src/Doc/IsarImplementation/Eq.thy
changeset 56420 b266e7a86485
parent 56419 f47de9e82b0f
child 56431 4eb88149c7b2
--- a/src/Doc/IsarImplementation/Eq.thy	Sat Apr 05 17:52:29 2014 +0100
+++ /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
@@ -1,126 +0,0 @@
-theory Eq
-imports Base
-begin
-
-chapter {* Equational reasoning *}
-
-text {* Equality is one of the most fundamental concepts of
-  mathematics.  The Isabelle/Pure logic (\chref{ch:logic}) provides a
-  builtin relation @{text "\<equiv> :: \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> prop"} that expresses equality
-  of arbitrary terms (or propositions) at the framework level, as
-  expressed by certain basic inference rules (\secref{sec:eq-rules}).
-
-  Equational reasoning means to replace equals by equals, using
-  reflexivity and transitivity to form chains of replacement steps,
-  and congruence rules to access sub-structures.  Conversions
-  (\secref{sec:conv}) provide a convenient framework to compose basic
-  equational steps to build specific equational reasoning tools.
-
-  Higher-order matching is able to provide suitable instantiations for
-  giving equality rules, which leads to the versatile concept of
-  @{text "\<lambda>"}-term rewriting (\secref{sec:rewriting}).  Internally
-  this is based on the general-purpose Simplifier engine of Isabelle,
-  which is more specific and more efficient than plain conversions.
-
-  Object-logics usually introduce specific notions of equality or
-  equivalence, and relate it with the Pure equality.  This enables to
-  re-use the Pure tools for equational reasoning for particular
-  object-logic connectives as well.
-*}
-
-
-section {* Basic equality rules \label{sec:eq-rules} *}
-
-text {* Isabelle/Pure uses @{text "\<equiv>"} for equality of arbitrary
-  terms, which includes equivalence of propositions of the logical
-  framework.  The conceptual axiomatization of the constant @{text "\<equiv>
-  :: \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> \<alpha> \<Rightarrow> prop"} is given in \figref{fig:pure-equality}.  The
-  inference kernel presents slightly different equality rules, which
-  may be understood as derived rules from this minimal axiomatization.
-  The Pure theory also provides some theorems that express the same
-  reasoning schemes as theorems that can be composed like object-level
-  rules as explained in \secref{sec:obj-rules}.
-
-  For example, @{ML Thm.symmetric} as Pure inference is an ML function
-  that maps a theorem @{text "th"} stating @{text "t \<equiv> u"} to one
-  stating @{text "u \<equiv> t"}.  In contrast, @{thm [source]
-  Pure.symmetric} as Pure theorem expresses the same reasoning in
-  declarative form.  If used like @{text "th [THEN Pure.symmetric]"}
-  in Isar source notation, it achieves a similar effect as the ML
-  inference function, although the rule attribute @{attribute THEN} or
-  ML operator @{ML "op RS"} involve the full machinery of higher-order
-  unification (modulo @{text "\<beta>\<eta>"}-conversion) and lifting of @{text
-  "\<And>/\<Longrightarrow>"} contexts. *}
-
-text %mlref {*
-  \begin{mldecls}
-  @{index_ML Thm.reflexive: "cterm -> thm"} \\
-  @{index_ML Thm.symmetric: "thm -> thm"} \\
-  @{index_ML Thm.transitive: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\
-  @{index_ML Thm.abstract_rule: "string -> cterm -> thm -> thm"} \\
-  @{index_ML Thm.combination: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\[0.5ex]
-  @{index_ML Thm.equal_intr: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\
-  @{index_ML Thm.equal_elim: "thm -> thm -> thm"} \\
-  \end{mldecls}
-
-  See also @{file "~~/src/Pure/thm.ML" } for further description of
-  these inference rules, and a few more for primitive @{text "\<beta>"} and
-  @{text "\<eta>"} conversions.  Note that @{text "\<alpha>"} conversion is
-  implicit due to the representation of terms with de-Bruijn indices
-  (\secref{sec:terms}). *}
-
-
-section {* Conversions \label{sec:conv} *}
-
-text {*
-  %FIXME
-
-  The classic article that introduces the concept of conversion (for
-  Cambridge LCF) is \cite{paulson:1983}.
-*}
-
-
-section {* Rewriting \label{sec:rewriting} *}
-
-text {* Rewriting normalizes a given term (theorem or goal) by
-  replacing instances of given equalities @{text "t \<equiv> u"} in subterms.
-  Rewriting continues until no rewrites are applicable to any subterm.
-  This may be used to unfold simple definitions of the form @{text "f
-  x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>n \<equiv> u"}, but is slightly more general than that.
-*}
-
-text %mlref {*
-  \begin{mldecls}
-  @{index_ML rewrite_rule: "Proof.context -> thm list -> thm -> thm"} \\
-  @{index_ML rewrite_goals_rule: "Proof.context -> thm list -> thm -> thm"} \\
-  @{index_ML rewrite_goal_tac: "Proof.context -> thm list -> int -> tactic"} \\
-  @{index_ML rewrite_goals_tac: "Proof.context -> thm list -> tactic"} \\
-  @{index_ML fold_goals_tac: "Proof.context -> thm list -> tactic"} \\
-  \end{mldecls}
-
-  \begin{description}
-
-  \item @{ML rewrite_rule}~@{text "ctxt rules thm"} rewrites the whole
-  theorem by the given rules.
-
-  \item @{ML rewrite_goals_rule}~@{text "ctxt rules thm"} rewrites the
-  outer premises of the given theorem.  Interpreting the same as a
-  goal state (\secref{sec:tactical-goals}) it means to rewrite all
-  subgoals (in the same manner as @{ML rewrite_goals_tac}).
-
-  \item @{ML rewrite_goal_tac}~@{text "ctxt rules i"} rewrites subgoal
-  @{text "i"} by the given rewrite rules.
-
-  \item @{ML rewrite_goals_tac}~@{text "ctxt rules"} rewrites all subgoals
-  by the given rewrite rules.
-
-  \item @{ML fold_goals_tac}~@{text "ctxt rules"} essentially uses @{ML
-  rewrite_goals_tac} with the symmetric form of each member of @{text
-  "rules"}, re-ordered to fold longer expression first.  This supports
-  to idea to fold primitive definitions that appear in expended form
-  in the proof state.
-
-  \end{description}
-*}
-
-end