author | wenzelm |
Mon, 13 Sep 2021 17:06:44 +0200 | |
changeset 74310 | d7a62db70a07 |
parent 73511 | 2cdbb6a2f2a7 |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
47269 | 1 |
(*<*) |
2 |
theory Basics |
|
3 |
imports Main |
|
4 |
begin |
|
5 |
(*>*) |
|
67406 | 6 |
text\<open> |
47269 | 7 |
This chapter introduces HOL as a functional programming language and shows |
8 |
how to prove properties of functional programs by induction. |
|
9 |
||
10 |
\section{Basics} |
|
11 |
||
52361 | 12 |
\subsection{Types, Terms and Formulas} |
47269 | 13 |
\label{sec:TypesTermsForms} |
14 |
||
15 |
HOL is a typed logic whose type system resembles that of functional |
|
16 |
programming languages. Thus there are |
|
17 |
\begin{description} |
|
18 |
\item[base types,] |
|
69597 | 19 |
in particular \<^typ>\<open>bool\<close>, the type of truth values, |
20 |
\<^typ>\<open>nat\<close>, the type of natural numbers ($\mathbb{N}$), and \indexed{\<^typ>\<open>int\<close>}{int}, |
|
47269 | 21 |
the type of mathematical integers ($\mathbb{Z}$). |
22 |
\item[type constructors,] |
|
69505 | 23 |
in particular \<open>list\<close>, the type of |
24 |
lists, and \<open>set\<close>, the type of sets. Type constructors are written |
|
54467 | 25 |
postfix, i.e., after their arguments. For example, |
69597 | 26 |
\<^typ>\<open>nat list\<close> is the type of lists whose elements are natural numbers. |
47269 | 27 |
\item[function types,] |
69505 | 28 |
denoted by \<open>\<Rightarrow>\<close>. |
47269 | 29 |
\item[type variables,] |
69597 | 30 |
denoted by \<^typ>\<open>'a\<close>, \<^typ>\<open>'b\<close>, etc., like in ML\@. |
47269 | 31 |
\end{description} |
69597 | 32 |
Note that \<^typ>\<open>'a \<Rightarrow> 'b list\<close> means \noquotes{@{typ[source]"'a \<Rightarrow> ('b list)"}}, |
33 |
not \<^typ>\<open>('a \<Rightarrow> 'b) list\<close>: postfix type constructors have precedence |
|
69505 | 34 |
over \<open>\<Rightarrow>\<close>. |
47269 | 35 |
|
55317 | 36 |
\conceptidx{Terms}{term} are formed as in functional programming by |
69505 | 37 |
applying functions to arguments. If \<open>f\<close> is a function of type |
38 |
\<open>\<tau>\<^sub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<tau>\<^sub>2\<close> and \<open>t\<close> is a term of type |
|
69597 | 39 |
\<open>\<tau>\<^sub>1\<close> then \<^term>\<open>f t\<close> is a term of type \<open>\<tau>\<^sub>2\<close>. We write \<open>t :: \<tau>\<close> to mean that term \<open>t\<close> has type \<open>\<tau>\<close>. |
47269 | 40 |
|
41 |
\begin{warn} |
|
69505 | 42 |
There are many predefined infix symbols like \<open>+\<close> and \<open>\<le>\<close>. |
69597 | 43 |
The name of the corresponding binary function is \<^term>\<open>(+)\<close>, |
44 |
not just \<open>+\<close>. That is, \<^term>\<open>x + y\<close> is nice surface syntax |
|
67399 | 45 |
(``syntactic sugar'') for \noquotes{@{term[source]"(+) x y"}}. |
47269 | 46 |
\end{warn} |
47 |
||
48 |
HOL also supports some basic constructs from functional programming: |
|
49 |
\begin{quote} |
|
69505 | 50 |
\<open>(if b then t\<^sub>1 else t\<^sub>2)\<close>\\ |
51 |
\<open>(let x = t in u)\<close>\\ |
|
52 |
\<open>(case t of pat\<^sub>1 \<Rightarrow> t\<^sub>1 | \<dots> | pat\<^sub>n \<Rightarrow> t\<^sub>n)\<close> |
|
47269 | 53 |
\end{quote} |
54 |
\begin{warn} |
|
55 |
The above three constructs must always be enclosed in parentheses |
|
56 |
if they occur inside other constructs. |
|
57 |
\end{warn} |
|
69505 | 58 |
Terms may also contain \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-abstractions. For example, |
69597 | 59 |
\<^term>\<open>\<lambda>x. x\<close> is the identity function. |
47269 | 60 |
|
69505 | 61 |
\conceptidx{Formulas}{formula} are terms of type \<open>bool\<close>. |
69597 | 62 |
There are the basic constants \<^term>\<open>True\<close> and \<^term>\<open>False\<close> and |
47269 | 63 |
the usual logical connectives (in decreasing order of precedence): |
69505 | 64 |
\<open>\<not>\<close>, \<open>\<and>\<close>, \<open>\<or>\<close>, \<open>\<longrightarrow>\<close>. |
47269 | 65 |
|
69505 | 66 |
\conceptidx{Equality}{equality} is available in the form of the infix function \<open>=\<close> |
69597 | 67 |
of type \<^typ>\<open>'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool\<close>. It also works for formulas, where |
47269 | 68 |
it means ``if and only if''. |
69 |
||
69597 | 70 |
\conceptidx{Quantifiers}{quantifier} are written \<^prop>\<open>\<forall>x. P\<close> and \<^prop>\<open>\<exists>x. P\<close>. |
47269 | 71 |
|
72 |
Isabelle automatically computes the type of each variable in a term. This is |
|
73 |
called \concept{type inference}. Despite type inference, it is sometimes |
|
55317 | 74 |
necessary to attach an explicit \concept{type constraint} (or \concept{type |
69505 | 75 |
annotation}) to a variable or term. The syntax is \<open>t :: \<tau>\<close> as in |
57804 | 76 |
\mbox{\noquotes{@{term[source] "m + (n::nat)"}}}. Type constraints may be |
47269 | 77 |
needed to |
69505 | 78 |
disambiguate terms involving overloaded functions such as \<open>+\<close>. |
47269 | 79 |
|
69505 | 80 |
Finally there are the universal quantifier \<open>\<And>\<close>\index{$4@\isasymAnd} and the implication |
81 |
\<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close>\index{$3@\isasymLongrightarrow}. They are part of the Isabelle framework, not the logic |
|
82 |
HOL. Logically, they agree with their HOL counterparts \<open>\<forall>\<close> and |
|
83 |
\<open>\<longrightarrow>\<close>, but operationally they behave differently. This will become |
|
47269 | 84 |
clearer as we go along. |
85 |
\begin{warn} |
|
86 |
Right-arrows of all kinds always associate to the right. In particular, |
|
87 |
the formula |
|
69505 | 88 |
\<open>A\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>2 \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>3\<close> means \<open>A\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> (A\<^sub>2 \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>3)\<close>. |
58655 | 89 |
The (Isabelle-specific\footnote{To display implications in this style in |
69505 | 90 |
Isabelle/jEdit you need to set Plugins $>$ Plugin Options $>$ Isabelle/General $>$ Print Mode to ``\texttt{brackets}'' and restart.}) notation \mbox{\<open>\<lbrakk> A\<^sub>1; \<dots>; A\<^sub>n \<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A\<close>} |
91 |
is short for the iterated implication \mbox{\<open>A\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> A\<close>}. |
|
47269 | 92 |
Sometimes we also employ inference rule notation: |
69505 | 93 |
\inferrule{\mbox{\<open>A\<^sub>1\<close>}\\ \mbox{\<open>\<dots>\<close>}\\ \mbox{\<open>A\<^sub>n\<close>}} |
94 |
{\mbox{\<open>A\<close>}} |
|
47269 | 95 |
\end{warn} |
96 |
||
97 |
||
98 |
\subsection{Theories} |
|
99 |
\label{sec:Basic:Theories} |
|
100 |
||
101 |
Roughly speaking, a \concept{theory} is a named collection of types, |
|
102 |
functions, and theorems, much like a module in a programming language. |
|
57804 | 103 |
All Isabelle text needs to go into a theory. |
69505 | 104 |
The general format of a theory \<open>T\<close> is |
47269 | 105 |
\begin{quote} |
69505 | 106 |
\indexed{\isacom{theory}}{theory} \<open>T\<close>\\ |
107 |
\indexed{\isacom{imports}}{imports} \<open>T\<^sub>1 \<dots> T\<^sub>n\<close>\\ |
|
47269 | 108 |
\isacom{begin}\\ |
109 |
\emph{definitions, theorems and proofs}\\ |
|
110 |
\isacom{end} |
|
111 |
\end{quote} |
|
69505 | 112 |
where \<open>T\<^sub>1 \<dots> T\<^sub>n\<close> are the names of existing |
113 |
theories that \<open>T\<close> is based on. The \<open>T\<^sub>i\<close> are the |
|
114 |
direct \conceptidx{parent theories}{parent theory} of \<open>T\<close>. |
|
47269 | 115 |
Everything defined in the parent theories (and their parents, recursively) is |
69505 | 116 |
automatically visible. Each theory \<open>T\<close> must |
117 |
reside in a \concept{theory file} named \<open>T.thy\<close>. |
|
47269 | 118 |
|
119 |
\begin{warn} |
|
69597 | 120 |
HOL contains a theory \<^theory>\<open>Main\<close>\index{Main@\<^theory>\<open>Main\<close>}, the union of all the basic |
47269 | 121 |
predefined theories like arithmetic, lists, sets, etc. |
69505 | 122 |
Unless you know what you are doing, always include \<open>Main\<close> |
47269 | 123 |
as a direct or indirect parent of all your theories. |
124 |
\end{warn} |
|
125 |
||
126 |
In addition to the theories that come with the Isabelle/HOL distribution |
|
68224 | 127 |
(see \<^url>\<open>https://isabelle.in.tum.de/library/HOL\<close>) |
47269 | 128 |
there is also the \emph{Archive of Formal Proofs} |
67605 | 129 |
at \<^url>\<open>https://isa-afp.org\<close>, a growing collection of Isabelle theories |
47269 | 130 |
that everybody can contribute to. |
131 |
||
132 |
\subsection{Quotation Marks} |
|
133 |
||
134 |
The textual definition of a theory follows a fixed syntax with keywords like |
|
73511
2cdbb6a2f2a7
updated to latest latex due to new mechanism for dealing with bold ccfonts
nipkow
parents:
69597
diff
changeset
|
135 |
\isacom{begin} and \isacom{datatype}. Embedded in this syntax are |
52361 | 136 |
the types and formulas of HOL. To distinguish the two levels, everything |
47269 | 137 |
HOL-specific (terms and types) must be enclosed in quotation marks: |
61643 | 138 |
\texttt{"}\dots\texttt{"}. Quotation marks around a |
47269 | 139 |
single identifier can be dropped. When Isabelle prints a syntax error |
140 |
message, it refers to the HOL syntax as the \concept{inner syntax} and the |
|
141 |
enclosing theory language as the \concept{outer syntax}. |
|
61643 | 142 |
|
62222 | 143 |
\ifsem\else |
61643 | 144 |
\subsection{Proof State} |
145 |
||
146 |
\begin{warn} |
|
62222 | 147 |
By default Isabelle/jEdit does not show the proof state but this tutorial |
148 |
refers to it frequently. You should tick the ``Proof state'' box |
|
149 |
to see the proof state in the output window. |
|
61643 | 150 |
\end{warn} |
62222 | 151 |
\fi |
67406 | 152 |
\<close> |
47269 | 153 |
(*<*) |
154 |
end |
|
67399 | 155 |
(*>*) |