src/Doc/Implementation/Eq.thy
changeset 56420 b266e7a86485
parent 54742 7a86358a3c0b
child 58555 7975676c08c0
--- /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
+++ b/src/Doc/Implementation/Eq.thy	Sat Apr 05 11:37:00 2014 +0200
@@ -0,0 +1,126 @@
+theory Eq
+imports Base
+begin
+
+chapter {* Equational reasoning *}
+
+text {* Equality is one of the most fundamental concepts of
+  mathematics.  The Isabelle/Pure logic (\chref{ch:logic}) provides a
+  builtin relation @{text "\<equiv> :: \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> prop"} that expresses equality
+  of arbitrary terms (or propositions) at the framework level, as
+  expressed by certain basic inference rules (\secref{sec:eq-rules}).
+
+  Equational reasoning means to replace equals by equals, using
+  reflexivity and transitivity to form chains of replacement steps,
+  and congruence rules to access sub-structures.  Conversions
+  (\secref{sec:conv}) provide a convenient framework to compose basic
+  equational steps to build specific equational reasoning tools.
+
+  Higher-order matching is able to provide suitable instantiations for
+  giving equality rules, which leads to the versatile concept of
+  @{text "\<lambda>"}-term rewriting (\secref{sec:rewriting}).  Internally
+  this is based on the general-purpose Simplifier engine of Isabelle,
+  which is more specific and more efficient than plain conversions.
+
+  Object-logics usually introduce specific notions of equality or
+  equivalence, and relate it with the Pure equality.  This enables to
+  re-use the Pure tools for equational reasoning for particular
+  object-logic connectives as well.
+*}
+
+
+section {* Basic equality rules \label{sec:eq-rules} *}
+
+text {* Isabelle/Pure uses @{text "\<equiv>"} for equality of arbitrary
+  terms, which includes equivalence of propositions of the logical
+  framework.  The conceptual axiomatization of the constant @{text "\<equiv>
+  :: \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> prop"} is given in \figref{fig:pure-equality}.  The
+  inference kernel presents slightly different equality rules, which
+  may be understood as derived rules from this minimal axiomatization.
+  The Pure theory also provides some theorems that express the same
+  reasoning schemes as theorems that can be composed like object-level
+  rules as explained in \secref{sec:obj-rules}.
+
+  For example, @{ML Thm.symmetric} as Pure inference is an ML function
+  that maps a theorem @{text "th"} stating @{text "t \<equiv> u"} to one
+  stating @{text "u \<equiv> t"}.  In contrast, @{thm [source]
+  Pure.symmetric} as Pure theorem expresses the same reasoning in
+  declarative form.  If used like @{text "th [THEN Pure.symmetric]"}
+  in Isar source notation, it achieves a similar effect as the ML
+  inference function, although the rule attribute @{attribute THEN} or
+  ML operator @{ML "op RS"} involve the full machinery of higher-order
+  unification (modulo @{text "\<beta>\<eta>"}-conversion) and lifting of @{text
+  "\<And>/\<Longrightarrow>"} contexts. *}
+
+text %mlref {*
+  \begin{mldecls}
+  @{index_ML Thm.reflexive: "cterm -> thm"} \\
+  @{index_ML Thm.symmetric: "thm -> thm"} \\
+  @{index_ML Thm.transitive: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\
+  @{index_ML Thm.abstract_rule: "string -> cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\
+  @{index_ML Thm.combination: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\[0.5ex]
+  @{index_ML Thm.equal_intr: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\
+  @{index_ML Thm.equal_elim: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\
+  \end{mldecls}
+
+  See also @{file "~~/src/Pure/thm.ML" } for further description of
+  these inference rules, and a few more for primitive @{text "\<beta>"} and
+  @{text "\<eta>"} conversions.  Note that @{text "\<alpha>"} conversion is
+  implicit due to the representation of terms with de-Bruijn indices
+  (\secref{sec:terms}). *}
+
+
+section {* Conversions \label{sec:conv} *}
+
+text {*
+  %FIXME
+
+  The classic article that introduces the concept of conversion (for
+  Cambridge LCF) is \cite{paulson:1983}.
+*}
+
+
+section {* Rewriting \label{sec:rewriting} *}
+
+text {* Rewriting normalizes a given term (theorem or goal) by
+  replacing instances of given equalities @{text "t \<equiv> u"} in subterms.
+  Rewriting continues until no rewrites are applicable to any subterm.
+  This may be used to unfold simple definitions of the form @{text "f
+  x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>n \<equiv> u"}, but is slightly more general than that.
+*}
+
+text %mlref {*
+  \begin{mldecls}
+  @{index_ML rewrite_rule: "Proof.context -> thm list -> thm -> thm"} \\
+  @{index_ML rewrite_goals_rule: "Proof.context -> thm list -> thm -> thm"} \\
+  @{index_ML rewrite_goal_tac: "Proof.context -> thm list -> int -> tactic"} \\
+  @{index_ML rewrite_goals_tac: "Proof.context -> thm list -> tactic"} \\
+  @{index_ML fold_goals_tac: "Proof.context -> thm list -> tactic"} \\
+  \end{mldecls}
+
+  \begin{description}
+
+  \item @{ML rewrite_rule}~@{text "ctxt rules thm"} rewrites the whole
+  theorem by the given rules.
+
+  \item @{ML rewrite_goals_rule}~@{text "ctxt rules thm"} rewrites the
+  outer premises of the given theorem.  Interpreting the same as a
+  goal state (\secref{sec:tactical-goals}) it means to rewrite all
+  subgoals (in the same manner as @{ML rewrite_goals_tac}).
+
+  \item @{ML rewrite_goal_tac}~@{text "ctxt rules i"} rewrites subgoal
+  @{text "i"} by the given rewrite rules.
+
+  \item @{ML rewrite_goals_tac}~@{text "ctxt rules"} rewrites all subgoals
+  by the given rewrite rules.
+
+  \item @{ML fold_goals_tac}~@{text "ctxt rules"} essentially uses @{ML
+  rewrite_goals_tac} with the symmetric form of each member of @{text
+  "rules"}, re-ordered to fold longer expression first.  This supports
+  to idea to fold primitive definitions that appear in expended form
+  in the proof state.
+
+  \end{description}
+*}
+
+end