author | wenzelm |
Thu, 21 Dec 2017 22:56:51 +0100 | |
changeset 67250 | 6c837185aa61 |
parent 67146 | 909dcdec2122 |
child 68540 | 000a0e062529 |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
61656 | 1 |
(*:maxLineLen=78:*) |
2 |
||
29755 | 3 |
theory Logic |
4 |
imports Base |
|
5 |
begin |
|
18537 | 6 |
|
58618 | 7 |
chapter \<open>Primitive logic \label{ch:logic}\<close> |
18537 | 8 |
|
58618 | 9 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 10 |
The logical foundations of Isabelle/Isar are that of the Pure logic, which |
11 |
has been introduced as a Natural Deduction framework in @{cite paulson700}. |
|
12 |
This is essentially the same logic as ``\<open>\<lambda>HOL\<close>'' in the more abstract |
|
13 |
setting of Pure Type Systems (PTS) @{cite "Barendregt-Geuvers:2001"}, |
|
14 |
although there are some key differences in the specific treatment of simple |
|
15 |
types in Isabelle/Pure. |
|
20480 | 16 |
|
61854 | 17 |
Following type-theoretic parlance, the Pure logic consists of three levels |
18 |
of \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-calculus with corresponding arrows, \<open>\<Rightarrow>\<close> for syntactic function space |
|
19 |
(terms depending on terms), \<open>\<And>\<close> for universal quantification (proofs |
|
20 |
depending on terms), and \<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close> for implication (proofs depending on proofs). |
|
20480 | 21 |
|
20537 | 22 |
Derivations are relative to a logical theory, which declares type |
61854 | 23 |
constructors, constants, and axioms. Theory declarations support schematic |
24 |
polymorphism, which is strictly speaking outside the logic.\<^footnote>\<open>This is the |
|
25 |
deeper logical reason, why the theory context \<open>\<Theta>\<close> is separate from the proof |
|
26 |
context \<open>\<Gamma>\<close> of the core calculus: type constructors, term constants, and |
|
27 |
facts (proof constants) may involve arbitrary type schemes, but the type of |
|
28 |
a locally fixed term parameter is also fixed!\<close> |
|
58618 | 29 |
\<close> |
20480 | 30 |
|
31 |
||
58618 | 32 |
section \<open>Types \label{sec:types}\<close> |
20437 | 33 |
|
58618 | 34 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 35 |
The language of types is an uninterpreted order-sorted first-order algebra; |
36 |
types are qualified by ordered type classes. |
|
20480 | 37 |
|
61416 | 38 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 39 |
A \<^emph>\<open>type class\<close> is an abstract syntactic entity declared in the theory |
40 |
context. The \<^emph>\<open>subclass relation\<close> \<open>c\<^sub>1 \<subseteq> c\<^sub>2\<close> is specified by stating an |
|
41 |
acyclic generating relation; the transitive closure is maintained |
|
42 |
internally. The resulting relation is an ordering: reflexive, transitive, |
|
43 |
and antisymmetric. |
|
20451 | 44 |
|
61854 | 45 |
A \<^emph>\<open>sort\<close> is a list of type classes written as \<open>s = {c\<^sub>1, \<dots>, c\<^sub>m}\<close>, it |
46 |
represents symbolic intersection. Notationally, the curly braces are omitted |
|
47 |
for singleton intersections, i.e.\ any class \<open>c\<close> may be read as a sort |
|
48 |
\<open>{c}\<close>. The ordering on type classes is extended to sorts according to the |
|
49 |
meaning of intersections: \<open>{c\<^sub>1, \<dots> c\<^sub>m} \<subseteq> {d\<^sub>1, \<dots>, d\<^sub>n}\<close> iff \<open>\<forall>j. \<exists>i. c\<^sub>i \<subseteq> |
|
50 |
d\<^sub>j\<close>. The empty intersection \<open>{}\<close> refers to the universal sort, which is the |
|
51 |
largest element wrt.\ the sort order. Thus \<open>{}\<close> represents the ``full |
|
52 |
sort'', not the empty one! The intersection of all (finitely many) classes |
|
53 |
declared in the current theory is the least element wrt.\ the sort ordering. |
|
20480 | 54 |
|
61416 | 55 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 56 |
A \<^emph>\<open>fixed type variable\<close> is a pair of a basic name (starting with a \<open>'\<close> |
57 |
character) and a sort constraint, e.g.\ \<open>('a, s)\<close> which is usually printed |
|
58 |
as \<open>\<alpha>\<^sub>s\<close>. A \<^emph>\<open>schematic type variable\<close> is a pair of an indexname and a sort |
|
59 |
constraint, e.g.\ \<open>(('a, 0), s)\<close> which is usually printed as \<open>?\<alpha>\<^sub>s\<close>. |
|
20451 | 60 |
|
61854 | 61 |
Note that \<^emph>\<open>all\<close> syntactic components contribute to the identity of type |
62 |
variables: basic name, index, and sort constraint. The core logic handles |
|
63 |
type variables with the same name but different sorts as different, although |
|
64 |
the type-inference layer (which is outside the core) rejects anything like |
|
65 |
that. |
|
20451 | 66 |
|
61854 | 67 |
A \<^emph>\<open>type constructor\<close> \<open>\<kappa>\<close> is a \<open>k\<close>-ary operator on types declared in the |
68 |
theory. Type constructor application is written postfix as \<open>(\<alpha>\<^sub>1, \<dots>, \<alpha>\<^sub>k)\<kappa>\<close>. |
|
69 |
For \<open>k = 0\<close> the argument tuple is omitted, e.g.\ \<open>prop\<close> instead of \<open>()prop\<close>. |
|
70 |
For \<open>k = 1\<close> the parentheses are omitted, e.g.\ \<open>\<alpha> list\<close> instead of |
|
71 |
\<open>(\<alpha>)list\<close>. Further notation is provided for specific constructors, notably |
|
72 |
the right-associative infix \<open>\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<beta>\<close> instead of \<open>(\<alpha>, \<beta>)fun\<close>. |
|
65446 | 73 |
|
61854 | 74 |
The logical category \<^emph>\<open>type\<close> is defined inductively over type variables and |
75 |
type constructors as follows: \<open>\<tau> = \<alpha>\<^sub>s | ?\<alpha>\<^sub>s | (\<tau>\<^sub>1, \<dots>, \<tau>\<^sub>k)\<kappa>\<close>. |
|
20451 | 76 |
|
61854 | 77 |
A \<^emph>\<open>type abbreviation\<close> is a syntactic definition \<open>(\<^vec>\<alpha>)\<kappa> = \<tau>\<close> of an |
78 |
arbitrary type expression \<open>\<tau>\<close> over variables \<open>\<^vec>\<alpha>\<close>. Type abbreviations |
|
79 |
appear as type constructors in the syntax, but are expanded before entering |
|
80 |
the logical core. |
|
20480 | 81 |
|
61854 | 82 |
A \<^emph>\<open>type arity\<close> declares the image behavior of a type constructor wrt.\ the |
83 |
algebra of sorts: \<open>\<kappa> :: (s\<^sub>1, \<dots>, s\<^sub>k)s\<close> means that \<open>(\<tau>\<^sub>1, \<dots>, \<tau>\<^sub>k)\<kappa>\<close> is of |
|
84 |
sort \<open>s\<close> if every argument type \<open>\<tau>\<^sub>i\<close> is of sort \<open>s\<^sub>i\<close>. Arity declarations |
|
85 |
are implicitly completed, i.e.\ \<open>\<kappa> :: (\<^vec>s)c\<close> entails \<open>\<kappa> :: |
|
61493 | 86 |
(\<^vec>s)c'\<close> for any \<open>c' \<supseteq> c\<close>. |
20491 | 87 |
|
61416 | 88 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 89 |
The sort algebra is always maintained as \<^emph>\<open>coregular\<close>, which means that type |
90 |
arities are consistent with the subclass relation: for any type constructor |
|
91 |
\<open>\<kappa>\<close>, and classes \<open>c\<^sub>1 \<subseteq> c\<^sub>2\<close>, and arities \<open>\<kappa> :: (\<^vec>s\<^sub>1)c\<^sub>1\<close> and \<open>\<kappa> :: |
|
92 |
(\<^vec>s\<^sub>2)c\<^sub>2\<close> holds \<open>\<^vec>s\<^sub>1 \<subseteq> \<^vec>s\<^sub>2\<close> component-wise. |
|
20451 | 93 |
|
20491 | 94 |
The key property of a coregular order-sorted algebra is that sort |
20537 | 95 |
constraints can be solved in a most general fashion: for each type |
61854 | 96 |
constructor \<open>\<kappa>\<close> and sort \<open>s\<close> there is a most general vector of argument |
97 |
sorts \<open>(s\<^sub>1, \<dots>, s\<^sub>k)\<close> such that a type scheme \<open>(\<alpha>\<^bsub>s\<^sub>1\<^esub>, \<dots>, \<alpha>\<^bsub>s\<^sub>k\<^esub>)\<kappa>\<close> is of |
|
98 |
sort \<open>s\<close>. Consequently, type unification has most general solutions (modulo |
|
99 |
equivalence of sorts), so type-inference produces primary types as expected |
|
100 |
@{cite "nipkow-prehofer"}. |
|
58618 | 101 |
\<close> |
20451 | 102 |
|
58618 | 103 |
text %mlref \<open> |
20480 | 104 |
\begin{mldecls} |
34921 | 105 |
@{index_ML_type class: string} \\ |
106 |
@{index_ML_type sort: "class list"} \\ |
|
107 |
@{index_ML_type arity: "string * sort list * sort"} \\ |
|
20480 | 108 |
@{index_ML_type typ} \\ |
39846 | 109 |
@{index_ML Term.map_atyps: "(typ -> typ) -> typ -> typ"} \\ |
110 |
@{index_ML Term.fold_atyps: "(typ -> 'a -> 'a) -> typ -> 'a -> 'a"} \\ |
|
20547 | 111 |
\end{mldecls} |
112 |
\begin{mldecls} |
|
20480 | 113 |
@{index_ML Sign.subsort: "theory -> sort * sort -> bool"} \\ |
114 |
@{index_ML Sign.of_sort: "theory -> typ * sort -> bool"} \\ |
|
47174 | 115 |
@{index_ML Sign.add_type: "Proof.context -> binding * int * mixfix -> theory -> theory"} \\ |
42401
9bfaf6819291
updated some theory primitives, which now depend on auxiliary context;
wenzelm
parents:
40255
diff
changeset
|
116 |
@{index_ML Sign.add_type_abbrev: "Proof.context -> |
9bfaf6819291
updated some theory primitives, which now depend on auxiliary context;
wenzelm
parents:
40255
diff
changeset
|
117 |
binding * string list * typ -> theory -> theory"} \\ |
30355 | 118 |
@{index_ML Sign.primitive_class: "binding * class list -> theory -> theory"} \\ |
20480 | 119 |
@{index_ML Sign.primitive_classrel: "class * class -> theory -> theory"} \\ |
120 |
@{index_ML Sign.primitive_arity: "arity -> theory -> theory"} \\ |
|
121 |
\end{mldecls} |
|
122 |
||
61439 | 123 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type class} represents type classes. |
20480 | 124 |
|
61854 | 125 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type sort} represents sorts, i.e.\ finite intersections of |
126 |
classes. The empty list @{ML "[]: sort"} refers to the empty class |
|
127 |
intersection, i.e.\ the ``full sort''. |
|
20451 | 128 |
|
61854 | 129 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type arity} represents type arities. A triple \<open>(\<kappa>, \<^vec>s, s) |
130 |
: arity\<close> represents \<open>\<kappa> :: (\<^vec>s)s\<close> as described above. |
|
20480 | 131 |
|
61854 | 132 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type typ} represents types; this is a datatype with constructors |
133 |
@{ML TFree}, @{ML TVar}, @{ML Type}. |
|
20480 | 134 |
|
61854 | 135 |
\<^descr> @{ML Term.map_atyps}~\<open>f \<tau>\<close> applies the mapping \<open>f\<close> to all atomic types |
136 |
(@{ML TFree}, @{ML TVar}) occurring in \<open>\<tau>\<close>. |
|
20519 | 137 |
|
61854 | 138 |
\<^descr> @{ML Term.fold_atyps}~\<open>f \<tau>\<close> iterates the operation \<open>f\<close> over all |
139 |
occurrences of atomic types (@{ML TFree}, @{ML TVar}) in \<open>\<tau>\<close>; the type |
|
140 |
structure is traversed from left to right. |
|
20494 | 141 |
|
61854 | 142 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.subsort}~\<open>thy (s\<^sub>1, s\<^sub>2)\<close> tests the subsort relation \<open>s\<^sub>1 \<subseteq> |
143 |
s\<^sub>2\<close>. |
|
20480 | 144 |
|
61854 | 145 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.of_sort}~\<open>thy (\<tau>, s)\<close> tests whether type \<open>\<tau>\<close> is of sort \<open>s\<close>. |
20480 | 146 |
|
61854 | 147 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.add_type}~\<open>ctxt (\<kappa>, k, mx)\<close> declares a new type constructors \<open>\<kappa>\<close> |
148 |
with \<open>k\<close> arguments and optional mixfix syntax. |
|
20451 | 149 |
|
61854 | 150 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.add_type_abbrev}~\<open>ctxt (\<kappa>, \<^vec>\<alpha>, \<tau>)\<close> defines a new type |
151 |
abbreviation \<open>(\<^vec>\<alpha>)\<kappa> = \<tau>\<close>. |
|
20480 | 152 |
|
61854 | 153 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.primitive_class}~\<open>(c, [c\<^sub>1, \<dots>, c\<^sub>n])\<close> declares a new class \<open>c\<close>, |
154 |
together with class relations \<open>c \<subseteq> c\<^sub>i\<close>, for \<open>i = 1, \<dots>, n\<close>. |
|
20480 | 155 |
|
61854 | 156 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.primitive_classrel}~\<open>(c\<^sub>1, c\<^sub>2)\<close> declares the class relation |
157 |
\<open>c\<^sub>1 \<subseteq> c\<^sub>2\<close>. |
|
20480 | 158 |
|
61854 | 159 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.primitive_arity}~\<open>(\<kappa>, \<^vec>s, s)\<close> declares the arity \<open>\<kappa> :: |
160 |
(\<^vec>s)s\<close>. |
|
58618 | 161 |
\<close> |
20437 | 162 |
|
58618 | 163 |
text %mlantiq \<open> |
39832 | 164 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl} |
61493 | 165 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "class"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
166 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "sort"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
167 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "type_name"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
168 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "type_abbrev"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
169 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "nonterminal"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
170 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "typ"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
39832 | 171 |
\end{matharray} |
172 |
||
55112
b1a5d603fd12
prefer rail cartouche -- avoid back-slashed quotes;
wenzelm
parents:
55029
diff
changeset
|
173 |
@{rail \<open> |
67146 | 174 |
@@{ML_antiquotation class} embedded |
39832 | 175 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
176 |
@@{ML_antiquotation sort} sort |
39832 | 177 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
178 |
(@@{ML_antiquotation type_name} | |
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
179 |
@@{ML_antiquotation type_abbrev} | |
67146 | 180 |
@@{ML_antiquotation nonterminal}) embedded |
39832 | 181 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
182 |
@@{ML_antiquotation typ} type |
55112
b1a5d603fd12
prefer rail cartouche -- avoid back-slashed quotes;
wenzelm
parents:
55029
diff
changeset
|
183 |
\<close>} |
39832 | 184 |
|
61854 | 185 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{class c}\<close> inlines the internalized class \<open>c\<close> --- as @{ML_type string} |
39832 | 186 |
literal. |
187 |
||
61854 | 188 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{sort s}\<close> inlines the internalized sort \<open>s\<close> --- as @{ML_type "string |
189 |
list"} literal. |
|
190 |
||
191 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{type_name c}\<close> inlines the internalized type constructor \<open>c\<close> --- as |
|
192 |
@{ML_type string} literal. |
|
193 |
||
194 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{type_abbrev c}\<close> inlines the internalized type abbreviation \<open>c\<close> --- as |
|
195 |
@{ML_type string} literal. |
|
196 |
||
197 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{nonterminal c}\<close> inlines the internalized syntactic type~/ grammar |
|
198 |
nonterminal \<open>c\<close> --- as @{ML_type string} literal. |
|
199 |
||
200 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{typ \<tau>}\<close> inlines the internalized type \<open>\<tau>\<close> --- as constructor term for |
|
201 |
datatype @{ML_type typ}. |
|
58618 | 202 |
\<close> |
39832 | 203 |
|
20437 | 204 |
|
58618 | 205 |
section \<open>Terms \label{sec:terms}\<close> |
18537 | 206 |
|
58618 | 207 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 208 |
The language of terms is that of simply-typed \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-calculus with de-Bruijn |
209 |
indices for bound variables (cf.\ @{cite debruijn72} or @{cite |
|
210 |
"paulson-ml2"}), with the types being determined by the corresponding |
|
211 |
binders. In contrast, free variables and constants have an explicit name and |
|
212 |
type in each occurrence. |
|
20514 | 213 |
|
61416 | 214 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 215 |
A \<^emph>\<open>bound variable\<close> is a natural number \<open>b\<close>, which accounts for the number |
216 |
of intermediate binders between the variable occurrence in the body and its |
|
217 |
binding position. For example, the de-Bruijn term \<open>\<lambda>\<^bsub>bool\<^esub>. \<lambda>\<^bsub>bool\<^esub>. 1 \<and> 0\<close> |
|
218 |
would correspond to \<open>\<lambda>x\<^bsub>bool\<^esub>. \<lambda>y\<^bsub>bool\<^esub>. x \<and> y\<close> in a named representation. |
|
219 |
Note that a bound variable may be represented by different de-Bruijn indices |
|
220 |
at different occurrences, depending on the nesting of abstractions. |
|
20537 | 221 |
|
61854 | 222 |
A \<^emph>\<open>loose variable\<close> is a bound variable that is outside the scope of local |
223 |
binders. The types (and names) for loose variables can be managed as a |
|
224 |
separate context, that is maintained as a stack of hypothetical binders. The |
|
225 |
core logic operates on closed terms, without any loose variables. |
|
20514 | 226 |
|
61854 | 227 |
A \<^emph>\<open>fixed variable\<close> is a pair of a basic name and a type, e.g.\ \<open>(x, \<tau>)\<close> |
228 |
which is usually printed \<open>x\<^sub>\<tau>\<close> here. A \<^emph>\<open>schematic variable\<close> is a pair of an |
|
229 |
indexname and a type, e.g.\ \<open>((x, 0), \<tau>)\<close> which is likewise printed as |
|
230 |
\<open>?x\<^sub>\<tau>\<close>. |
|
20491 | 231 |
|
61416 | 232 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 233 |
A \<^emph>\<open>constant\<close> is a pair of a basic name and a type, e.g.\ \<open>(c, \<tau>)\<close> which is |
234 |
usually printed as \<open>c\<^sub>\<tau>\<close> here. Constants are declared in the context as |
|
235 |
polymorphic families \<open>c :: \<sigma>\<close>, meaning that all substitution instances \<open>c\<^sub>\<tau>\<close> |
|
236 |
for \<open>\<tau> = \<sigma>\<vartheta>\<close> are valid. |
|
20514 | 237 |
|
61854 | 238 |
The vector of \<^emph>\<open>type arguments\<close> of constant \<open>c\<^sub>\<tau>\<close> wrt.\ the declaration \<open>c |
239 |
:: \<sigma>\<close> is defined as the codomain of the matcher \<open>\<vartheta> = {?\<alpha>\<^sub>1 \<mapsto> \<tau>\<^sub>1, |
|
240 |
\<dots>, ?\<alpha>\<^sub>n \<mapsto> \<tau>\<^sub>n}\<close> presented in canonical order \<open>(\<tau>\<^sub>1, \<dots>, \<tau>\<^sub>n)\<close>, corresponding |
|
241 |
to the left-to-right occurrences of the \<open>\<alpha>\<^sub>i\<close> in \<open>\<sigma>\<close>. Within a given theory |
|
242 |
context, there is a one-to-one correspondence between any constant \<open>c\<^sub>\<tau>\<close> and |
|
243 |
the application \<open>c(\<tau>\<^sub>1, \<dots>, \<tau>\<^sub>n)\<close> of its type arguments. For example, with |
|
244 |
\<open>plus :: \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha>\<close>, the instance \<open>plus\<^bsub>nat \<Rightarrow> nat \<Rightarrow> nat\<^esub>\<close> corresponds to |
|
61493 | 245 |
\<open>plus(nat)\<close>. |
20480 | 246 |
|
61854 | 247 |
Constant declarations \<open>c :: \<sigma>\<close> may contain sort constraints for type |
248 |
variables in \<open>\<sigma>\<close>. These are observed by type-inference as expected, but |
|
249 |
\<^emph>\<open>ignored\<close> by the core logic. This means the primitive logic is able to |
|
250 |
reason with instances of polymorphic constants that the user-level |
|
251 |
type-checker would reject due to violation of type class restrictions. |
|
20480 | 252 |
|
61416 | 253 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 254 |
An \<^emph>\<open>atomic term\<close> is either a variable or constant. The logical category |
255 |
\<^emph>\<open>term\<close> is defined inductively over atomic terms, with abstraction and |
|
256 |
application as follows: \<open>t = b | x\<^sub>\<tau> | ?x\<^sub>\<tau> | c\<^sub>\<tau> | \<lambda>\<^sub>\<tau>. t | t\<^sub>1 t\<^sub>2\<close>. |
|
257 |
Parsing and printing takes care of converting between an external |
|
258 |
representation with named bound variables. Subsequently, we shall use the |
|
259 |
latter notation instead of internal de-Bruijn representation. |
|
20498 | 260 |
|
61854 | 261 |
The inductive relation \<open>t :: \<tau>\<close> assigns a (unique) type to a term according |
262 |
to the structure of atomic terms, abstractions, and applications: |
|
20498 | 263 |
\[ |
61493 | 264 |
\infer{\<open>a\<^sub>\<tau> :: \<tau>\<close>}{} |
20498 | 265 |
\qquad |
61493 | 266 |
\infer{\<open>(\<lambda>x\<^sub>\<tau>. t) :: \<tau> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>\<close>}{\<open>t :: \<sigma>\<close>} |
20501 | 267 |
\qquad |
61493 | 268 |
\infer{\<open>t u :: \<sigma>\<close>}{\<open>t :: \<tau> \<Rightarrow> \<sigma>\<close> & \<open>u :: \<tau>\<close>} |
20498 | 269 |
\] |
61477 | 270 |
A \<^emph>\<open>well-typed term\<close> is a term that can be typed according to these rules. |
20498 | 271 |
|
61854 | 272 |
Typing information can be omitted: type-inference is able to reconstruct the |
273 |
most general type of a raw term, while assigning most general types to all |
|
274 |
of its variables and constants. Type-inference depends on a context of type |
|
275 |
constraints for fixed variables, and declarations for polymorphic constants. |
|
20514 | 276 |
|
20537 | 277 |
The identity of atomic terms consists both of the name and the type |
61854 | 278 |
component. This means that different variables \<open>x\<^bsub>\<tau>\<^sub>1\<^esub>\<close> and \<open>x\<^bsub>\<tau>\<^sub>2\<^esub>\<close> may |
279 |
become the same after type instantiation. Type-inference rejects variables |
|
280 |
of the same name, but different types. In contrast, mixed instances of |
|
34929 | 281 |
polymorphic constants occur routinely. |
20514 | 282 |
|
61416 | 283 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 284 |
The \<^emph>\<open>hidden polymorphism\<close> of a term \<open>t :: \<sigma>\<close> is the set of type variables |
285 |
occurring in \<open>t\<close>, but not in its type \<open>\<sigma>\<close>. This means that the term |
|
286 |
implicitly depends on type arguments that are not accounted in the result |
|
287 |
type, i.e.\ there are different type instances \<open>t\<vartheta> :: \<sigma>\<close> and |
|
288 |
\<open>t\<vartheta>' :: \<sigma>\<close> with the same type. This slightly pathological |
|
289 |
situation notoriously demands additional care. |
|
20514 | 290 |
|
61416 | 291 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 292 |
A \<^emph>\<open>term abbreviation\<close> is a syntactic definition \<open>c\<^sub>\<sigma> \<equiv> t\<close> of a closed term |
293 |
\<open>t\<close> of type \<open>\<sigma>\<close>, without any hidden polymorphism. A term abbreviation looks |
|
294 |
like a constant in the syntax, but is expanded before entering the logical |
|
295 |
core. Abbreviations are usually reverted when printing terms, using \<open>t \<rightarrow> |
|
296 |
c\<^sub>\<sigma>\<close> as rules for higher-order rewriting. |
|
20519 | 297 |
|
61416 | 298 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 299 |
Canonical operations on \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-terms include \<open>\<alpha>\<beta>\<eta>\<close>-conversion: \<open>\<alpha>\<close>-conversion |
300 |
refers to capture-free renaming of bound variables; \<open>\<beta>\<close>-conversion contracts |
|
301 |
an abstraction applied to an argument term, substituting the argument in the |
|
302 |
body: \<open>(\<lambda>x. b)a\<close> becomes \<open>b[a/x]\<close>; \<open>\<eta>\<close>-conversion contracts vacuous |
|
303 |
application-abstraction: \<open>\<lambda>x. f x\<close> becomes \<open>f\<close>, provided that the bound |
|
304 |
variable does not occur in \<open>f\<close>. |
|
20519 | 305 |
|
61854 | 306 |
Terms are normally treated modulo \<open>\<alpha>\<close>-conversion, which is implicit in the |
307 |
de-Bruijn representation. Names for bound variables in abstractions are |
|
308 |
maintained separately as (meaningless) comments, mostly for parsing and |
|
309 |
printing. Full \<open>\<alpha>\<beta>\<eta>\<close>-conversion is commonplace in various standard |
|
310 |
operations (\secref{sec:obj-rules}) that are based on higher-order |
|
311 |
unification and matching. |
|
58618 | 312 |
\<close> |
18537 | 313 |
|
58618 | 314 |
text %mlref \<open> |
20514 | 315 |
\begin{mldecls} |
316 |
@{index_ML_type term} \\ |
|
46262 | 317 |
@{index_ML_op "aconv": "term * term -> bool"} \\ |
39846 | 318 |
@{index_ML Term.map_types: "(typ -> typ) -> term -> term"} \\ |
319 |
@{index_ML Term.fold_types: "(typ -> 'a -> 'a) -> term -> 'a -> 'a"} \\ |
|
320 |
@{index_ML Term.map_aterms: "(term -> term) -> term -> term"} \\ |
|
321 |
@{index_ML Term.fold_aterms: "(term -> 'a -> 'a) -> term -> 'a -> 'a"} \\ |
|
20547 | 322 |
\end{mldecls} |
323 |
\begin{mldecls} |
|
20514 | 324 |
@{index_ML fastype_of: "term -> typ"} \\ |
20519 | 325 |
@{index_ML lambda: "term -> term -> term"} \\ |
326 |
@{index_ML betapply: "term * term -> term"} \\ |
|
42934 | 327 |
@{index_ML incr_boundvars: "int -> term -> term"} \\ |
42401
9bfaf6819291
updated some theory primitives, which now depend on auxiliary context;
wenzelm
parents:
40255
diff
changeset
|
328 |
@{index_ML Sign.declare_const: "Proof.context -> |
9bfaf6819291
updated some theory primitives, which now depend on auxiliary context;
wenzelm
parents:
40255
diff
changeset
|
329 |
(binding * typ) * mixfix -> theory -> term * theory"} \\ |
33174 | 330 |
@{index_ML Sign.add_abbrev: "string -> binding * term -> |
24972
acafb18a47dc
replaced Sign.add_consts_i by Sign.declare_const;
wenzelm
parents:
24828
diff
changeset
|
331 |
theory -> (term * term) * theory"} \\ |
20519 | 332 |
@{index_ML Sign.const_typargs: "theory -> string * typ -> typ list"} \\ |
333 |
@{index_ML Sign.const_instance: "theory -> string * typ list -> typ"} \\ |
|
20514 | 334 |
\end{mldecls} |
18537 | 335 |
|
61854 | 336 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type term} represents de-Bruijn terms, with comments in |
337 |
abstractions, and explicitly named free variables and constants; this is a |
|
338 |
datatype with constructors @{index_ML Bound}, @{index_ML Free}, @{index_ML |
|
339 |
Var}, @{index_ML Const}, @{index_ML Abs}, @{index_ML_op "$"}. |
|
20519 | 340 |
|
61854 | 341 |
\<^descr> \<open>t\<close>~@{ML_text aconv}~\<open>u\<close> checks \<open>\<alpha>\<close>-equivalence of two terms. This is the |
342 |
basic equality relation on type @{ML_type term}; raw datatype equality |
|
343 |
should only be used for operations related to parsing or printing! |
|
20537 | 344 |
|
61854 | 345 |
\<^descr> @{ML Term.map_types}~\<open>f t\<close> applies the mapping \<open>f\<close> to all types occurring |
346 |
in \<open>t\<close>. |
|
347 |
||
348 |
\<^descr> @{ML Term.fold_types}~\<open>f t\<close> iterates the operation \<open>f\<close> over all |
|
349 |
occurrences of types in \<open>t\<close>; the term structure is traversed from left to |
|
350 |
right. |
|
20519 | 351 |
|
61854 | 352 |
\<^descr> @{ML Term.map_aterms}~\<open>f t\<close> applies the mapping \<open>f\<close> to all atomic terms |
353 |
(@{ML Bound}, @{ML Free}, @{ML Var}, @{ML Const}) occurring in \<open>t\<close>. |
|
20537 | 354 |
|
61854 | 355 |
\<^descr> @{ML Term.fold_aterms}~\<open>f t\<close> iterates the operation \<open>f\<close> over all |
356 |
occurrences of atomic terms (@{ML Bound}, @{ML Free}, @{ML Var}, @{ML |
|
357 |
Const}) in \<open>t\<close>; the term structure is traversed from left to right. |
|
20519 | 358 |
|
61854 | 359 |
\<^descr> @{ML fastype_of}~\<open>t\<close> determines the type of a well-typed term. This |
360 |
operation is relatively slow, despite the omission of any sanity checks. |
|
20519 | 361 |
|
61854 | 362 |
\<^descr> @{ML lambda}~\<open>a b\<close> produces an abstraction \<open>\<lambda>a. b\<close>, where occurrences of |
363 |
the atomic term \<open>a\<close> in the body \<open>b\<close> are replaced by bound variables. |
|
20519 | 364 |
|
61854 | 365 |
\<^descr> @{ML betapply}~\<open>(t, u)\<close> produces an application \<open>t u\<close>, with topmost |
366 |
\<open>\<beta>\<close>-conversion if \<open>t\<close> is an abstraction. |
|
20519 | 367 |
|
61854 | 368 |
\<^descr> @{ML incr_boundvars}~\<open>j\<close> increments a term's dangling bound variables by |
369 |
the offset \<open>j\<close>. This is required when moving a subterm into a context where |
|
370 |
it is enclosed by a different number of abstractions. Bound variables with a |
|
371 |
matching abstraction are unaffected. |
|
42934 | 372 |
|
61854 | 373 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.declare_const}~\<open>ctxt ((c, \<sigma>), mx)\<close> declares a new constant \<open>c :: |
374 |
\<sigma>\<close> with optional mixfix syntax. |
|
20519 | 375 |
|
61854 | 376 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.add_abbrev}~\<open>print_mode (c, t)\<close> introduces a new term |
377 |
abbreviation \<open>c \<equiv> t\<close>. |
|
20519 | 378 |
|
61854 | 379 |
\<^descr> @{ML Sign.const_typargs}~\<open>thy (c, \<tau>)\<close> and @{ML Sign.const_instance}~\<open>thy |
380 |
(c, [\<tau>\<^sub>1, \<dots>, \<tau>\<^sub>n])\<close> convert between two representations of polymorphic |
|
381 |
constants: full type instance vs.\ compact type arguments form. |
|
58618 | 382 |
\<close> |
18537 | 383 |
|
58618 | 384 |
text %mlantiq \<open> |
39832 | 385 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl} |
61493 | 386 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "const_name"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
387 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "const_abbrev"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
388 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "const"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
389 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "term"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
390 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "prop"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
39832 | 391 |
\end{matharray} |
392 |
||
55112
b1a5d603fd12
prefer rail cartouche -- avoid back-slashed quotes;
wenzelm
parents:
55029
diff
changeset
|
393 |
@{rail \<open> |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
394 |
(@@{ML_antiquotation const_name} | |
67146 | 395 |
@@{ML_antiquotation const_abbrev}) embedded |
39832 | 396 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
397 |
@@{ML_antiquotation const} ('(' (type + ',') ')')? |
39832 | 398 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
399 |
@@{ML_antiquotation term} term |
39832 | 400 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
401 |
@@{ML_antiquotation prop} prop |
55112
b1a5d603fd12
prefer rail cartouche -- avoid back-slashed quotes;
wenzelm
parents:
55029
diff
changeset
|
402 |
\<close>} |
39832 | 403 |
|
61854 | 404 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{const_name c}\<close> inlines the internalized logical constant name \<open>c\<close> --- |
405 |
as @{ML_type string} literal. |
|
406 |
||
407 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{const_abbrev c}\<close> inlines the internalized abbreviated constant name \<open>c\<close> |
|
408 |
--- as @{ML_type string} literal. |
|
39832 | 409 |
|
61854 | 410 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{const c(\<^vec>\<tau>)}\<close> inlines the internalized constant \<open>c\<close> with precise |
411 |
type instantiation in the sense of @{ML Sign.const_instance} --- as @{ML |
|
412 |
Const} constructor term for datatype @{ML_type term}. |
|
39832 | 413 |
|
61854 | 414 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{term t}\<close> inlines the internalized term \<open>t\<close> --- as constructor term for |
39832 | 415 |
datatype @{ML_type term}. |
416 |
||
61854 | 417 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{prop \<phi>}\<close> inlines the internalized proposition \<open>\<phi>\<close> --- as constructor |
418 |
term for datatype @{ML_type term}. |
|
58618 | 419 |
\<close> |
39832 | 420 |
|
18537 | 421 |
|
58618 | 422 |
section \<open>Theorems \label{sec:thms}\<close> |
18537 | 423 |
|
58618 | 424 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 425 |
A \<^emph>\<open>proposition\<close> is a well-typed term of type \<open>prop\<close>, a \<^emph>\<open>theorem\<close> is a |
426 |
proven proposition (depending on a context of hypotheses and the background |
|
427 |
theory). Primitive inferences include plain Natural Deduction rules for the |
|
428 |
primary connectives \<open>\<And>\<close> and \<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close> of the framework. There is also a builtin |
|
61493 | 429 |
notion of equality/equivalence \<open>\<equiv>\<close>. |
58618 | 430 |
\<close> |
20521 | 431 |
|
29758 | 432 |
|
58618 | 433 |
subsection \<open>Primitive connectives and rules \label{sec:prim-rules}\<close> |
18537 | 434 |
|
58618 | 435 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 436 |
The theory \<open>Pure\<close> contains constant declarations for the primitive |
437 |
connectives \<open>\<And>\<close>, \<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close>, and \<open>\<equiv>\<close> of the logical framework, see |
|
438 |
\figref{fig:pure-connectives}. The derivability judgment \<open>A\<^sub>1, \<dots>, A\<^sub>n \<turnstile> B\<close> |
|
439 |
is defined inductively by the primitive inferences given in |
|
440 |
\figref{fig:prim-rules}, with the global restriction that the hypotheses |
|
441 |
must \<^emph>\<open>not\<close> contain any schematic variables. The builtin equality is |
|
442 |
conceptually axiomatized as shown in \figref{fig:pure-equality}, although |
|
443 |
the implementation works directly with derived inferences. |
|
20521 | 444 |
|
445 |
\begin{figure}[htb] |
|
446 |
\begin{center} |
|
20501 | 447 |
\begin{tabular}{ll} |
61493 | 448 |
\<open>all :: (\<alpha> \<Rightarrow> prop) \<Rightarrow> prop\<close> & universal quantification (binder \<open>\<And>\<close>) \\ |
449 |
\<open>\<Longrightarrow> :: prop \<Rightarrow> prop \<Rightarrow> prop\<close> & implication (right associative infix) \\ |
|
450 |
\<open>\<equiv> :: \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> prop\<close> & equality relation (infix) \\ |
|
20501 | 451 |
\end{tabular} |
20537 | 452 |
\caption{Primitive connectives of Pure}\label{fig:pure-connectives} |
20521 | 453 |
\end{center} |
454 |
\end{figure} |
|
18537 | 455 |
|
20501 | 456 |
\begin{figure}[htb] |
457 |
\begin{center} |
|
20498 | 458 |
\[ |
61493 | 459 |
\infer[\<open>(axiom)\<close>]{\<open>\<turnstile> A\<close>}{\<open>A \<in> \<Theta>\<close>} |
20498 | 460 |
\qquad |
61493 | 461 |
\infer[\<open>(assume)\<close>]{\<open>A \<turnstile> A\<close>}{} |
20498 | 462 |
\] |
463 |
\[ |
|
61493 | 464 |
\infer[\<open>(\<And>\<hyphen>intro)\<close>]{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<And>x. B[x]\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[x]\<close> & \<open>x \<notin> \<Gamma>\<close>} |
20498 | 465 |
\qquad |
61493 | 466 |
\infer[\<open>(\<And>\<hyphen>elim)\<close>]{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[a]\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<And>x. B[x]\<close>} |
20498 | 467 |
\] |
468 |
\[ |
|
61493 | 469 |
\infer[\<open>(\<Longrightarrow>\<hyphen>intro)\<close>]{\<open>\<Gamma> - A \<turnstile> A \<Longrightarrow> B\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B\<close>} |
20498 | 470 |
\qquad |
61493 | 471 |
\infer[\<open>(\<Longrightarrow>\<hyphen>elim)\<close>]{\<open>\<Gamma>\<^sub>1 \<union> \<Gamma>\<^sub>2 \<turnstile> B\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma>\<^sub>1 \<turnstile> A \<Longrightarrow> B\<close> & \<open>\<Gamma>\<^sub>2 \<turnstile> A\<close>} |
20498 | 472 |
\] |
20521 | 473 |
\caption{Primitive inferences of Pure}\label{fig:prim-rules} |
474 |
\end{center} |
|
475 |
\end{figure} |
|
476 |
||
477 |
\begin{figure}[htb] |
|
478 |
\begin{center} |
|
479 |
\begin{tabular}{ll} |
|
61493 | 480 |
\<open>\<turnstile> (\<lambda>x. b[x]) a \<equiv> b[a]\<close> & \<open>\<beta>\<close>-conversion \\ |
481 |
\<open>\<turnstile> x \<equiv> x\<close> & reflexivity \\ |
|
482 |
\<open>\<turnstile> x \<equiv> y \<Longrightarrow> P x \<Longrightarrow> P y\<close> & substitution \\ |
|
483 |
\<open>\<turnstile> (\<And>x. f x \<equiv> g x) \<Longrightarrow> f \<equiv> g\<close> & extensionality \\ |
|
484 |
\<open>\<turnstile> (A \<Longrightarrow> B) \<Longrightarrow> (B \<Longrightarrow> A) \<Longrightarrow> A \<equiv> B\<close> & logical equivalence \\ |
|
20521 | 485 |
\end{tabular} |
20542 | 486 |
\caption{Conceptual axiomatization of Pure equality}\label{fig:pure-equality} |
20501 | 487 |
\end{center} |
488 |
\end{figure} |
|
18537 | 489 |
|
61854 | 490 |
The introduction and elimination rules for \<open>\<And>\<close> and \<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close> are analogous to |
491 |
formation of dependently typed \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-terms representing the underlying proof |
|
492 |
objects. Proof terms are irrelevant in the Pure logic, though; they cannot |
|
493 |
occur within propositions. The system provides a runtime option to record |
|
52408 | 494 |
explicit proof terms for primitive inferences, see also |
61854 | 495 |
\secref{sec:proof-terms}. Thus all three levels of \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-calculus become |
496 |
explicit: \<open>\<Rightarrow>\<close> for terms, and \<open>\<And>/\<Longrightarrow>\<close> for proofs (cf.\ @{cite |
|
497 |
"Berghofer-Nipkow:2000:TPHOL"}). |
|
20491 | 498 |
|
61854 | 499 |
Observe that locally fixed parameters (as in \<open>\<And>\<hyphen>intro\<close>) need not be recorded |
500 |
in the hypotheses, because the simple syntactic types of Pure are always |
|
501 |
inhabitable. ``Assumptions'' \<open>x :: \<tau>\<close> for type-membership are only present |
|
502 |
as long as some \<open>x\<^sub>\<tau>\<close> occurs in the statement body.\<^footnote>\<open>This is the key |
|
503 |
difference to ``\<open>\<lambda>HOL\<close>'' in the PTS framework @{cite |
|
504 |
"Barendregt-Geuvers:2001"}, where hypotheses \<open>x : A\<close> are treated uniformly |
|
505 |
for propositions and types.\<close> |
|
20501 | 506 |
|
61416 | 507 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 508 |
The axiomatization of a theory is implicitly closed by forming all instances |
509 |
of type and term variables: \<open>\<turnstile> A\<vartheta>\<close> holds for any substitution |
|
510 |
instance of an axiom \<open>\<turnstile> A\<close>. By pushing substitutions through derivations |
|
511 |
inductively, we also get admissible \<open>generalize\<close> and \<open>instantiate\<close> rules as |
|
512 |
shown in \figref{fig:subst-rules}. |
|
20501 | 513 |
|
514 |
\begin{figure}[htb] |
|
515 |
\begin{center} |
|
20498 | 516 |
\[ |
61493 | 517 |
\infer{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[?\<alpha>]\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[\<alpha>]\<close> & \<open>\<alpha> \<notin> \<Gamma>\<close>} |
20501 | 518 |
\quad |
61493 | 519 |
\infer[\quad\<open>(generalize)\<close>]{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[?x]\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[x]\<close> & \<open>x \<notin> \<Gamma>\<close>} |
20498 | 520 |
\] |
521 |
\[ |
|
61493 | 522 |
\infer{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[\<tau>]\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[?\<alpha>]\<close>} |
20501 | 523 |
\quad |
61493 | 524 |
\infer[\quad\<open>(instantiate)\<close>]{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[t]\<close>}{\<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B[?x]\<close>} |
20498 | 525 |
\] |
20501 | 526 |
\caption{Admissible substitution rules}\label{fig:subst-rules} |
527 |
\end{center} |
|
528 |
\end{figure} |
|
18537 | 529 |
|
61854 | 530 |
Note that \<open>instantiate\<close> does not require an explicit side-condition, because |
531 |
\<open>\<Gamma>\<close> may never contain schematic variables. |
|
20537 | 532 |
|
61854 | 533 |
In principle, variables could be substituted in hypotheses as well, but this |
534 |
would disrupt the monotonicity of reasoning: deriving \<open>\<Gamma>\<vartheta> \<turnstile> |
|
535 |
B\<vartheta>\<close> from \<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> B\<close> is correct, but \<open>\<Gamma>\<vartheta> \<supseteq> \<Gamma>\<close> does not |
|
536 |
necessarily hold: the result belongs to a different proof context. |
|
20542 | 537 |
|
61416 | 538 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 539 |
An \<^emph>\<open>oracle\<close> is a function that produces axioms on the fly. Logically, this |
540 |
is an instance of the \<open>axiom\<close> rule (\figref{fig:prim-rules}), but there is |
|
541 |
an operational difference. The system always records oracle invocations |
|
542 |
within derivations of theorems by a unique tag. |
|
20542 | 543 |
|
61854 | 544 |
Axiomatizations should be limited to the bare minimum, typically as part of |
545 |
the initial logical basis of an object-logic formalization. Later on, |
|
546 |
theories are usually developed in a strictly definitional fashion, by |
|
547 |
stating only certain equalities over new constants. |
|
20542 | 548 |
|
61854 | 549 |
A \<^emph>\<open>simple definition\<close> consists of a constant declaration \<open>c :: \<sigma>\<close> together |
550 |
with an axiom \<open>\<turnstile> c \<equiv> t\<close>, where \<open>t :: \<sigma>\<close> is a closed term without any hidden |
|
551 |
polymorphism. The RHS may depend on further defined constants, but not \<open>c\<close> |
|
552 |
itself. Definitions of functions may be presented as \<open>c \<^vec>x \<equiv> t\<close> |
|
553 |
instead of the puristic \<open>c \<equiv> \<lambda>\<^vec>x. t\<close>. |
|
20542 | 554 |
|
61854 | 555 |
An \<^emph>\<open>overloaded definition\<close> consists of a collection of axioms for the same |
556 |
constant, with zero or one equations \<open>c((\<^vec>\<alpha>)\<kappa>) \<equiv> t\<close> for each type |
|
557 |
constructor \<open>\<kappa>\<close> (for distinct variables \<open>\<^vec>\<alpha>\<close>). The RHS may mention |
|
558 |
previously defined constants as above, or arbitrary constants \<open>d(\<alpha>\<^sub>i)\<close> for |
|
559 |
some \<open>\<alpha>\<^sub>i\<close> projected from \<open>\<^vec>\<alpha>\<close>. Thus overloaded definitions |
|
560 |
essentially work by primitive recursion over the syntactic structure of a |
|
561 |
single type argument. See also @{cite \<open>\S4.3\<close> |
|
562 |
"Haftmann-Wenzel:2006:classes"}. |
|
58618 | 563 |
\<close> |
20498 | 564 |
|
58618 | 565 |
text %mlref \<open> |
20521 | 566 |
\begin{mldecls} |
46253 | 567 |
@{index_ML Logic.all: "term -> term -> term"} \\ |
568 |
@{index_ML Logic.mk_implies: "term * term -> term"} \\ |
|
569 |
\end{mldecls} |
|
570 |
\begin{mldecls} |
|
20521 | 571 |
@{index_ML_type ctyp} \\ |
572 |
@{index_ML_type cterm} \\ |
|
59621
291934bac95e
Thm.cterm_of and Thm.ctyp_of operate on local context;
wenzelm
parents:
58728
diff
changeset
|
573 |
@{index_ML Thm.ctyp_of: "Proof.context -> typ -> ctyp"} \\ |
291934bac95e
Thm.cterm_of and Thm.ctyp_of operate on local context;
wenzelm
parents:
58728
diff
changeset
|
574 |
@{index_ML Thm.cterm_of: "Proof.context -> term -> cterm"} \\ |
46497
89ccf66aa73d
renamed Thm.capply to Thm.apply, and Thm.cabs to Thm.lambda in conformance with similar operations in structure Term and Logic;
wenzelm
parents:
46262
diff
changeset
|
575 |
@{index_ML Thm.apply: "cterm -> cterm -> cterm"} \\ |
89ccf66aa73d
renamed Thm.capply to Thm.apply, and Thm.cabs to Thm.lambda in conformance with similar operations in structure Term and Logic;
wenzelm
parents:
46262
diff
changeset
|
576 |
@{index_ML Thm.lambda: "cterm -> cterm -> cterm"} \\ |
60938 | 577 |
@{index_ML Thm.all: "Proof.context -> cterm -> cterm -> cterm"} \\ |
46253 | 578 |
@{index_ML Drule.mk_implies: "cterm * cterm -> cterm"} \\ |
20547 | 579 |
\end{mldecls} |
580 |
\begin{mldecls} |
|
20521 | 581 |
@{index_ML_type thm} \\ |
50126
3dec88149176
theorem status about oracles/futures is no longer printed by default;
wenzelm
parents:
48985
diff
changeset
|
582 |
@{index_ML Thm.peek_status: "thm -> {oracle: bool, unfinished: bool, failed: bool}"} \\ |
42933 | 583 |
@{index_ML Thm.transfer: "theory -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
20542 | 584 |
@{index_ML Thm.assume: "cterm -> thm"} \\ |
585 |
@{index_ML Thm.forall_intr: "cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
586 |
@{index_ML Thm.forall_elim: "cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
587 |
@{index_ML Thm.implies_intr: "cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
588 |
@{index_ML Thm.implies_elim: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
589 |
@{index_ML Thm.generalize: "string list * string list -> int -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
60642
48dd1cefb4ae
simplified Thm.instantiate and derivatives: the LHS refers to non-certified variables -- this merely serves as index into already certified structures (or is ignored);
wenzelm
parents:
59902
diff
changeset
|
590 |
@{index_ML Thm.instantiate: "((indexname * sort) * ctyp) list * ((indexname * typ) * cterm) list |
48dd1cefb4ae
simplified Thm.instantiate and derivatives: the LHS refers to non-certified variables -- this merely serves as index into already certified structures (or is ignored);
wenzelm
parents:
59902
diff
changeset
|
591 |
-> thm -> thm"} \\ |
42401
9bfaf6819291
updated some theory primitives, which now depend on auxiliary context;
wenzelm
parents:
40255
diff
changeset
|
592 |
@{index_ML Thm.add_axiom: "Proof.context -> |
9bfaf6819291
updated some theory primitives, which now depend on auxiliary context;
wenzelm
parents:
40255
diff
changeset
|
593 |
binding * term -> theory -> (string * thm) * theory"} \\ |
39821 | 594 |
@{index_ML Thm.add_oracle: "binding * ('a -> cterm) -> theory -> |
595 |
(string * ('a -> thm)) * theory"} \\ |
|
61261
ddb2da7cb2e4
more explicit Defs.context: use proper name spaces as far as possible;
wenzelm
parents:
61255
diff
changeset
|
596 |
@{index_ML Thm.add_def: "Defs.context -> bool -> bool -> |
42401
9bfaf6819291
updated some theory primitives, which now depend on auxiliary context;
wenzelm
parents:
40255
diff
changeset
|
597 |
binding * term -> theory -> (string * thm) * theory"} \\ |
20547 | 598 |
\end{mldecls} |
599 |
\begin{mldecls} |
|
61261
ddb2da7cb2e4
more explicit Defs.context: use proper name spaces as far as possible;
wenzelm
parents:
61255
diff
changeset
|
600 |
@{index_ML Theory.add_deps: "Defs.context -> string -> |
61255
15865e0c5598
eliminated separate type Theory.dep: use typeargs uniformly for consts/types;
wenzelm
parents:
61246
diff
changeset
|
601 |
Defs.entry -> Defs.entry list -> theory -> theory"} \\ |
20521 | 602 |
\end{mldecls} |
603 |
||
61854 | 604 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.peek_status}~\<open>thm\<close> informs about the current status of the |
605 |
derivation object behind the given theorem. This is a snapshot of a |
|
606 |
potentially ongoing (parallel) evaluation of proofs. The three Boolean |
|
607 |
values indicate the following: \<^verbatim>\<open>oracle\<close> if the finished part contains some |
|
608 |
oracle invocation; \<^verbatim>\<open>unfinished\<close> if some future proofs are still pending; |
|
609 |
\<^verbatim>\<open>failed\<close> if some future proof has failed, rendering the theorem invalid! |
|
50126
3dec88149176
theorem status about oracles/futures is no longer printed by default;
wenzelm
parents:
48985
diff
changeset
|
610 |
|
61854 | 611 |
\<^descr> @{ML Logic.all}~\<open>a B\<close> produces a Pure quantification \<open>\<And>a. B\<close>, where |
612 |
occurrences of the atomic term \<open>a\<close> in the body proposition \<open>B\<close> are replaced |
|
613 |
by bound variables. (See also @{ML lambda} on terms.) |
|
46253 | 614 |
|
61854 | 615 |
\<^descr> @{ML Logic.mk_implies}~\<open>(A, B)\<close> produces a Pure implication \<open>A \<Longrightarrow> B\<close>. |
46253 | 616 |
|
61854 | 617 |
\<^descr> Types @{ML_type ctyp} and @{ML_type cterm} represent certified types and |
618 |
terms, respectively. These are abstract datatypes that guarantee that its |
|
619 |
values have passed the full well-formedness (and well-typedness) checks, |
|
620 |
relative to the declarations of type constructors, constants etc.\ in the |
|
621 |
background theory. The abstract types @{ML_type ctyp} and @{ML_type cterm} |
|
622 |
are part of the same inference kernel that is mainly responsible for |
|
623 |
@{ML_type thm}. Thus syntactic operations on @{ML_type ctyp} and @{ML_type |
|
624 |
cterm} are located in the @{ML_structure Thm} module, even though theorems |
|
625 |
are not yet involved at that stage. |
|
20542 | 626 |
|
61854 | 627 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.ctyp_of}~\<open>ctxt \<tau>\<close> and @{ML Thm.cterm_of}~\<open>ctxt t\<close> explicitly |
628 |
check types and terms, respectively. This also involves some basic |
|
629 |
normalizations, such expansion of type and term abbreviations from the |
|
630 |
underlying theory context. Full re-certification is relatively slow and |
|
631 |
should be avoided in tight reasoning loops. |
|
20547 | 632 |
|
61854 | 633 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.apply}, @{ML Thm.lambda}, @{ML Thm.all}, @{ML Drule.mk_implies} |
634 |
etc.\ compose certified terms (or propositions) incrementally. This is |
|
635 |
equivalent to @{ML Thm.cterm_of} after unchecked @{ML_op "$"}, @{ML lambda}, |
|
636 |
@{ML Logic.all}, @{ML Logic.mk_implies} etc., but there can be a big |
|
637 |
difference in performance when large existing entities are composed by a few |
|
638 |
extra constructions on top. There are separate operations to decompose |
|
46253 | 639 |
certified terms and theorems to produce certified terms again. |
20542 | 640 |
|
61854 | 641 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type thm} represents proven propositions. This is an abstract |
642 |
datatype that guarantees that its values have been constructed by basic |
|
643 |
principles of the @{ML_structure Thm} module. Every @{ML_type thm} value |
|
644 |
refers its background theory, cf.\ \secref{sec:context-theory}. |
|
20542 | 645 |
|
61854 | 646 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.transfer}~\<open>thy thm\<close> transfers the given theorem to a \<^emph>\<open>larger\<close> |
647 |
theory, see also \secref{sec:context}. This formal adjustment of the |
|
648 |
background context has no logical significance, but is occasionally required |
|
649 |
for formal reasons, e.g.\ when theorems that are imported from more basic |
|
650 |
theories are used in the current situation. |
|
42933 | 651 |
|
61854 | 652 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.assume}, @{ML Thm.forall_intr}, @{ML Thm.forall_elim}, @{ML |
653 |
Thm.implies_intr}, and @{ML Thm.implies_elim} correspond to the primitive |
|
654 |
inferences of \figref{fig:prim-rules}. |
|
20542 | 655 |
|
61854 | 656 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.generalize}~\<open>(\<^vec>\<alpha>, \<^vec>x)\<close> corresponds to the |
657 |
\<open>generalize\<close> rules of \figref{fig:subst-rules}. Here collections of type and |
|
658 |
term variables are generalized simultaneously, specified by the given basic |
|
659 |
names. |
|
20521 | 660 |
|
61854 | 661 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.instantiate}~\<open>(\<^vec>\<alpha>\<^sub>s, \<^vec>x\<^sub>\<tau>)\<close> corresponds to the |
662 |
\<open>instantiate\<close> rules of \figref{fig:subst-rules}. Type variables are |
|
663 |
substituted before term variables. Note that the types in \<open>\<^vec>x\<^sub>\<tau>\<close> refer |
|
664 |
to the instantiated versions. |
|
20542 | 665 |
|
61854 | 666 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.add_axiom}~\<open>ctxt (name, A)\<close> declares an arbitrary proposition as |
667 |
axiom, and retrieves it as a theorem from the resulting theory, cf.\ \<open>axiom\<close> |
|
668 |
in \figref{fig:prim-rules}. Note that the low-level representation in the |
|
669 |
axiom table may differ slightly from the returned theorem. |
|
20542 | 670 |
|
61854 | 671 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.add_oracle}~\<open>(binding, oracle)\<close> produces a named oracle rule, |
672 |
essentially generating arbitrary axioms on the fly, cf.\ \<open>axiom\<close> in |
|
673 |
\figref{fig:prim-rules}. |
|
20521 | 674 |
|
61854 | 675 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.add_def}~\<open>ctxt unchecked overloaded (name, c \<^vec>x \<equiv> t)\<close> |
676 |
states a definitional axiom for an existing constant \<open>c\<close>. Dependencies are |
|
677 |
recorded via @{ML Theory.add_deps}, unless the \<open>unchecked\<close> option is set. |
|
678 |
Note that the low-level representation in the axiom table may differ |
|
679 |
slightly from the returned theorem. |
|
20542 | 680 |
|
61854 | 681 |
\<^descr> @{ML Theory.add_deps}~\<open>ctxt name c\<^sub>\<tau> \<^vec>d\<^sub>\<sigma>\<close> declares dependencies of |
682 |
a named specification for constant \<open>c\<^sub>\<tau>\<close>, relative to existing |
|
683 |
specifications for constants \<open>\<^vec>d\<^sub>\<sigma>\<close>. This also works for type |
|
684 |
constructors. |
|
58618 | 685 |
\<close> |
20521 | 686 |
|
58618 | 687 |
text %mlantiq \<open> |
39832 | 688 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl} |
61493 | 689 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "ctyp"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
690 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "cterm"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
691 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "cprop"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
692 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "thm"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
693 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "thms"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
694 |
@{ML_antiquotation_def "lemma"} & : & \<open>ML_antiquotation\<close> \\ |
|
39832 | 695 |
\end{matharray} |
696 |
||
55112
b1a5d603fd12
prefer rail cartouche -- avoid back-slashed quotes;
wenzelm
parents:
55029
diff
changeset
|
697 |
@{rail \<open> |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
698 |
@@{ML_antiquotation ctyp} typ |
39832 | 699 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
700 |
@@{ML_antiquotation cterm} term |
39832 | 701 |
; |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
702 |
@@{ML_antiquotation cprop} prop |
39832 | 703 |
; |
62969 | 704 |
@@{ML_antiquotation thm} thm |
42510
b9c106763325
use @{rail} antiquotation (with some nested markup);
wenzelm
parents:
42401
diff
changeset
|
705 |
; |
62969 | 706 |
@@{ML_antiquotation thms} thms |
39832 | 707 |
; |
55029
61a6bf7d4b02
clarified @{rail} syntax: prefer explicit \<newline> symbol;
wenzelm
parents:
54883
diff
changeset
|
708 |
@@{ML_antiquotation lemma} ('(' @'open' ')')? ((prop +) + @'and') \<newline> |
42517
b68e1c27709a
simplified keyword markup (without formal checking);
wenzelm
parents:
42510
diff
changeset
|
709 |
@'by' method method? |
55112
b1a5d603fd12
prefer rail cartouche -- avoid back-slashed quotes;
wenzelm
parents:
55029
diff
changeset
|
710 |
\<close>} |
39832 | 711 |
|
61854 | 712 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{ctyp \<tau>}\<close> produces a certified type wrt.\ the current background theory |
713 |
--- as abstract value of type @{ML_type ctyp}. |
|
714 |
||
715 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{cterm t}\<close> and \<open>@{cprop \<phi>}\<close> produce a certified term wrt.\ the current |
|
716 |
background theory --- as abstract value of type @{ML_type cterm}. |
|
39832 | 717 |
|
61854 | 718 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{thm a}\<close> produces a singleton fact --- as abstract value of type |
719 |
@{ML_type thm}. |
|
39832 | 720 |
|
61854 | 721 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{thms a}\<close> produces a general fact --- as abstract value of type |
722 |
@{ML_type "thm list"}. |
|
39832 | 723 |
|
61854 | 724 |
\<^descr> \<open>@{lemma \<phi> by meth}\<close> produces a fact that is proven on the spot according |
725 |
to the minimal proof, which imitates a terminal Isar proof. The result is an |
|
726 |
abstract value of type @{ML_type thm} or @{ML_type "thm list"}, depending on |
|
727 |
the number of propositions given here. |
|
39832 | 728 |
|
61854 | 729 |
The internal derivation object lacks a proper theorem name, but it is |
730 |
formally closed, unless the \<open>(open)\<close> option is specified (this may impact |
|
731 |
performance of applications with proof terms). |
|
39832 | 732 |
|
61854 | 733 |
Since ML antiquotations are always evaluated at compile-time, there is no |
734 |
run-time overhead even for non-trivial proofs. Nonetheless, the |
|
735 |
justification is syntactically limited to a single @{command "by"} step. |
|
736 |
More complex Isar proofs should be done in regular theory source, before |
|
737 |
compiling the corresponding ML text that uses the result. |
|
58618 | 738 |
\<close> |
39832 | 739 |
|
740 |
||
58618 | 741 |
subsection \<open>Auxiliary connectives \label{sec:logic-aux}\<close> |
20521 | 742 |
|
61854 | 743 |
text \<open> |
744 |
Theory \<open>Pure\<close> provides a few auxiliary connectives that are defined on top |
|
745 |
of the primitive ones, see \figref{fig:pure-aux}. These special constants |
|
746 |
are useful in certain internal encodings, and are normally not directly |
|
747 |
exposed to the user. |
|
20501 | 748 |
|
749 |
\begin{figure}[htb] |
|
750 |
\begin{center} |
|
20498 | 751 |
\begin{tabular}{ll} |
61493 | 752 |
\<open>conjunction :: prop \<Rightarrow> prop \<Rightarrow> prop\<close> & (infix \<open>&&&\<close>) \\ |
753 |
\<open>\<turnstile> A &&& B \<equiv> (\<And>C. (A \<Longrightarrow> B \<Longrightarrow> C) \<Longrightarrow> C)\<close> \\[1ex] |
|
754 |
\<open>prop :: prop \<Rightarrow> prop\<close> & (prefix \<open>#\<close>, suppressed) \\ |
|
755 |
\<open>#A \<equiv> A\<close> \\[1ex] |
|
756 |
\<open>term :: \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> prop\<close> & (prefix \<open>TERM\<close>) \\ |
|
757 |
\<open>term x \<equiv> (\<And>A. A \<Longrightarrow> A)\<close> \\[1ex] |
|
758 |
\<open>type :: \<alpha> itself\<close> & (prefix \<open>TYPE\<close>) \\ |
|
759 |
\<open>(unspecified)\<close> \\ |
|
20498 | 760 |
\end{tabular} |
20521 | 761 |
\caption{Definitions of auxiliary connectives}\label{fig:pure-aux} |
20501 | 762 |
\end{center} |
763 |
\end{figure} |
|
764 |
||
61854 | 765 |
The introduction \<open>A \<Longrightarrow> B \<Longrightarrow> A &&& B\<close>, and eliminations (projections) \<open>A &&& B |
766 |
\<Longrightarrow> A\<close> and \<open>A &&& B \<Longrightarrow> B\<close> are available as derived rules. Conjunction allows to |
|
767 |
treat simultaneous assumptions and conclusions uniformly, e.g.\ consider \<open>A |
|
768 |
\<Longrightarrow> B \<Longrightarrow> C &&& D\<close>. In particular, the goal mechanism represents multiple claims |
|
769 |
as explicit conjunction internally, but this is refined (via backwards |
|
770 |
introduction) into separate sub-goals before the user commences the proof; |
|
771 |
the final result is projected into a list of theorems using eliminations |
|
772 |
(cf.\ \secref{sec:tactical-goals}). |
|
20498 | 773 |
|
61854 | 774 |
The \<open>prop\<close> marker (\<open>#\<close>) makes arbitrarily complex propositions appear as |
775 |
atomic, without changing the meaning: \<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> A\<close> and \<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> #A\<close> are |
|
776 |
interchangeable. See \secref{sec:tactical-goals} for specific operations. |
|
20521 | 777 |
|
61854 | 778 |
The \<open>term\<close> marker turns any well-typed term into a derivable proposition: \<open>\<turnstile> |
779 |
TERM t\<close> holds unconditionally. Although this is logically vacuous, it allows |
|
780 |
to treat terms and proofs uniformly, similar to a type-theoretic framework. |
|
20498 | 781 |
|
61854 | 782 |
The \<open>TYPE\<close> constructor is the canonical representative of the unspecified |
783 |
type \<open>\<alpha> itself\<close>; it essentially injects the language of types into that of |
|
784 |
terms. There is specific notation \<open>TYPE(\<tau>)\<close> for \<open>TYPE\<^bsub>\<tau> itself\<^esub>\<close>. Although |
|
785 |
being devoid of any particular meaning, the term \<open>TYPE(\<tau>)\<close> accounts for the |
|
786 |
type \<open>\<tau>\<close> within the term language. In particular, \<open>TYPE(\<alpha>)\<close> may be used as |
|
787 |
formal argument in primitive definitions, in order to circumvent hidden |
|
788 |
polymorphism (cf.\ \secref{sec:terms}). For example, \<open>c TYPE(\<alpha>) \<equiv> A[\<alpha>]\<close> |
|
789 |
defines \<open>c :: \<alpha> itself \<Rightarrow> prop\<close> in terms of a proposition \<open>A\<close> that depends on |
|
790 |
an additional type argument, which is essentially a predicate on types. |
|
58618 | 791 |
\<close> |
20501 | 792 |
|
58618 | 793 |
text %mlref \<open> |
20521 | 794 |
\begin{mldecls} |
795 |
@{index_ML Conjunction.intr: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
796 |
@{index_ML Conjunction.elim: "thm -> thm * thm"} \\ |
|
797 |
@{index_ML Drule.mk_term: "cterm -> thm"} \\ |
|
798 |
@{index_ML Drule.dest_term: "thm -> cterm"} \\ |
|
799 |
@{index_ML Logic.mk_type: "typ -> term"} \\ |
|
800 |
@{index_ML Logic.dest_type: "term -> typ"} \\ |
|
801 |
\end{mldecls} |
|
802 |
||
61493 | 803 |
\<^descr> @{ML Conjunction.intr} derives \<open>A &&& B\<close> from \<open>A\<close> and \<open>B\<close>. |
20542 | 804 |
|
61854 | 805 |
\<^descr> @{ML Conjunction.elim} derives \<open>A\<close> and \<open>B\<close> from \<open>A &&& B\<close>. |
20542 | 806 |
|
61493 | 807 |
\<^descr> @{ML Drule.mk_term} derives \<open>TERM t\<close>. |
20542 | 808 |
|
61493 | 809 |
\<^descr> @{ML Drule.dest_term} recovers term \<open>t\<close> from \<open>TERM t\<close>. |
20542 | 810 |
|
61493 | 811 |
\<^descr> @{ML Logic.mk_type}~\<open>\<tau>\<close> produces the term \<open>TYPE(\<tau>)\<close>. |
20542 | 812 |
|
61854 | 813 |
\<^descr> @{ML Logic.dest_type}~\<open>TYPE(\<tau>)\<close> recovers the type \<open>\<tau>\<close>. |
58618 | 814 |
\<close> |
18537 | 815 |
|
20480 | 816 |
|
58618 | 817 |
subsection \<open>Sort hypotheses\<close> |
52406 | 818 |
|
61854 | 819 |
text \<open> |
820 |
Type variables are decorated with sorts, as explained in \secref{sec:types}. |
|
821 |
This constrains type instantiation to certain ranges of types: variable |
|
822 |
\<open>\<alpha>\<^sub>s\<close> may only be assigned to types \<open>\<tau>\<close> that belong to sort \<open>s\<close>. Within the |
|
823 |
logic, sort constraints act like implicit preconditions on the result \<open>\<lparr>\<alpha>\<^sub>1 |
|
824 |
: s\<^sub>1\<rparr>, \<dots>, \<lparr>\<alpha>\<^sub>n : s\<^sub>n\<rparr>, \<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<phi>\<close> where the type variables \<open>\<alpha>\<^sub>1, \<dots>, \<alpha>\<^sub>n\<close> cover |
|
825 |
the propositions \<open>\<Gamma>\<close>, \<open>\<phi>\<close>, as well as the proof of \<open>\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<phi>\<close>. |
|
52406 | 826 |
|
61854 | 827 |
These \<^emph>\<open>sort hypothesis\<close> of a theorem are passed monotonically through |
828 |
further derivations. They are redundant, as long as the statement of a |
|
829 |
theorem still contains the type variables that are accounted here. The |
|
830 |
logical significance of sort hypotheses is limited to the boundary case |
|
831 |
where type variables disappear from the proposition, e.g.\ \<open>\<lparr>\<alpha>\<^sub>s : s\<rparr> \<turnstile> \<phi>\<close>. |
|
832 |
Since such dangling type variables can be renamed arbitrarily without |
|
833 |
changing the proposition \<open>\<phi>\<close>, the inference kernel maintains sort hypotheses |
|
834 |
in anonymous form \<open>s \<turnstile> \<phi>\<close>. |
|
52406 | 835 |
|
61854 | 836 |
In most practical situations, such extra sort hypotheses may be stripped in |
837 |
a final bookkeeping step, e.g.\ at the end of a proof: they are typically |
|
838 |
left over from intermediate reasoning with type classes that can be |
|
839 |
satisfied by some concrete type \<open>\<tau>\<close> of sort \<open>s\<close> to replace the hypothetical |
|
840 |
type variable \<open>\<alpha>\<^sub>s\<close>. |
|
841 |
\<close> |
|
52406 | 842 |
|
58618 | 843 |
text %mlref \<open> |
52406 | 844 |
\begin{mldecls} |
845 |
@{index_ML Thm.extra_shyps: "thm -> sort list"} \\ |
|
846 |
@{index_ML Thm.strip_shyps: "thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
847 |
\end{mldecls} |
|
848 |
||
61854 | 849 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.extra_shyps}~\<open>thm\<close> determines the extraneous sort hypotheses of |
850 |
the given theorem, i.e.\ the sorts that are not present within type |
|
851 |
variables of the statement. |
|
52406 | 852 |
|
61854 | 853 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.strip_shyps}~\<open>thm\<close> removes any extraneous sort hypotheses that |
854 |
can be witnessed from the type signature. |
|
58618 | 855 |
\<close> |
52406 | 856 |
|
61854 | 857 |
text %mlex \<open> |
858 |
The following artificial example demonstrates the derivation of @{prop |
|
859 |
False} with a pending sort hypothesis involving a logically empty sort. |
|
860 |
\<close> |
|
52406 | 861 |
|
862 |
class empty = |
|
863 |
assumes bad: "\<And>(x::'a) y. x \<noteq> y" |
|
864 |
||
865 |
theorem (in empty) false: False |
|
866 |
using bad by blast |
|
867 |
||
59902 | 868 |
ML_val \<open>@{assert} (Thm.extra_shyps @{thm false} = [@{sort empty}])\<close> |
52406 | 869 |
|
61854 | 870 |
text \<open> |
871 |
Thanks to the inference kernel managing sort hypothesis according to their |
|
872 |
logical significance, this example is merely an instance of \<^emph>\<open>ex falso |
|
873 |
quodlibet consequitur\<close> --- not a collapse of the logical framework! |
|
874 |
\<close> |
|
52406 | 875 |
|
876 |
||
58618 | 877 |
section \<open>Object-level rules \label{sec:obj-rules}\<close> |
18537 | 878 |
|
58618 | 879 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 880 |
The primitive inferences covered so far mostly serve foundational purposes. |
881 |
User-level reasoning usually works via object-level rules that are |
|
882 |
represented as theorems of Pure. Composition of rules involves |
|
883 |
\<^emph>\<open>backchaining\<close>, \<^emph>\<open>higher-order unification\<close> modulo \<open>\<alpha>\<beta>\<eta>\<close>-conversion of |
|
884 |
\<open>\<lambda>\<close>-terms, and so-called \<^emph>\<open>lifting\<close> of rules into a context of \<open>\<And>\<close> and \<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close> |
|
885 |
connectives. Thus the full power of higher-order Natural Deduction in |
|
886 |
Isabelle/Pure becomes readily available. |
|
58618 | 887 |
\<close> |
20491 | 888 |
|
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
889 |
|
58618 | 890 |
subsection \<open>Hereditary Harrop Formulae\<close> |
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
891 |
|
58618 | 892 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 893 |
The idea of object-level rules is to model Natural Deduction inferences in |
894 |
the style of Gentzen @{cite "Gentzen:1935"}, but we allow arbitrary nesting |
|
895 |
similar to @{cite extensions91}. The most basic rule format is that of a |
|
896 |
\<^emph>\<open>Horn Clause\<close>: |
|
29768 | 897 |
\[ |
61493 | 898 |
\infer{\<open>A\<close>}{\<open>A\<^sub>1\<close> & \<open>\<dots>\<close> & \<open>A\<^sub>n\<close>} |
29768 | 899 |
\] |
61854 | 900 |
where \<open>A, A\<^sub>1, \<dots>, A\<^sub>n\<close> are atomic propositions of the framework, usually of |
901 |
the form \<open>Trueprop B\<close>, where \<open>B\<close> is a (compound) object-level statement. |
|
902 |
This object-level inference corresponds to an iterated implication in Pure |
|
903 |
like this: |
|
29768 | 904 |
\[ |
61493 | 905 |
\<open>A\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> A\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> A\<close> |
29768 | 906 |
\] |
61854 | 907 |
As an example consider conjunction introduction: \<open>A \<Longrightarrow> B \<Longrightarrow> A \<and> B\<close>. Any |
908 |
parameters occurring in such rule statements are conceptionally treated as |
|
909 |
arbitrary: |
|
29768 | 910 |
\[ |
61493 | 911 |
\<open>\<And>x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m. A\<^sub>1 x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> A\<^sub>n x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m \<Longrightarrow> A x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m\<close> |
29768 | 912 |
\] |
20491 | 913 |
|
61854 | 914 |
Nesting of rules means that the positions of \<open>A\<^sub>i\<close> may again hold compound |
915 |
rules, not just atomic propositions. Propositions of this format are called |
|
916 |
\<^emph>\<open>Hereditary Harrop Formulae\<close> in the literature @{cite "Miller:1991"}. Here |
|
917 |
we give an inductive characterization as follows: |
|
29768 | 918 |
|
61416 | 919 |
\<^medskip> |
29768 | 920 |
\begin{tabular}{ll} |
61493 | 921 |
\<open>\<^bold>x\<close> & set of variables \\ |
922 |
\<open>\<^bold>A\<close> & set of atomic propositions \\ |
|
923 |
\<open>\<^bold>H = \<And>\<^bold>x\<^sup>*. \<^bold>H\<^sup>* \<Longrightarrow> \<^bold>A\<close> & set of Hereditary Harrop Formulas \\ |
|
29768 | 924 |
\end{tabular} |
61416 | 925 |
\<^medskip> |
29768 | 926 |
|
61854 | 927 |
Thus we essentially impose nesting levels on propositions formed from \<open>\<And>\<close> |
928 |
and \<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close>. At each level there is a prefix of parameters and compound |
|
929 |
premises, concluding an atomic proposition. Typical examples are |
|
930 |
\<open>\<longrightarrow>\<close>-introduction \<open>(A \<Longrightarrow> B) \<Longrightarrow> A \<longrightarrow> B\<close> or mathematical induction \<open>P 0 \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>n. P n |
|
931 |
\<Longrightarrow> P (Suc n)) \<Longrightarrow> P n\<close>. Even deeper nesting occurs in well-founded induction |
|
932 |
\<open>(\<And>x. (\<And>y. y \<prec> x \<Longrightarrow> P y) \<Longrightarrow> P x) \<Longrightarrow> P x\<close>, but this already marks the limit of |
|
933 |
rule complexity that is usually seen in practice. |
|
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
934 |
|
61416 | 935 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 936 |
Regular user-level inferences in Isabelle/Pure always maintain the following |
937 |
canonical form of results: |
|
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
938 |
|
61854 | 939 |
\<^item> Normalization by \<open>(A \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x. B x)) \<equiv> (\<And>x. A \<Longrightarrow> B x)\<close>, which is a theorem of |
940 |
Pure, means that quantifiers are pushed in front of implication at each |
|
941 |
level of nesting. The normal form is a Hereditary Harrop Formula. |
|
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
942 |
|
61854 | 943 |
\<^item> The outermost prefix of parameters is represented via schematic variables: |
944 |
instead of \<open>\<And>\<^vec>x. \<^vec>H \<^vec>x \<Longrightarrow> A \<^vec>x\<close> we have \<open>\<^vec>H |
|
945 |
?\<^vec>x \<Longrightarrow> A ?\<^vec>x\<close>. Note that this representation looses information |
|
946 |
about the order of parameters, and vacuous quantifiers vanish automatically. |
|
58618 | 947 |
\<close> |
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
948 |
|
58618 | 949 |
text %mlref \<open> |
29771 | 950 |
\begin{mldecls} |
54883
dd04a8b654fc
proper context for norm_hhf and derived operations;
wenzelm
parents:
53200
diff
changeset
|
951 |
@{index_ML Simplifier.norm_hhf: "Proof.context -> thm -> thm"} \\ |
29771 | 952 |
\end{mldecls} |
953 |
||
61854 | 954 |
\<^descr> @{ML Simplifier.norm_hhf}~\<open>ctxt thm\<close> normalizes the given theorem |
955 |
according to the canonical form specified above. This is occasionally |
|
956 |
helpful to repair some low-level tools that do not handle Hereditary Harrop |
|
957 |
Formulae properly. |
|
58618 | 958 |
\<close> |
29771 | 959 |
|
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
960 |
|
58618 | 961 |
subsection \<open>Rule composition\<close> |
29769
03634a9e91ae
improved section on "Hereditary Harrop Formulae";
wenzelm
parents:
29768
diff
changeset
|
962 |
|
58618 | 963 |
text \<open> |
61854 | 964 |
The rule calculus of Isabelle/Pure provides two main inferences: @{inference |
965 |
resolution} (i.e.\ back-chaining of rules) and @{inference assumption} |
|
966 |
(i.e.\ closing a branch), both modulo higher-order unification. There are |
|
967 |
also combined variants, notably @{inference elim_resolution} and @{inference |
|
968 |
dest_resolution}. |
|
20491 | 969 |
|
61854 | 970 |
To understand the all-important @{inference resolution} principle, we first |
971 |
consider raw @{inference_def composition} (modulo higher-order unification |
|
972 |
with substitution \<open>\<vartheta>\<close>): |
|
20498 | 973 |
\[ |
61493 | 974 |
\infer[(@{inference_def composition})]{\<open>\<^vec>A\<vartheta> \<Longrightarrow> C\<vartheta>\<close>} |
975 |
{\<open>\<^vec>A \<Longrightarrow> B\<close> & \<open>B' \<Longrightarrow> C\<close> & \<open>B\<vartheta> = B'\<vartheta>\<close>} |
|
20498 | 976 |
\] |
61854 | 977 |
Here the conclusion of the first rule is unified with the premise of the |
978 |
second; the resulting rule instance inherits the premises of the first and |
|
979 |
conclusion of the second. Note that \<open>C\<close> can again consist of iterated |
|
980 |
implications. We can also permute the premises of the second rule |
|
981 |
back-and-forth in order to compose with \<open>B'\<close> in any position (subsequently |
|
982 |
we shall always refer to position 1 w.l.o.g.). |
|
20498 | 983 |
|
61854 | 984 |
In @{inference composition} the internal structure of the common part \<open>B\<close> |
985 |
and \<open>B'\<close> is not taken into account. For proper @{inference resolution} we |
|
986 |
require \<open>B\<close> to be atomic, and explicitly observe the structure \<open>\<And>\<^vec>x. |
|
987 |
\<^vec>H \<^vec>x \<Longrightarrow> B' \<^vec>x\<close> of the premise of the second rule. The idea |
|
988 |
is to adapt the first rule by ``lifting'' it into this context, by means of |
|
989 |
iterated application of the following inferences: |
|
20498 | 990 |
\[ |
61493 | 991 |
\infer[(@{inference_def imp_lift})]{\<open>(\<^vec>H \<Longrightarrow> \<^vec>A) \<Longrightarrow> (\<^vec>H \<Longrightarrow> B)\<close>}{\<open>\<^vec>A \<Longrightarrow> B\<close>} |
20498 | 992 |
\] |
993 |
\[ |
|
61493 | 994 |
\infer[(@{inference_def all_lift})]{\<open>(\<And>\<^vec>x. \<^vec>A (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x)) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>\<^vec>x. B (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x))\<close>}{\<open>\<^vec>A ?\<^vec>a \<Longrightarrow> B ?\<^vec>a\<close>} |
20498 | 995 |
\] |
29771 | 996 |
By combining raw composition with lifting, we get full @{inference |
997 |
resolution} as follows: |
|
20498 | 998 |
\[ |
29771 | 999 |
\infer[(@{inference_def resolution})] |
61493 | 1000 |
{\<open>(\<And>\<^vec>x. \<^vec>H \<^vec>x \<Longrightarrow> \<^vec>A (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x))\<vartheta> \<Longrightarrow> C\<vartheta>\<close>} |
20498 | 1001 |
{\begin{tabular}{l} |
61493 | 1002 |
\<open>\<^vec>A ?\<^vec>a \<Longrightarrow> B ?\<^vec>a\<close> \\ |
1003 |
\<open>(\<And>\<^vec>x. \<^vec>H \<^vec>x \<Longrightarrow> B' \<^vec>x) \<Longrightarrow> C\<close> \\ |
|
1004 |
\<open>(\<lambda>\<^vec>x. B (?\<^vec>a \<^vec>x))\<vartheta> = B'\<vartheta>\<close> \\ |
|
20498 | 1005 |
\end{tabular}} |
1006 |
\] |
|
1007 |
||
61854 | 1008 |
Continued resolution of rules allows to back-chain a problem towards more |
1009 |
and sub-problems. Branches are closed either by resolving with a rule of 0 |
|
1010 |
premises, or by producing a ``short-circuit'' within a solved situation |
|
1011 |
(again modulo unification): |
|
29771 | 1012 |
\[ |
61493 | 1013 |
\infer[(@{inference_def assumption})]{\<open>C\<vartheta>\<close>} |
61962
9c8fc56032e3
eliminated obscure macro that is in conflict with amsmath.sty;
wenzelm
parents:
61854
diff
changeset
|
1014 |
{\<open>(\<And>\<^vec>x. \<^vec>H \<^vec>x \<Longrightarrow> A \<^vec>x) \<Longrightarrow> C\<close> & \<open>A\<vartheta> = H\<^sub>i\<vartheta>\<close>~~\mbox{(for some~\<open>i\<close>)}} |
29771 | 1015 |
\] |
20498 | 1016 |
|
52422 | 1017 |
%FIXME @{inference_def elim_resolution}, @{inference_def dest_resolution} |
58618 | 1018 |
\<close> |
18537 | 1019 |
|
58618 | 1020 |
text %mlref \<open> |
29768 | 1021 |
\begin{mldecls} |
46262 | 1022 |
@{index_ML_op "RSN": "thm * (int * thm) -> thm"} \\ |
1023 |
@{index_ML_op "RS": "thm * thm -> thm"} \\ |
|
46256 | 1024 |
|
46262 | 1025 |
@{index_ML_op "RLN": "thm list * (int * thm list) -> thm list"} \\ |
1026 |
@{index_ML_op "RL": "thm list * thm list -> thm list"} \\ |
|
46256 | 1027 |
|
46262 | 1028 |
@{index_ML_op "MRS": "thm list * thm -> thm"} \\ |
1029 |
@{index_ML_op "OF": "thm * thm list -> thm"} \\ |
|
29768 | 1030 |
\end{mldecls} |
1031 |
||
61854 | 1032 |
\<^descr> \<open>rule\<^sub>1 RSN (i, rule\<^sub>2)\<close> resolves the conclusion of \<open>rule\<^sub>1\<close> with the |
1033 |
\<open>i\<close>-th premise of \<open>rule\<^sub>2\<close>, according to the @{inference resolution} |
|
1034 |
principle explained above. Unless there is precisely one resolvent it raises |
|
1035 |
exception @{ML THM}. |
|
46256 | 1036 |
|
61854 | 1037 |
This corresponds to the rule attribute @{attribute THEN} in Isar source |
1038 |
language. |
|
46256 | 1039 |
|
61854 | 1040 |
\<^descr> \<open>rule\<^sub>1 RS rule\<^sub>2\<close> abbreviates \<open>rule\<^sub>1 RSN (1, rule\<^sub>2)\<close>. |
29768 | 1041 |
|
61854 | 1042 |
\<^descr> \<open>rules\<^sub>1 RLN (i, rules\<^sub>2)\<close> joins lists of rules. For every \<open>rule\<^sub>1\<close> in |
1043 |
\<open>rules\<^sub>1\<close> and \<open>rule\<^sub>2\<close> in \<open>rules\<^sub>2\<close>, it resolves the conclusion of \<open>rule\<^sub>1\<close> |
|
1044 |
with the \<open>i\<close>-th premise of \<open>rule\<^sub>2\<close>, accumulating multiple results in one |
|
1045 |
big list. Note that such strict enumerations of higher-order unifications |
|
1046 |
can be inefficient compared to the lazy variant seen in elementary tactics |
|
1047 |
like @{ML resolve_tac}. |
|
46256 | 1048 |
|
61854 | 1049 |
\<^descr> \<open>rules\<^sub>1 RL rules\<^sub>2\<close> abbreviates \<open>rules\<^sub>1 RLN (1, rules\<^sub>2)\<close>. |
46256 | 1050 |
|
61854 | 1051 |
\<^descr> \<open>[rule\<^sub>1, \<dots>, rule\<^sub>n] MRS rule\<close> resolves \<open>rule\<^sub>i\<close> against premise \<open>i\<close> of |
1052 |
\<open>rule\<close>, for \<open>i = n, \<dots>, 1\<close>. By working from right to left, newly emerging |
|
1053 |
premises are concatenated in the result, without interfering. |
|
46256 | 1054 |
|
61854 | 1055 |
\<^descr> \<open>rule OF rules\<close> is an alternative notation for \<open>rules MRS rule\<close>, which |
1056 |
makes rule composition look more like function application. Note that the |
|
1057 |
argument \<open>rules\<close> need not be atomic. |
|
46256 | 1058 |
|
61854 | 1059 |
This corresponds to the rule attribute @{attribute OF} in Isar source |
1060 |
language. |
|
58618 | 1061 |
\<close> |
30272 | 1062 |
|
52407 | 1063 |
|
58618 | 1064 |
section \<open>Proof terms \label{sec:proof-terms}\<close> |
52407 | 1065 |
|
61854 | 1066 |
text \<open> |
1067 |
The Isabelle/Pure inference kernel can record the proof of each theorem as a |
|
1068 |
proof term that contains all logical inferences in detail. Rule composition |
|
1069 |
by resolution (\secref{sec:obj-rules}) and type-class reasoning is broken |
|
1070 |
down to primitive rules of the logical framework. The proof term can be |
|
1071 |
inspected by a separate proof-checker, for example. |
|
52407 | 1072 |
|
61854 | 1073 |
According to the well-known \<^emph>\<open>Curry-Howard isomorphism\<close>, a proof can be |
1074 |
viewed as a \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-term. Following this idea, proofs in Isabelle are internally |
|
1075 |
represented by a datatype similar to the one for terms described in |
|
1076 |
\secref{sec:terms}. On top of these syntactic terms, two more layers of |
|
1077 |
\<open>\<lambda>\<close>-calculus are added, which correspond to \<open>\<And>x :: \<alpha>. B x\<close> and \<open>A \<Longrightarrow> B\<close> |
|
1078 |
according to the propositions-as-types principle. The resulting 3-level |
|
1079 |
\<open>\<lambda>\<close>-calculus resembles ``\<open>\<lambda>HOL\<close>'' in the more abstract setting of Pure Type |
|
1080 |
Systems (PTS) @{cite "Barendregt-Geuvers:2001"}, if some fine points like |
|
1081 |
schematic polymorphism and type classes are ignored. |
|
52407 | 1082 |
|
61416 | 1083 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 1084 |
\<^emph>\<open>Proof abstractions\<close> of the form \<open>\<^bold>\<lambda>x :: \<alpha>. prf\<close> or \<open>\<^bold>\<lambda>p : A. prf\<close> |
1085 |
correspond to introduction of \<open>\<And>\<close>/\<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close>, and \<^emph>\<open>proof applications\<close> of the form |
|
1086 |
\<open>p \<cdot> t\<close> or \<open>p \<bullet> q\<close> correspond to elimination of \<open>\<And>\<close>/\<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close>. Actual types \<open>\<alpha>\<close>, |
|
1087 |
propositions \<open>A\<close>, and terms \<open>t\<close> might be suppressed and reconstructed from |
|
1088 |
the overall proof term. |
|
52407 | 1089 |
|
61416 | 1090 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 1091 |
Various atomic proofs indicate special situations within the proof |
1092 |
construction as follows. |
|
52407 | 1093 |
|
61854 | 1094 |
A \<^emph>\<open>bound proof variable\<close> is a natural number \<open>b\<close> that acts as de-Bruijn |
1095 |
index for proof term abstractions. |
|
52407 | 1096 |
|
61854 | 1097 |
A \<^emph>\<open>minimal proof\<close> ``\<open>?\<close>'' is a dummy proof term. This indicates some |
1098 |
unrecorded part of the proof. |
|
52407 | 1099 |
|
61854 | 1100 |
\<open>Hyp A\<close> refers to some pending hypothesis by giving its proposition. This |
1101 |
indicates an open context of implicit hypotheses, similar to loose bound |
|
1102 |
variables or free variables within a term (\secref{sec:terms}). |
|
52407 | 1103 |
|
61854 | 1104 |
An \<^emph>\<open>axiom\<close> or \<^emph>\<open>oracle\<close> \<open>a : A[\<^vec>\<tau>]\<close> refers some postulated \<open>proof |
1105 |
constant\<close>, which is subject to schematic polymorphism of theory content, and |
|
1106 |
the particular type instantiation may be given explicitly. The vector of |
|
1107 |
types \<open>\<^vec>\<tau>\<close> refers to the schematic type variables in the generic |
|
61493 | 1108 |
proposition \<open>A\<close> in canonical order. |
52407 | 1109 |
|
61854 | 1110 |
A \<^emph>\<open>proof promise\<close> \<open>a : A[\<^vec>\<tau>]\<close> is a placeholder for some proof of |
1111 |
polymorphic proposition \<open>A\<close>, with explicit type instantiation as given by |
|
1112 |
the vector \<open>\<^vec>\<tau>\<close>, as above. Unlike axioms or oracles, proof promises |
|
1113 |
may be \<^emph>\<open>fulfilled\<close> eventually, by substituting \<open>a\<close> by some particular proof |
|
1114 |
\<open>q\<close> at the corresponding type instance. This acts like Hindley-Milner |
|
1115 |
\<open>let\<close>-polymorphism: a generic local proof definition may get used at |
|
1116 |
different type instances, and is replaced by the concrete instance |
|
1117 |
eventually. |
|
52407 | 1118 |
|
61854 | 1119 |
A \<^emph>\<open>named theorem\<close> wraps up some concrete proof as a closed formal entity, |
1120 |
in the manner of constant definitions for proof terms. The \<^emph>\<open>proof body\<close> of |
|
1121 |
such boxed theorems involves some digest about oracles and promises |
|
1122 |
occurring in the original proof. This allows the inference kernel to manage |
|
1123 |
this critical information without the full overhead of explicit proof terms. |
|
58618 | 1124 |
\<close> |
52407 | 1125 |
|
52411 | 1126 |
|
58618 | 1127 |
subsection \<open>Reconstructing and checking proof terms\<close> |
52411 | 1128 |
|
61854 | 1129 |
text \<open> |
1130 |
Fully explicit proof terms can be large, but most of this information is |
|
1131 |
redundant and can be reconstructed from the context. Therefore, the |
|
1132 |
Isabelle/Pure inference kernel records only \<^emph>\<open>implicit\<close> proof terms, by |
|
1133 |
omitting all typing information in terms, all term and type labels of proof |
|
1134 |
abstractions, and some argument terms of applications \<open>p \<cdot> t\<close> (if possible). |
|
52411 | 1135 |
|
61854 | 1136 |
There are separate operations to reconstruct the full proof term later on, |
1137 |
using \<^emph>\<open>higher-order pattern unification\<close> @{cite "nipkow-patterns" and |
|
1138 |
"Berghofer-Nipkow:2000:TPHOL"}. |
|
52411 | 1139 |
|
61854 | 1140 |
The \<^emph>\<open>proof checker\<close> expects a fully reconstructed proof term, and can turn |
1141 |
it into a theorem by replaying its primitive inferences within the kernel. |
|
1142 |
\<close> |
|
52411 | 1143 |
|
52412 | 1144 |
|
58618 | 1145 |
subsection \<open>Concrete syntax of proof terms\<close> |
52412 | 1146 |
|
61854 | 1147 |
text \<open> |
1148 |
The concrete syntax of proof terms is a slight extension of the regular |
|
1149 |
inner syntax of Isabelle/Pure @{cite "isabelle-isar-ref"}. Its main |
|
1150 |
syntactic category @{syntax (inner) proof} is defined as follows: |
|
52412 | 1151 |
|
1152 |
\begin{center} |
|
1153 |
\begin{supertabular}{rclr} |
|
1154 |
||
61503 | 1155 |
@{syntax_def (inner) proof} & = & \<^verbatim>\<open>Lam\<close> \<open>params\<close> \<^verbatim>\<open>.\<close> \<open>proof\<close> \\ |
1156 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>\<^bold>\<lambda>\<close> \<open>params\<close> \<^verbatim>\<open>.\<close> \<open>proof\<close> \\ |
|
1157 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>proof\<close> \<^verbatim>\<open>%\<close> \<open>any\<close> \\ |
|
61493 | 1158 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>proof\<close> \<open>\<cdot>\<close> \<open>any\<close> \\ |
61503 | 1159 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>proof\<close> \<^verbatim>\<open>%%\<close> \<open>proof\<close> \\ |
61493 | 1160 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>proof\<close> \<open>\<bullet>\<close> \<open>proof\<close> \\ |
1161 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>id | longid\<close> \\ |
|
52412 | 1162 |
\\ |
1163 |
||
61493 | 1164 |
\<open>param\<close> & = & \<open>idt\<close> \\ |
61503 | 1165 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>idt\<close> \<^verbatim>\<open>:\<close> \<open>prop\<close> \\ |
1166 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<^verbatim>\<open>(\<close> \<open>param\<close> \<^verbatim>\<open>)\<close> \\ |
|
52412 | 1167 |
\\ |
1168 |
||
61493 | 1169 |
\<open>params\<close> & = & \<open>param\<close> \\ |
1170 |
& \<open>|\<close> & \<open>param\<close> \<open>params\<close> \\ |
|
52412 | 1171 |
|
1172 |
\end{supertabular} |
|
1173 |
\end{center} |
|
1174 |
||
61854 | 1175 |
Implicit term arguments in partial proofs are indicated by ``\<open>_\<close>''. Type |
1176 |
arguments for theorems and axioms may be specified using \<open>p \<cdot> TYPE(type)\<close> |
|
1177 |
(they must appear before any other term argument of a theorem or axiom, but |
|
1178 |
may be omitted altogether). |
|
52412 | 1179 |
|
61416 | 1180 |
\<^medskip> |
61854 | 1181 |
There are separate read and print operations for proof terms, in order to |
1182 |
avoid conflicts with the regular term language. |
|
58618 | 1183 |
\<close> |
52412 | 1184 |
|
58618 | 1185 |
text %mlref \<open> |
52408 | 1186 |
\begin{mldecls} |
1187 |
@{index_ML_type proof} \\ |
|
1188 |
@{index_ML_type proof_body} \\ |
|
65446 | 1189 |
@{index_ML Proofterm.proofs: "int Unsynchronized.ref"} \\ |
52411 | 1190 |
@{index_ML Reconstruct.reconstruct_proof: |
62922 | 1191 |
"Proof.context -> term -> proof -> proof"} \\ |
1192 |
@{index_ML Reconstruct.expand_proof: "Proof.context -> |
|
52411 | 1193 |
(string * term option) list -> proof -> proof"} \\ |
52412 | 1194 |
@{index_ML Proof_Checker.thm_of_proof: "theory -> proof -> thm"} \\ |
1195 |
@{index_ML Proof_Syntax.read_proof: "theory -> bool -> bool -> string -> proof"} \\ |
|
1196 |
@{index_ML Proof_Syntax.pretty_proof: "Proof.context -> proof -> Pretty.T"} \\ |
|
52408 | 1197 |
\end{mldecls} |
1198 |
||
61854 | 1199 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type proof} represents proof terms; this is a datatype with |
1200 |
constructors @{index_ML Abst}, @{index_ML AbsP}, @{index_ML_op "%"}, |
|
1201 |
@{index_ML_op "%%"}, @{index_ML PBound}, @{index_ML MinProof}, @{index_ML |
|
1202 |
Hyp}, @{index_ML PAxm}, @{index_ML Oracle}, @{index_ML Promise}, @{index_ML |
|
1203 |
PThm} as explained above. %FIXME OfClass (!?) |
|
1204 |
||
1205 |
\<^descr> Type @{ML_type proof_body} represents the nested proof information of a |
|
1206 |
named theorem, consisting of a digest of oracles and named theorem over some |
|
1207 |
proof term. The digest only covers the directly visible part of the proof: |
|
1208 |
in order to get the full information, the implicit graph of nested theorems |
|
1209 |
needs to be traversed (e.g.\ using @{ML Proofterm.fold_body_thms}). |
|
52408 | 1210 |
|
61854 | 1211 |
\<^descr> @{ML Thm.proof_of}~\<open>thm\<close> and @{ML Thm.proof_body_of}~\<open>thm\<close> produce the |
1212 |
proof term or proof body (with digest of oracles and theorems) from a given |
|
1213 |
theorem. Note that this involves a full join of internal futures that |
|
1214 |
fulfill pending proof promises, and thus disrupts the natural bottom-up |
|
1215 |
construction of proofs by introducing dynamic ad-hoc dependencies. Parallel |
|
1216 |
performance may suffer by inspecting proof terms at run-time. |
|
52408 | 1217 |
|
65446 | 1218 |
\<^descr> @{ML Proofterm.proofs} specifies the detail of proof recording within |
1219 |
@{ML_type thm} values produced by the inference kernel: @{ML 0} records only |
|
1220 |
the names of oracles, @{ML 1} records oracle names and propositions, @{ML 2} |
|
1221 |
additionally records full proof terms. Officially named theorems that |
|
1222 |
contribute to a result are recorded in any case. |
|
52408 | 1223 |
|
62922 | 1224 |
\<^descr> @{ML Reconstruct.reconstruct_proof}~\<open>ctxt prop prf\<close> turns the implicit |
61854 | 1225 |
proof term \<open>prf\<close> into a full proof of the given proposition. |
52487
48bc24467008
backout dedd7952a62c: static "proofs" value within theory prevents later inferencing with different configuration;
wenzelm
parents:
52486
diff
changeset
|
1226 |
|
61854 | 1227 |
Reconstruction may fail if \<open>prf\<close> is not a proof of \<open>prop\<close>, or if it does not |
1228 |
contain sufficient information for reconstruction. Failure may only happen |
|
1229 |
for proofs that are constructed manually, but not for those produced |
|
1230 |
automatically by the inference kernel. |
|
52411 | 1231 |
|
62922 | 1232 |
\<^descr> @{ML Reconstruct.expand_proof}~\<open>ctxt [thm\<^sub>1, \<dots>, thm\<^sub>n] prf\<close> expands and |
61854 | 1233 |
reconstructs the proofs of all specified theorems, with the given (full) |
1234 |
proof. Theorems that are not unique specified via their name may be |
|
1235 |
disambiguated by giving their proposition. |
|
52411 | 1236 |
|
61854 | 1237 |
\<^descr> @{ML Proof_Checker.thm_of_proof}~\<open>thy prf\<close> turns the given (full) proof |
1238 |
into a theorem, by replaying it using only primitive rules of the inference |
|
1239 |
kernel. |
|
52411 | 1240 |
|
61854 | 1241 |
\<^descr> @{ML Proof_Syntax.read_proof}~\<open>thy b\<^sub>1 b\<^sub>2 s\<close> reads in a proof term. The |
1242 |
Boolean flags indicate the use of sort and type information. Usually, typing |
|
1243 |
information is left implicit and is inferred during proof reconstruction. |
|
1244 |
%FIXME eliminate flags!? |
|
52412 | 1245 |
|
61854 | 1246 |
\<^descr> @{ML Proof_Syntax.pretty_proof}~\<open>ctxt prf\<close> pretty-prints the given proof |
1247 |
term. |
|
58618 | 1248 |
\<close> |
52408 | 1249 |
|
61854 | 1250 |
text %mlex \<open> |
63680 | 1251 |
\<^item> \<^file>\<open>~~/src/HOL/Proofs/ex/Proof_Terms.thy\<close> provides basic examples involving |
1252 |
proof terms. |
|
52410 | 1253 |
|
63680 | 1254 |
\<^item> \<^file>\<open>~~/src/HOL/Proofs/ex/XML_Data.thy\<close> demonstrates export and import of |
1255 |
proof terms via XML/ML data representation. |
|
58618 | 1256 |
\<close> |
52410 | 1257 |
|
18537 | 1258 |
end |