47269
|
1 |
(*<*)
|
|
2 |
theory Basics
|
|
3 |
imports Main
|
|
4 |
begin
|
|
5 |
(*>*)
|
67406
|
6 |
text\<open>
|
47269
|
7 |
This chapter introduces HOL as a functional programming language and shows
|
|
8 |
how to prove properties of functional programs by induction.
|
|
9 |
|
|
10 |
\section{Basics}
|
|
11 |
|
52361
|
12 |
\subsection{Types, Terms and Formulas}
|
47269
|
13 |
\label{sec:TypesTermsForms}
|
|
14 |
|
|
15 |
HOL is a typed logic whose type system resembles that of functional
|
|
16 |
programming languages. Thus there are
|
|
17 |
\begin{description}
|
|
18 |
\item[base types,]
|
69597
|
19 |
in particular \<^typ>\<open>bool\<close>, the type of truth values,
|
|
20 |
\<^typ>\<open>nat\<close>, the type of natural numbers ($\mathbb{N}$), and \indexed{\<^typ>\<open>int\<close>}{int},
|
47269
|
21 |
the type of mathematical integers ($\mathbb{Z}$).
|
|
22 |
\item[type constructors,]
|
69505
|
23 |
in particular \<open>list\<close>, the type of
|
|
24 |
lists, and \<open>set\<close>, the type of sets. Type constructors are written
|
54467
|
25 |
postfix, i.e., after their arguments. For example,
|
69597
|
26 |
\<^typ>\<open>nat list\<close> is the type of lists whose elements are natural numbers.
|
47269
|
27 |
\item[function types,]
|
69505
|
28 |
denoted by \<open>\<Rightarrow>\<close>.
|
47269
|
29 |
\item[type variables,]
|
69597
|
30 |
denoted by \<^typ>\<open>'a\<close>, \<^typ>\<open>'b\<close>, etc., like in ML\@.
|
47269
|
31 |
\end{description}
|
69597
|
32 |
Note that \<^typ>\<open>'a \<Rightarrow> 'b list\<close> means \noquotes{@{typ[source]"'a \<Rightarrow> ('b list)"}},
|
|
33 |
not \<^typ>\<open>('a \<Rightarrow> 'b) list\<close>: postfix type constructors have precedence
|
69505
|
34 |
over \<open>\<Rightarrow>\<close>.
|
47269
|
35 |
|
55317
|
36 |
\conceptidx{Terms}{term} are formed as in functional programming by
|
69505
|
37 |
applying functions to arguments. If \<open>f\<close> is a function of type
|
|
38 |
\<open>\<tau>\<^sub>1 \<Rightarrow> \<tau>\<^sub>2\<close> and \<open>t\<close> is a term of type
|
69597
|
39 |
\<open>\<tau>\<^sub>1\<close> then \<^term>\<open>f t\<close> is a term of type \<open>\<tau>\<^sub>2\<close>. We write \<open>t :: \<tau>\<close> to mean that term \<open>t\<close> has type \<open>\<tau>\<close>.
|
47269
|
40 |
|
|
41 |
\begin{warn}
|
69505
|
42 |
There are many predefined infix symbols like \<open>+\<close> and \<open>\<le>\<close>.
|
69597
|
43 |
The name of the corresponding binary function is \<^term>\<open>(+)\<close>,
|
|
44 |
not just \<open>+\<close>. That is, \<^term>\<open>x + y\<close> is nice surface syntax
|
67399
|
45 |
(``syntactic sugar'') for \noquotes{@{term[source]"(+) x y"}}.
|
47269
|
46 |
\end{warn}
|
|
47 |
|
|
48 |
HOL also supports some basic constructs from functional programming:
|
|
49 |
\begin{quote}
|
69505
|
50 |
\<open>(if b then t\<^sub>1 else t\<^sub>2)\<close>\\
|
|
51 |
\<open>(let x = t in u)\<close>\\
|
|
52 |
\<open>(case t of pat\<^sub>1 \<Rightarrow> t\<^sub>1 | \<dots> | pat\<^sub>n \<Rightarrow> t\<^sub>n)\<close>
|
47269
|
53 |
\end{quote}
|
|
54 |
\begin{warn}
|
|
55 |
The above three constructs must always be enclosed in parentheses
|
|
56 |
if they occur inside other constructs.
|
|
57 |
\end{warn}
|
69505
|
58 |
Terms may also contain \<open>\<lambda>\<close>-abstractions. For example,
|
69597
|
59 |
\<^term>\<open>\<lambda>x. x\<close> is the identity function.
|
47269
|
60 |
|
69505
|
61 |
\conceptidx{Formulas}{formula} are terms of type \<open>bool\<close>.
|
69597
|
62 |
There are the basic constants \<^term>\<open>True\<close> and \<^term>\<open>False\<close> and
|
47269
|
63 |
the usual logical connectives (in decreasing order of precedence):
|
69505
|
64 |
\<open>\<not>\<close>, \<open>\<and>\<close>, \<open>\<or>\<close>, \<open>\<longrightarrow>\<close>.
|
47269
|
65 |
|
69505
|
66 |
\conceptidx{Equality}{equality} is available in the form of the infix function \<open>=\<close>
|
69597
|
67 |
of type \<^typ>\<open>'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> bool\<close>. It also works for formulas, where
|
47269
|
68 |
it means ``if and only if''.
|
|
69 |
|
69597
|
70 |
\conceptidx{Quantifiers}{quantifier} are written \<^prop>\<open>\<forall>x. P\<close> and \<^prop>\<open>\<exists>x. P\<close>.
|
47269
|
71 |
|
|
72 |
Isabelle automatically computes the type of each variable in a term. This is
|
|
73 |
called \concept{type inference}. Despite type inference, it is sometimes
|
55317
|
74 |
necessary to attach an explicit \concept{type constraint} (or \concept{type
|
69505
|
75 |
annotation}) to a variable or term. The syntax is \<open>t :: \<tau>\<close> as in
|
57804
|
76 |
\mbox{\noquotes{@{term[source] "m + (n::nat)"}}}. Type constraints may be
|
47269
|
77 |
needed to
|
69505
|
78 |
disambiguate terms involving overloaded functions such as \<open>+\<close>.
|
47269
|
79 |
|
69505
|
80 |
Finally there are the universal quantifier \<open>\<And>\<close>\index{$4@\isasymAnd} and the implication
|
|
81 |
\<open>\<Longrightarrow>\<close>\index{$3@\isasymLongrightarrow}. They are part of the Isabelle framework, not the logic
|
|
82 |
HOL. Logically, they agree with their HOL counterparts \<open>\<forall>\<close> and
|
|
83 |
\<open>\<longrightarrow>\<close>, but operationally they behave differently. This will become
|
47269
|
84 |
clearer as we go along.
|
|
85 |
\begin{warn}
|
|
86 |
Right-arrows of all kinds always associate to the right. In particular,
|
|
87 |
the formula
|
69505
|
88 |
\<open>A\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>2 \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>3\<close> means \<open>A\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> (A\<^sub>2 \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>3)\<close>.
|
58655
|
89 |
The (Isabelle-specific\footnote{To display implications in this style in
|
69505
|
90 |
Isabelle/jEdit you need to set Plugins $>$ Plugin Options $>$ Isabelle/General $>$ Print Mode to ``\texttt{brackets}'' and restart.}) notation \mbox{\<open>\<lbrakk> A\<^sub>1; \<dots>; A\<^sub>n \<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> A\<close>}
|
|
91 |
is short for the iterated implication \mbox{\<open>A\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<Longrightarrow> A\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> A\<close>}.
|
47269
|
92 |
Sometimes we also employ inference rule notation:
|
69505
|
93 |
\inferrule{\mbox{\<open>A\<^sub>1\<close>}\\ \mbox{\<open>\<dots>\<close>}\\ \mbox{\<open>A\<^sub>n\<close>}}
|
|
94 |
{\mbox{\<open>A\<close>}}
|
47269
|
95 |
\end{warn}
|
|
96 |
|
|
97 |
|
|
98 |
\subsection{Theories}
|
|
99 |
\label{sec:Basic:Theories}
|
|
100 |
|
|
101 |
Roughly speaking, a \concept{theory} is a named collection of types,
|
|
102 |
functions, and theorems, much like a module in a programming language.
|
57804
|
103 |
All Isabelle text needs to go into a theory.
|
69505
|
104 |
The general format of a theory \<open>T\<close> is
|
47269
|
105 |
\begin{quote}
|
69505
|
106 |
\indexed{\isacom{theory}}{theory} \<open>T\<close>\\
|
|
107 |
\indexed{\isacom{imports}}{imports} \<open>T\<^sub>1 \<dots> T\<^sub>n\<close>\\
|
47269
|
108 |
\isacom{begin}\\
|
|
109 |
\emph{definitions, theorems and proofs}\\
|
|
110 |
\isacom{end}
|
|
111 |
\end{quote}
|
69505
|
112 |
where \<open>T\<^sub>1 \<dots> T\<^sub>n\<close> are the names of existing
|
|
113 |
theories that \<open>T\<close> is based on. The \<open>T\<^sub>i\<close> are the
|
|
114 |
direct \conceptidx{parent theories}{parent theory} of \<open>T\<close>.
|
47269
|
115 |
Everything defined in the parent theories (and their parents, recursively) is
|
69505
|
116 |
automatically visible. Each theory \<open>T\<close> must
|
|
117 |
reside in a \concept{theory file} named \<open>T.thy\<close>.
|
47269
|
118 |
|
|
119 |
\begin{warn}
|
69597
|
120 |
HOL contains a theory \<^theory>\<open>Main\<close>\index{Main@\<^theory>\<open>Main\<close>}, the union of all the basic
|
47269
|
121 |
predefined theories like arithmetic, lists, sets, etc.
|
69505
|
122 |
Unless you know what you are doing, always include \<open>Main\<close>
|
47269
|
123 |
as a direct or indirect parent of all your theories.
|
|
124 |
\end{warn}
|
|
125 |
|
|
126 |
In addition to the theories that come with the Isabelle/HOL distribution
|
68224
|
127 |
(see \<^url>\<open>https://isabelle.in.tum.de/library/HOL\<close>)
|
47269
|
128 |
there is also the \emph{Archive of Formal Proofs}
|
67605
|
129 |
at \<^url>\<open>https://isa-afp.org\<close>, a growing collection of Isabelle theories
|
47269
|
130 |
that everybody can contribute to.
|
|
131 |
|
|
132 |
\subsection{Quotation Marks}
|
|
133 |
|
|
134 |
The textual definition of a theory follows a fixed syntax with keywords like
|
|
135 |
\isacommand{begin} and \isacommand{datatype}. Embedded in this syntax are
|
52361
|
136 |
the types and formulas of HOL. To distinguish the two levels, everything
|
47269
|
137 |
HOL-specific (terms and types) must be enclosed in quotation marks:
|
61643
|
138 |
\texttt{"}\dots\texttt{"}. Quotation marks around a
|
47269
|
139 |
single identifier can be dropped. When Isabelle prints a syntax error
|
|
140 |
message, it refers to the HOL syntax as the \concept{inner syntax} and the
|
|
141 |
enclosing theory language as the \concept{outer syntax}.
|
61643
|
142 |
|
62222
|
143 |
\ifsem\else
|
61643
|
144 |
\subsection{Proof State}
|
|
145 |
|
|
146 |
\begin{warn}
|
62222
|
147 |
By default Isabelle/jEdit does not show the proof state but this tutorial
|
|
148 |
refers to it frequently. You should tick the ``Proof state'' box
|
|
149 |
to see the proof state in the output window.
|
61643
|
150 |
\end{warn}
|
62222
|
151 |
\fi
|
67406
|
152 |
\<close>
|
47269
|
153 |
(*<*)
|
|
154 |
end
|
67399
|
155 |
(*>*)
|