item[\ttindexbold{assumption} {\it i} $thm$] |
556 |
attempts to solve premise~$i$ of~$thm$ by assumption. |
|
557 |
||
558 |
\item[\ttindexbold{eq_assumption}] |
|
559 |
is like {\tt assumption} but does not use unification. |
|
326 | 560 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 561 |
|
562 |
||
563 |
\subsection{Resolution} |
|
326 | 564 |
\index{resolution} |
104 | 565 |
\begin{ttbox} |
566 |
biresolution : bool -> (bool*thm)list -> int -> thm |
|
567 |
-> thm Sequence.seq |
|
568 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 569 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 570 |
\item[\ttindexbold{biresolution} $match$ $rules$ $i$ $state$] |
326 | 571 |
performs bi-resolution on subgoal~$i$ of $state$, using the list of $\it |
104 | 572 |
(flag,rule)$ pairs. For each pair, it applies resolution if the flag |
573 |
is~{\tt false} and elim-resolution if the flag is~{\tt true}. If $match$ |
|
574 |
is~{\tt true}, the $state$ is not instantiated. |
|
326 | 575 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 576 |
|
577 |
||
578 |
\subsection{Composition: resolution without lifting} |
|
326 | 579 |
\index{resolution!without lifting} |
104 | 580 |
\begin{ttbox} |
581 |
compose : thm * int * thm -> thm list |
|
582 |
COMP : thm * thm -> thm |
|
583 |
bicompose : bool -> bool * thm * int -> int -> thm |
|
584 |
-> thm Sequence.seq |
|
585 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
586 |
In forward proof, a typical use of composition is to regard an assertion of |
|
587 |
the form $\phi\Imp\psi$ as atomic. Schematic variables are not renamed, so |
|
588 |
beware of clashes! |
|
326 | 589 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 590 |
\item[\ttindexbold{compose} ($thm@1$, $i$, $thm@2$)] |
591 |
uses $thm@1$, regarded as an atomic formula, to solve premise~$i$ |
|
592 |
of~$thm@2$. Let $thm@1$ and $thm@2$ be $\psi$ and $\List{\phi@1; \ldots; |
|
593 |
\phi@n} \Imp \phi$. For each $s$ that unifies~$\psi$ and $\phi@i$, the |
|
594 |
result list contains the theorem |
|
595 |
\[ (\List{\phi@1; \ldots; \phi@{i-1}; \phi@{i+1}; \ldots; \phi@n} \Imp \phi)s. |
|
596 |
\] |
|
597 |
||
1119 | 598 |
\item[$thm@1$ \ttindexbold{COMP} $thm@2$] |
104 | 599 |
calls \hbox{\tt compose ($thm@1$, 1, $thm@2$)} and returns the result, if |
326 | 600 |
unique; otherwise, it raises exception~\xdx{THM}\@. It is |
104 | 601 |
analogous to {\tt RS}\@. |
602 |
||
603 |
For example, suppose that $thm@1$ is $a=b\Imp b=a$, a symmetry rule, and |
|
332 | 604 |
that $thm@2$ is $\List{P\Imp Q; \neg Q} \Imp\neg P$, which is the |
104 | 605 |
principle of contrapositives. Then the result would be the |
606 |
derived rule $\neg(b=a)\Imp\neg(a=b)$. |
|
607 |
||
608 |
\item[\ttindexbold{bicompose} $match$ ($flag$, $rule$, $m$) $i$ $state$] |
|
609 |
refines subgoal~$i$ of $state$ using $rule$, without lifting. The $rule$ |
|
610 |
is taken to have the form $\List{\psi@1; \ldots; \psi@m} \Imp \psi$, where |
|
326 | 611 |
$\psi$ need not be atomic; thus $m$ determines the number of new |
104 | 612 |
subgoals. If $flag$ is {\tt true} then it performs elim-resolution --- it |
613 |
solves the first premise of~$rule$ by assumption and deletes that |
|
614 |
assumption. If $match$ is~{\tt true}, the $state$ is not instantiated. |
|
326 | 615 |
\end{ttdescription} |
104 | 616 |
|
617 |
||
618 |
\subsection{Other meta-rules} |
|
619 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
620 |
trivial : Sign.cterm -> thm |
|
621 |
lift_rule : (thm * int) -> thm -> thm |
|
622 |
rename_params_rule : string list * int -> thm -> thm |
|
623 |
rewrite_cterm : thm list -> Sign.cterm -> thm |
|
624 |
flexflex_rule : thm -> thm Sequence.seq |
|
625 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
326 | 626 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
104 | 627 |
\item[\ttindexbold{trivial} $ct$] |
628 |
makes the theorem \(\phi\Imp\phi\), where $\phi$ is the value of~$ct$. |
|
629 |
This is the initial state for a goal-directed proof of~$\phi$. The rule |
|
630 |
checks that $ct$ has type~$prop$. |
|
631 |
||
632 |
\item[\ttindexbold{lift_rule} ($state$, $i$) $rule$] \index{lifting} |
|
633 |
prepares $rule$ for resolution by lifting it over the parameters and |
|
634 |
assumptions of subgoal~$i$ of~$state$. |
|
635 |
||
636 |
\item[\ttindexbold{rename_params_rule} ({\it names}, {\it i}) $thm$] |
|
637 |
uses the $names$ to rename the parameters of premise~$i$ of $thm$. The |
|
638 |
names must be distinct. If there are fewer names than parameters, then the |
|
639 |
rule renames the innermost parameters and may modify the remaining ones to |
|
640 |
ensure that all the parameters are distinct. |
|
641 |
\index{parameters!renaming} |
|
642 |
||
643 |
\item[\ttindexbold{rewrite_cterm} $defs$ $ct$] |
|
644 |
transforms $ct$ to $ct'$ by repeatedly applying $defs$ as rewrite rules; it |
|
645 |
returns the conclusion~$ct\equiv ct'$. This underlies the meta-rewriting |
|
646 |
tactics and rules. |
|
326 | 647 |
\index{meta-rewriting!in terms} |
104 | 648 |
|
649 |
\item[\ttindexbold{flexflex_rule} $thm$] \index{flex-flex constraints} |
|
650 |
removes all flex-flex pairs from $thm$ using the trivial unifier. |
|
326 | 651 |
\end{ttdescription} |
1590 | 652 |
\index{meta-rules|)} |
653 |
||
654 |
||
655 |
\section{Proof objects} |
|
656 |
\index{proof objects|(} Isabelle can record the full meta-level proof of each |
|
657 |
theorem. The proof object contains all logical inferences in detail, while |
|
658 |
omitting bookkeeping steps that have no logical meaning to an outside |
|
659 |
observer. Rewriting steps are recorded in similar detail as the output of |
|
660 |
simplifier tracing. The proof object can be inspected by a separate |
|
661 |
proof-checker, or used to generate human-readable proof digests. |
|
662 |
||
663 |
Full proof objects are large. They multiply storage requirements by about |
|
664 |
seven; attempts to build large logics (such as {\sc zf} and {\sc hol}) may |
|
665 |
fail. Isabelle normally builds minimal proof objects, which include only uses |
|
666 |
of oracles. You can also request an intermediate level of detail, containing |
|
667 |
uses of oracles, axioms and theorems. These smaller proof objects indicate a |
|
668 |
theorem's dependencies. |
|
669 |
||
670 |
Isabelle provides proof objects for the sake of transparency. Their aim is to |
|
671 |
increase your confidence in Isabelle. They let you inspect proofs constructed |
|
672 |
by the classical reasoner or simplifier, and inform you of all uses of |
|
673 |
oracles. Seldom will proof objects be given whole to an automatic |
|
674 |
proof-checker: none has been written. It is up to you to examine and |
|
675 |
interpret them sensibly. For example, when scrutinizing a theorem's |
|
676 |
derivation for dependence upon some oracle or axiom, remember to scrutinize |
|
677 |
all of its lemmas. Their proofs are included in the main derivation, through |
|
678 |
the {\tt Theorem} constructor. |
|
679 |
||
680 |
Proof objects are expressed using a polymorphic type of variable-branching |
|
681 |
trees. Proof objects (formally known as {\em derivations\/}) are trees |
|
682 |
labelled by rules, where {\tt rule} is a complicated datatype declared in the |
|
683 |
file {\tt Pure/thm.ML}. |
|
684 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
685 |
datatype 'a mtree = Join of 'a * 'a mtree list; |
|
686 |
datatype rule = \(\ldots\); |
|
687 |
type deriv = rule mtree; |
|
688 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
689 |
% |
|
690 |
Each theorem's derivation is stored as the {\tt der} field of its internal |
|
691 |
record: |
|
692 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
693 |
#der (rep_thm conjI); |
|
694 |
{\out Join (Theorem ({ProtoPure, CPure, HOL},"conjI"),} |
|
695 |
{\out [Join (MinProof,[])]) : deriv} |
|
696 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
697 |
This proof object identifies a labelled theorem, {\tt conjI}, whose underlying |
|
698 |
proof has not been recorded; all we have is {\tt MinProof}. |
|
699 |
||
700 |
Nontrivial proof objects are unreadably large and complex. Isabelle provides |
|
701 |
several functions to help you inspect them informally. These functions omit |
|
702 |
the more obscure inferences and attempt to restructure the others into natural |
|
703 |
formats, linear or tree-structured. |
|
704 |
||
705 |
\begin{ttbox} |
|
706 |
keep_derivs : deriv_kind ref |
|
707 |
Deriv.size : deriv -> int |
|
708 |
Deriv.drop : 'a mtree * int -> 'a mtree |
|
709 |
Deriv.linear : deriv -> deriv list |
|
710 |
Deriv.linear : deriv -> Deriv.orule mtree |
|
711 |
\end{ttbox} |
|
712 |
||
713 |
\begin{ttdescription} |
|
714 |
\item[\ttindexbold{keep_derivs} := MinDeriv $|$ ThmDeriv $|$ FullDeriv;] |
|
715 |
specifies one of the three options for keeping derivations. They can be |
|
716 |
minimal (oracles only), include theorems and axioms, or be full. |
|
717 |
||
718 |
\item[\ttindexbold{Deriv.size} $der$] yields the size of a derivation, |
|
719 |
excluding lemmas. |
|
720 |
||
721 |
\item[\ttindexbold{Deriv.drop} ($tree$,$n$)] returns the subtree $n$ levels |
|
722 |
down, always following the first child. It is good for stripping off |
|
723 |
outer level inferences that are used to put a theorem into standard form. |
|
724 |
||
725 |
\item[\ttindexbold{Deriv.linear} $der$] converts a derivation into a linear |
|
726 |
format, replacing the deep nesting by a list of rules. Intuitively, this |
|
727 |
reveals the single-step Isabelle proof that is constructed internally by |
|
728 |
tactics. |
|
729 |
||
730 |
\item[\ttindexbold{Deriv.tree} $der$] converts a derivation into an |
|
731 |
object-level proof tree. A resolution by an object-rule is converted to a |
|
732 |
tree node labelled by that rule. Complications arise if the object-rule is |
|
733 |
itself derived in some way. Nested resolutions are unravelled, but other |
|
734 |
operations on rules (such as rewriting) are left as-is. |
|
735 |
\end{ttdescription} |
|
736 |
||
737 |
\index{proof objects|)} |
|
104 | 738 |
\index{theorems|)} |