author | wenzelm |
Mon, 21 Jun 2010 11:24:19 +0200 | |
changeset 37380 | 35815ce9218a |
parent 33026 | 8f35633c4922 |
child 37671 | fa53d267dab3 |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
33026 | 1 |
(* Title: HOL/Isar_Examples/Peirce.thy |
6444
2ebe9e630cab
Miscellaneous Isabelle/Isar examples for Higher-Order Logic.
wenzelm
parents:
diff
changeset
|
2 |
Author: Markus Wenzel, TU Muenchen |
2ebe9e630cab
Miscellaneous Isabelle/Isar examples for Higher-Order Logic.
wenzelm
parents:
diff
changeset
|
3 |
*) |
2ebe9e630cab
Miscellaneous Isabelle/Isar examples for Higher-Order Logic.
wenzelm
parents:
diff
changeset
|
4 |
|
10007 | 5 |
header {* Peirce's Law *} |
6444
2ebe9e630cab
Miscellaneous Isabelle/Isar examples for Higher-Order Logic.
wenzelm
parents:
diff
changeset
|
6 |
|
31758 | 7 |
theory Peirce |
8 |
imports Main |
|
9 |
begin |
|
6444
2ebe9e630cab
Miscellaneous Isabelle/Isar examples for Higher-Order Logic.
wenzelm
parents:
diff
changeset
|
10 |
|
7860 | 11 |
text {* |
12 |
We consider Peirce's Law: $((A \impl B) \impl A) \impl A$. This is |
|
13 |
an inherently non-intuitionistic statement, so its proof will |
|
14 |
certainly involve some form of classical contradiction. |
|
15 |
||
16 |
The first proof is again a well-balanced combination of plain |
|
7874 | 17 |
backward and forward reasoning. The actual classical step is where |
18 |
the negated goal may be introduced as additional assumption. This |
|
19 |
eventually leads to a contradiction.\footnote{The rule involved there |
|
20 |
is negation elimination; it holds in intuitionistic logic as well.} |
|
10007 | 21 |
*} |
7860 | 22 |
|
10007 | 23 |
theorem "((A --> B) --> A) --> A" |
24 |
proof |
|
23373 | 25 |
assume "(A --> B) --> A" |
10007 | 26 |
show A |
27 |
proof (rule classical) |
|
28 |
assume "~ A" |
|
29 |
have "A --> B" |
|
30 |
proof |
|
31 |
assume A |
|
23373 | 32 |
with `~ A` show B by contradiction |
10007 | 33 |
qed |
23373 | 34 |
with `(A --> B) --> A` show A .. |
10007 | 35 |
qed |
36 |
qed |
|
6444
2ebe9e630cab
Miscellaneous Isabelle/Isar examples for Higher-Order Logic.
wenzelm
parents:
diff
changeset
|
37 |
|
7860 | 38 |
text {* |
7874 | 39 |
In the subsequent version the reasoning is rearranged by means of |
40 |
``weak assumptions'' (as introduced by \isacommand{presume}). Before |
|
7860 | 41 |
assuming the negated goal $\neg A$, its intended consequence $A \impl |
42 |
B$ is put into place in order to solve the main problem. |
|
43 |
Nevertheless, we do not get anything for free, but have to establish |
|
7874 | 44 |
$A \impl B$ later on. The overall effect is that of a logical |
45 |
\emph{cut}. |
|
7860 | 46 |
|
47 |
Technically speaking, whenever some goal is solved by |
|
48 |
\isacommand{show} in the context of weak assumptions then the latter |
|
49 |
give rise to new subgoals, which may be established separately. In |
|
50 |
contrast, strong assumptions (as introduced by \isacommand{assume}) |
|
51 |
are solved immediately. |
|
10007 | 52 |
*} |
7860 | 53 |
|
10007 | 54 |
theorem "((A --> B) --> A) --> A" |
55 |
proof |
|
23373 | 56 |
assume "(A --> B) --> A" |
10007 | 57 |
show A |
58 |
proof (rule classical) |
|
59 |
presume "A --> B" |
|
23373 | 60 |
with `(A --> B) --> A` show A .. |
10007 | 61 |
next |
62 |
assume "~ A" |
|
63 |
show "A --> B" |
|
64 |
proof |
|
65 |
assume A |
|
23373 | 66 |
with `~ A` show B by contradiction |
10007 | 67 |
qed |
68 |
qed |
|
69 |
qed |
|
6444
2ebe9e630cab
Miscellaneous Isabelle/Isar examples for Higher-Order Logic.
wenzelm
parents:
diff
changeset
|
70 |
|
7860 | 71 |
text {* |
72 |
Note that the goals stemming from weak assumptions may be even left |
|
73 |
until qed time, where they get eventually solved ``by assumption'' as |
|
7874 | 74 |
well. In that case there is really no fundamental difference between |
75 |
the two kinds of assumptions, apart from the order of reducing the |
|
76 |
individual parts of the proof configuration. |
|
7860 | 77 |
|
78 |
Nevertheless, the ``strong'' mode of plain assumptions is quite |
|
7982 | 79 |
important in practice to achieve robustness of proof text |
7860 | 80 |
interpretation. By forcing both the conclusion \emph{and} the |
7869 | 81 |
assumptions to unify with the pending goal to be solved, goal |
82 |
selection becomes quite deterministic. For example, decomposition |
|
7982 | 83 |
with rules of the ``case-analysis'' type usually gives rise to |
84 |
several goals that only differ in there local contexts. With strong |
|
85 |
assumptions these may be still solved in any order in a predictable |
|
86 |
way, while weak ones would quickly lead to great confusion, |
|
87 |
eventually demanding even some backtracking. |
|
10007 | 88 |
*} |
7860 | 89 |
|
10007 | 90 |
end |