\chapter{Generic tools and packages}\label{ch:gen-tools}
\section{Theory specification commands}
\subsection{Axiomatic type classes}\label{sec:axclass}
\indexisarcmd{axclass}\indexisarcmd{instance}\indexisarmeth{intro-classes}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{axclass} & : & \isartrans{theory}{theory} \\
\isarcmd{instance} & : & \isartrans{theory}{proof(prove)} \\
intro_classes & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
Axiomatic type classes are provided by Isabelle/Pure as a \emph{definitional}
interface to type classes (cf.~\S\ref{sec:classes}). Thus any object logic
may make use of this light-weight mechanism of abstract theories
\cite{Wenzel:1997:TPHOL}. There is also a tutorial on using axiomatic type
classes in Isabelle \cite{isabelle-axclass} that is part of the standard
Isabelle documentation.
\begin{rail}
'axclass' classdecl (axmdecl prop +)
;
'instance' (nameref ('<' | subseteq) nameref | nameref '::' arity)
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\AXCLASS~c \subseteq \vec c~~axms$] defines an axiomatic type class as
the intersection of existing classes, with additional axioms holding. Class
axioms may not contain more than one type variable. The class axioms (with
implicit sort constraints added) are bound to the given names. Furthermore
a class introduction rule is generated (being bound as $c{.}intro$); this
rule is employed by method $intro_classes$ to support instantiation proofs
of this class.
The ``axioms'' are stored as theorems according to the given name
specifications, adding the class name $c$ as name space prefix; the same
facts are also stored collectively as $c{\dtt}axioms$.
\item [$\INSTANCE~c@1 \subseteq c@2$ and $\INSTANCE~t :: (\vec s)s$] setup a
goal stating a class relation or type arity. The proof would usually
proceed by $intro_classes$, and then establish the characteristic theorems
of the type classes involved. After finishing the proof, the theory will be
augmented by a type signature declaration corresponding to the resulting
theorem.
\item [$intro_classes$] repeatedly expands all class introduction rules of
this theory. Note that this method usually needs not be named explicitly,
as it is already included in the default proof step (of $\PROOFNAME$ etc.).
In particular, instantiation of trivial (syntactic) classes may be performed
by a single ``$\DDOT$'' proof step.
\end{descr}
\subsection{Locales and local contexts}\label{sec:locale}
Locales are named local contexts, consisting of a list of declaration elements
that are modeled after the Isar proof context commands (cf.\
\S\ref{sec:proof-context}).
\subsubsection{Localized commands}
Existing locales may be augmented later on by adding new facts. Note that the
actual context definition may not be changed! Several theory commands that
produce facts in some way are available in ``localized'' versions, referring
to a named locale instead of the global theory context.
\indexouternonterm{locale}
\begin{rail}
locale: '(' 'in' name ')'
;
\end{rail}
Emerging facts of localized commands are stored in two versions, both in the
target locale and the theory (after export). The latter view produces a
qualified binding, using the locale name as a name space prefix.
For example, ``$\LEMMAS~(\IN~loc)~a = \vec b$'' retrieves facts $\vec b$ from
the locale context of $loc$ and augments its body by an appropriate
``$\isarkeyword{notes}$'' element (see below). The exported view of $a$,
after discharging the locale context, is stored as $loc{.}a$ within the global
theory. A localized goal ``$\LEMMANAME~(\IN~loc)~a:~\phi$'' works similarly,
only that the fact emerges through the subsequent proof, which may refer to
the full infrastructure of the locale context (covering local parameters with
typing and concrete syntax, assumptions, definitions etc.). Most notably,
fact declarations of the locale are active during the proof as well (e.g.\
local $simp$ rules).
As a general principle, results exported from a locale context acquire
additional premises according to the specification. Usually this is only a
single predicate according to the standard ``closed'' view of locale
specifications.
\subsubsection{Locale specifications}
\indexisarcmd{locale}\indexisarcmd{print-locale}\indexisarcmd{print-locales}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{locale} & : & \isarkeep{theory} \\
\isarcmd{print_locale}^* & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
\isarcmd{print_locales}^* & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
\end{matharray}
\indexouternonterm{contextexpr}\indexouternonterm{contextelem}
\railalias{printlocale}{print\_locale}
\railterm{printlocale}
\begin{rail}
'locale' ('(open)')? name ('=' localeexpr)?
;
printlocale localeexpr
;
localeexpr: ((contextexpr '+' (contextelem+)) | contextexpr | (contextelem+))
;
contextexpr: nameref | '(' contextexpr ')' |
(contextexpr (name+)) | (contextexpr + '+')
;
contextelem: fixes | assumes | defines | notes | includes
;
fixes: 'fixes' (name ('::' type)? structmixfix? + 'and')
;
assumes: 'assumes' (thmdecl? props + 'and')
;
defines: 'defines' (thmdecl? prop proppat? + 'and')
;
notes: 'notes' (thmdef? thmrefs + 'and')
;
includes: 'includes' contextexpr
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\LOCALE~loc~=~import~+~body$] defines a new locale $loc$ as a context
consisting of a certain view of existing locales ($import$) plus some
additional elements ($body$). Both $import$ and $body$ are optional; the
degenerate form $\LOCALE~loc$ defines an empty locale, which may still be
useful to collect declarations of facts later on. Type-inference on locale
expressions automatically takes care of the most general typing that the
combined context elements may acquire.
The $import$ consists of a structured context expression, consisting of
references to existing locales, renamed contexts, or merged contexts.
Renaming uses positional notation: $c~\vec x$ means that (a prefix) the
fixed parameters of context $c$ are named according to $\vec x$; a
``\texttt{_}'' (underscore).\indexisarthm{_@\texttt{_}} means to skip that
position. Also note that concrete syntax only works with the original name.
Merging proceeds from left-to-right, suppressing any duplicates stemming
from different paths through the import hierarchy.
The $body$ consists of basic context elements, further context expressions
may be included as well.
\begin{descr}
\item [$\FIXES{~x::\tau~(mx)}$] declares a local parameter of type $\tau$
and mixfix annotation $mx$ (both are optional). The special syntax
declaration ``$(structure)$'' means that $x$ may be referenced
implicitly in this context.
\item [$\ASSUMES{a}{\vec\phi}$] introduces local premises, similar to
$\ASSUMENAME$ within a proof (cf.\ \S\ref{sec:proof-context}).
\item [$\DEFINES{a}{x \equiv t}$] defines a previously declared parameter.
This is close to $\DEFNAME$ within a proof (cf.\
\S\ref{sec:proof-context}), but $\DEFINESNAME$ takes an equational
proposition instead of variable-term pair. The left-hand side of the
equation may have additional arguments, e.g.\ ``$\DEFINES{}{f~\vec x
\equiv t}$''.
\item [$\NOTES{a}{\vec b}$] reconsiders facts within a local context. Most
notably, this may include arbitrary declarations in any attribute
specifications included here, e.g.\ a local $simp$ rule.
\item [$\INCLUDES{c}$] copies the specified context in a statically scoped
manner. Only available in the long goal format of \S\ref{sec:goals}.
In contrast, the initial $import$ specification of a locale expression
maintains a dynamic relation to the locales being referenced (benefiting
from any later fact declarations in the obvious manner).
\end{descr}
Note that ``$\IS{p}$'' patterns given in the syntax of $\ASSUMESNAME$ and
$\DEFINESNAME$ above are illegal in locale definitions. In the long goal
format of \S\ref{sec:goals}, term bindings may be included as expected,
though.
\medskip By default, locale specifications are ``closed up'' by turning the
given text into a predicate definition $loc_axioms$ and deriving the
original assumptions as local lemmas (modulo local definitions). The
predicate statement covers only the newly specified assumptions, omitting
the content of included locale expressions. The full cumulative view is
only provided on export, involving another predicate $loc$ that refers to
the complete specification text.
In any case, the predicate arguments are those locale parameters that
actually occur in the respective piece of text. Also note that these
predicates operate at the meta-level in theory, but the locale packages
attempts to internalize statements according to the object-logic setup
(e.g.\ replacing $\Forall$ by $\forall$, and $\Imp$ by $\imp$ in HOL; see
also \S\ref{sec:object-logic}). Separate introduction rules
$loc_axioms.intro$ and $loc.intro$ are declared as well.
The $(open)$ option of a locale specification prevents both the current
$loc_axioms$ and cumulative $loc$ predicate constructions. Predicates are
also omitted for empty specification texts.
\item [$\isarkeyword{print_locale}~import~+~body$] prints the specified locale
expression in a flattened form. The notable special case
$\isarkeyword{print_locale}~loc$ just prints the contents of the named
locale, but keep in mind that type-inference will normalize type variables
according to the usual alphabetical order.
\item [$\isarkeyword{print_locales}$] prints the names of all locales of the
current theory.
\end{descr}
\subsubsection{Interpretation of locales}
Locale expressions (more precisely, \emph{context expressions}) may be
instantiated, and the instantiated facts added to the current context.
This requires a proof of the instantiated specification and is called
\emph{locale interpretation}. Interpretation is possible in theories
($\isarcmd{interpretation}$) and proof contexts
($\isarcmd{interpret}$).
\indexisarcmd{interpretation}\indexisarcmd{interpret}
\indexisarcmd{print-interps}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{interpretation} & : & \isartrans{theory}{proof(prove)} \\
\isarcmd{interpret} & : & \isartrans{proof(state) ~|~ proof(chain)}{proof(prove)} \\
\isarcmd{print_interps}^* & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
\end{matharray}
\indexouternonterm{interp}
\railalias{printinterps}{print\_interps}
\railterm{printinterps}
\begin{rail}
'interpretation' interp
;
'interpret' interp
;
printinterps name
;
interp: thmdecl? contextexpr ('[' (inst+) ']')?
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\isarcmd{interpretation}~expr~insts$]
interprets $expr$ in the theory. The instantiation is positional.
All parameters must receive an instantiation term --- with the
exception of defined parameters. These are, if omitted, derived
from the defining equation and other instantiations. Use ``\_'' to
omit an instantiation term. Free variables are automatically
generalized.
The context expression may be preceded by a name and/or attributes.
These take effect in the post-processing of facts. The name is used
to prefix fact names, for example to avoid accidental hiding of
other facts. Attributes are applied after attributes of the
interpreted facts.
The command is aware of interpretations already active in the
theory. No proof obligations are generated for those, neither is
post-processing applied to their facts. This avoids duplication of
interpreted facts, in particular. Note that, in the case of a
locale with import, parts of the interpretation may already be
active. The command will only generate proof obligations and add
facts for new parts.
Adding facts to locales has the
effect of adding interpreted facts to the theory for all active
interpretations also.
\item [$\isarcmd{interpret}~expr~insts$]
interprets $expr$ in the proof context and is otherwise similar to
the previous command. Free variables in instantiations are not
generalized, however.
\item [$\isarcmd{print_interps}~loc$]
prints the interpretations of a particular locale $loc$ that are
active in the current context, either theory or proof context.
\end{descr}
\begin{warn}
Since attributes are applied to interpreted theorems, interpretation
may modify the current simpset and claset. Take this into
account when choosing attributes for local theorems.
\end{warn}
\section{Derived proof schemes}
\subsection{Generalized elimination}\label{sec:obtain}
\indexisarcmd{obtain}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{obtain} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(prove)} \\
\end{matharray}
Generalized elimination means that additional elements with certain properties
may be introduced in the current context, by virtue of a locally proven
``soundness statement''. Technically speaking, the $\OBTAINNAME$ language
element is like a declaration of $\FIXNAME$ and $\ASSUMENAME$ (see also see
\S\ref{sec:proof-context}), together with a soundness proof of its additional
claim. According to the nature of existential reasoning, assumptions get
eliminated from any result exported from the context later, provided that the
corresponding parameters do \emph{not} occur in the conclusion.
\begin{rail}
'obtain' (vars + 'and') 'where' (props + 'and')
;
\end{rail}
$\OBTAINNAME$ is defined as a derived Isar command as follows, where $\vec b$
shall refer to (optional) facts indicated for forward chaining.
\begin{matharray}{l}
\langle facts~\vec b\rangle \\
\OBTAIN{\vec x}{a}{\vec \phi}~~\langle proof\rangle \equiv {} \\[1ex]
\quad \HAVE{}{\All{thesis} (\All{\vec x} \vec\phi \Imp thesis) \Imp thesis} \\
\quad \PROOF{succeed} \\
\qquad \FIX{thesis} \\
\qquad \ASSUME{that~[intro?]}{\All{\vec x} \vec\phi \Imp thesis} \\
\qquad \THUS{}{thesis} \\
\quad\qquad \APPLY{-} \\
\quad\qquad \USING{\vec b}~~\langle proof\rangle \\
\quad \QED{} \\
\quad \FIX{\vec x}~\ASSUMENAME^\ast~a\colon~\vec\phi \\
\end{matharray}
Typically, the soundness proof is relatively straight-forward, often just by
canonical automated tools such as ``$\BY{simp}$'' or ``$\BY{blast}$''.
Accordingly, the ``$that$'' reduction above is declared as simplification and
introduction rule.
\medskip
In a sense, $\OBTAINNAME$ represents at the level of Isar proofs what would be
meta-logical existential quantifiers and conjunctions. This concept has a
broad range of useful applications, ranging from plain elimination (or
introduction) of object-level existentials and conjunctions, to elimination
over results of symbolic evaluation of recursive definitions, for example.
Also note that $\OBTAINNAME$ without parameters acts much like $\HAVENAME$,
where the result is treated as a genuine assumption.
\subsection{Calculational reasoning}\label{sec:calculation}
\indexisarcmd{also}\indexisarcmd{finally}
\indexisarcmd{moreover}\indexisarcmd{ultimately}
\indexisarcmd{print-trans-rules}
\indexisaratt{trans}\indexisaratt{sym}\indexisaratt{symmetric}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{also} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
\isarcmd{finally} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(chain)} \\
\isarcmd{moreover} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
\isarcmd{ultimately} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(chain)} \\
\isarcmd{print_trans_rules}^* & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
trans & : & \isaratt \\
sym & : & \isaratt \\
symmetric & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
Calculational proof is forward reasoning with implicit application of
transitivity rules (such those of $=$, $\leq$, $<$). Isabelle/Isar maintains
an auxiliary register $calculation$\indexisarthm{calculation} for accumulating
results obtained by transitivity composed with the current result. Command
$\ALSO$ updates $calculation$ involving $this$, while $\FINALLY$ exhibits the
final $calculation$ by forward chaining towards the next goal statement. Both
commands require valid current facts, i.e.\ may occur only after commands that
produce theorems such as $\ASSUMENAME$, $\NOTENAME$, or some finished proof of
$\HAVENAME$, $\SHOWNAME$ etc. The $\MOREOVER$ and $\ULTIMATELY$ commands are
similar to $\ALSO$ and $\FINALLY$, but only collect further results in
$calculation$ without applying any rules yet.
Also note that the implicit term abbreviation ``$\dots$'' has its canonical
application with calculational proofs. It refers to the argument of the
preceding statement. (The argument of a curried infix expression happens to be
its right-hand side.)
Isabelle/Isar calculations are implicitly subject to block structure in the
sense that new threads of calculational reasoning are commenced for any new
block (as opened by a local goal, for example). This means that, apart from
being able to nest calculations, there is no separate \emph{begin-calculation}
command required.
\medskip
The Isar calculation proof commands may be defined as follows:\footnote{We
suppress internal bookkeeping such as proper handling of block-structure.}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\ALSO@0 & \equiv & \NOTE{calculation}{this} \\
\ALSO@{n+1} & \equiv & \NOTE{calculation}{trans~[OF~calculation~this]} \\[0.5ex]
\FINALLY & \equiv & \ALSO~\FROM{calculation} \\
\MOREOVER & \equiv & \NOTE{calculation}{calculation~this} \\
\ULTIMATELY & \equiv & \MOREOVER~\FROM{calculation} \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
('also' | 'finally') ('(' thmrefs ')')?
;
'trans' (() | 'add' | 'del')
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\ALSO~(\vec a)$] maintains the auxiliary $calculation$ register as
follows. The first occurrence of $\ALSO$ in some calculational thread
initializes $calculation$ by $this$. Any subsequent $\ALSO$ on the same
level of block-structure updates $calculation$ by some transitivity rule
applied to $calculation$ and $this$ (in that order). Transitivity rules are
picked from the current context, unless alternative rules are given as
explicit arguments.
\item [$\FINALLY~(\vec a)$] maintaining $calculation$ in the same way as
$\ALSO$, and concludes the current calculational thread. The final result
is exhibited as fact for forward chaining towards the next goal. Basically,
$\FINALLY$ just abbreviates $\ALSO~\FROM{calculation}$. Note that
``$\FINALLY~\SHOW{}{\Var{thesis}}~\DOT$'' and
``$\FINALLY~\HAVE{}{\phi}~\DOT$'' are typical idioms for concluding
calculational proofs.
\item [$\MOREOVER$ and $\ULTIMATELY$] are analogous to $\ALSO$ and $\FINALLY$,
but collect results only, without applying rules.
\item [$\isarkeyword{print_trans_rules}$] prints the list of transitivity
rules (for calculational commands $\ALSO$ and $\FINALLY$) and symmetry rules
(for the $symmetric$ operation and single step elimination patters) of the
current context.
\item [$trans$] declares theorems as transitivity rules.
\item [$sym$] declares symmetry rules.
\item [$symmetric$] resolves a theorem with some rule declared as $sym$ in the
current context. For example, ``$\ASSUME{[symmetric]}{x = y}$'' produces a
swapped fact derived from that assumption.
In structured proof texts it is often more appropriate to use an explicit
single-step elimination proof, such as ``$\ASSUME{}{x = y}~\HENCE{}{y =
x}~\DDOT$''. The very same rules known to $symmetric$ are declared as
$elim?$ as well.
\end{descr}
\section{Proof tools}
\subsection{Miscellaneous methods and attributes}\label{sec:misc-meth-att}
\indexisarmeth{unfold}\indexisarmeth{fold}\indexisarmeth{insert}
\indexisarmeth{erule}\indexisarmeth{drule}\indexisarmeth{frule}
\indexisarmeth{fail}\indexisarmeth{succeed}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
unfold & : & \isarmeth \\
fold & : & \isarmeth \\
insert & : & \isarmeth \\[0.5ex]
erule^* & : & \isarmeth \\
drule^* & : & \isarmeth \\
frule^* & : & \isarmeth \\
succeed & : & \isarmeth \\
fail & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
('fold' | 'unfold' | 'insert') thmrefs
;
('erule' | 'drule' | 'frule') ('('nat')')? thmrefs
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$unfold~\vec a$ and $fold~\vec a$] expand (or fold back again) the
given meta-level definitions throughout all goals; any chained facts
provided are inserted into the goal and subject to rewriting as well.
\item [$insert~\vec a$] inserts theorems as facts into all goals of the proof
state. Note that current facts indicated for forward chaining are ignored.
\item [$erule~\vec a$, $drule~\vec a$, and $frule~\vec a$] are similar to the
basic $rule$ method (see \S\ref{sec:pure-meth-att}), but apply rules by
elim-resolution, destruct-resolution, and forward-resolution, respectively
\cite{isabelle-ref}. The optional natural number argument (default $0$)
specifies additional assumption steps to be performed here.
Note that these methods are improper ones, mainly serving for
experimentation and tactic script emulation. Different modes of basic rule
application are usually expressed in Isar at the proof language level,
rather than via implicit proof state manipulations. For example, a proper
single-step elimination would be done using the plain $rule$ method, with
forward chaining of current facts.
\item [$succeed$] yields a single (unchanged) result; it is the identity of
the ``\texttt{,}'' method combinator (cf.\ \S\ref{sec:syn-meth}).
\item [$fail$] yields an empty result sequence; it is the identity of the
``\texttt{|}'' method combinator (cf.\ \S\ref{sec:syn-meth}).
\end{descr}
\indexisaratt{tagged}\indexisaratt{untagged}
\indexisaratt{THEN}\indexisaratt{COMP}
\indexisaratt{unfolded}\indexisaratt{folded}
\indexisaratt{standard}\indexisarattof{Pure}{elim-format}
\indexisaratt{no-vars}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
tagged & : & \isaratt \\
untagged & : & \isaratt \\[0.5ex]
THEN & : & \isaratt \\
COMP & : & \isaratt \\[0.5ex]
unfolded & : & \isaratt \\
folded & : & \isaratt \\[0.5ex]
elim_format & : & \isaratt \\
standard^* & : & \isaratt \\
no_vars^* & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
'tagged' (nameref+)
;
'untagged' name
;
('THEN' | 'COMP') ('[' nat ']')? thmref
;
('unfolded' | 'folded') thmrefs
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$tagged~name~args$ and $untagged~name$] add and remove $tags$ of some
theorem. Tags may be any list of strings that serve as comment for some
tools (e.g.\ $\LEMMANAME$ causes the tag ``$lemma$'' to be added to the
result). The first string is considered the tag name, the rest its
arguments. Note that untag removes any tags of the same name.
\item [$THEN~a$ and $COMP~a$] compose rules by resolution. $THEN$ resolves
with the first premise of $a$ (an alternative position may be also
specified); the $COMP$ version skips the automatic lifting process that is
normally intended (cf.\ \texttt{RS} and \texttt{COMP} in
\cite[\S5]{isabelle-ref}).
\item [$unfolded~\vec a$ and $folded~\vec a$] expand and fold back again the
given meta-level definitions throughout a rule.
\item [$elim_format$] turns a destruction rule into elimination rule format,
by resolving with the rule $\PROP A \Imp (\PROP A \Imp \PROP B) \Imp \PROP
B$.
Note that the Classical Reasoner (\S\ref{sec:classical}) provides its own
version of this operation.
\item [$standard$] puts a theorem into the standard form of object-rules at
the outermost theory level. Note that this operation violates the local
proof context (including active locales).
\item [$no_vars$] replaces schematic variables by free ones; this is mainly
for tuning output of pretty printed theorems.
\end{descr}
\subsection{Further tactic emulations}\label{sec:tactics}
The following improper proof methods emulate traditional tactics. These admit
direct access to the goal state, which is normally considered harmful! In
particular, this may involve both numbered goal addressing (default 1), and
dynamic instantiation within the scope of some subgoal.
\begin{warn}
Dynamic instantiations refer to universally quantified parameters of
a subgoal (the dynamic context) rather than fixed variables and term
abbreviations of a (static) Isar context.
\end{warn}
Tactic emulation methods, unlike their ML counterparts, admit
simultaneous instantiation from both dynamic and static contexts. If
names occur in both contexts goal parameters hide locally fixed
variables. Likewise, schematic variables refer to term abbreviations,
if present in the static context. Otherwise the schematic variable is
interpreted as a schematic variable and left to be solved by unification
with certain parts of the subgoal.
Note that the tactic emulation proof methods in Isabelle/Isar are consistently
named $foo_tac$. Note also that variable names occurring on left hand sides
of instantiations must be preceded by a question mark if they coincide with
a keyword or contain dots.
This is consistent with the attribute $where$ (see \S\ref{sec:pure-meth-att}).
\indexisarmeth{rule-tac}\indexisarmeth{erule-tac}
\indexisarmeth{drule-tac}\indexisarmeth{frule-tac}
\indexisarmeth{cut-tac}\indexisarmeth{thin-tac}
\indexisarmeth{subgoal-tac}\indexisarmeth{rename-tac}
\indexisarmeth{rotate-tac}\indexisarmeth{tactic}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
rule_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
erule_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
drule_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
frule_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
cut_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
thin_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
subgoal_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
rename_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
rotate_tac^* & : & \isarmeth \\
tactic^* & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
\railalias{ruletac}{rule\_tac}
\railterm{ruletac}
\railalias{eruletac}{erule\_tac}
\railterm{eruletac}
\railalias{druletac}{drule\_tac}
\railterm{druletac}
\railalias{fruletac}{frule\_tac}
\railterm{fruletac}
\railalias{cuttac}{cut\_tac}
\railterm{cuttac}
\railalias{thintac}{thin\_tac}
\railterm{thintac}
\railalias{subgoaltac}{subgoal\_tac}
\railterm{subgoaltac}
\railalias{renametac}{rename\_tac}
\railterm{renametac}
\railalias{rotatetac}{rotate\_tac}
\railterm{rotatetac}
\begin{rail}
( ruletac | eruletac | druletac | fruletac | cuttac | thintac ) goalspec?
( insts thmref | thmrefs )
;
subgoaltac goalspec? (prop +)
;
renametac goalspec? (name +)
;
rotatetac goalspec? int?
;
'tactic' text
;
insts: ((name '=' term) + 'and') 'in'
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$rule_tac$ etc.] do resolution of rules with explicit instantiation.
This works the same way as the ML tactics \texttt{res_inst_tac} etc. (see
\cite[\S3]{isabelle-ref}).
Multiple rules may be only given if there is no instantiation; then
$rule_tac$ is the same as \texttt{resolve_tac} in ML (see
\cite[\S3]{isabelle-ref}).
\item [$cut_tac$] inserts facts into the proof state as assumption of a
subgoal, see also \texttt{cut_facts_tac} in \cite[\S3]{isabelle-ref}. Note
that the scope of schematic variables is spread over the main goal
statement. Instantiations may be given as well, see also ML tactic
\texttt{cut_inst_tac} in \cite[\S3]{isabelle-ref}.
\item [$thin_tac~\phi$] deletes the specified assumption from a subgoal; note
that $\phi$ may contain schematic variables. See also \texttt{thin_tac} in
\cite[\S3]{isabelle-ref}.
\item [$subgoal_tac~\phi$] adds $\phi$ as an assumption to a subgoal. See
also \texttt{subgoal_tac} and \texttt{subgoals_tac} in
\cite[\S3]{isabelle-ref}.
\item [$rename_tac~\vec x$] renames parameters of a goal according to the list
$\vec x$, which refers to the \emph{suffix} of variables.
\item [$rotate_tac~n$] rotates the assumptions of a goal by $n$ positions:
from right to left if $n$ is positive, and from left to right if $n$ is
negative; the default value is $1$. See also \texttt{rotate_tac} in
\cite[\S3]{isabelle-ref}.
\item [$tactic~text$] produces a proof method from any ML text of type
\texttt{tactic}. Apart from the usual ML environment and the current
implicit theory context, the ML code may refer to the following locally
bound values:
{\footnotesize\begin{verbatim}
val ctxt : Proof.context
val facts : thm list
val thm : string -> thm
val thms : string -> thm list
\end{verbatim}}
Here \texttt{ctxt} refers to the current proof context, \texttt{facts}
indicates any current facts for forward-chaining, and
\texttt{thm}~/~\texttt{thms} retrieve named facts (including global
theorems) from the context.
\end{descr}
\subsection{The Simplifier}\label{sec:simplifier}
\subsubsection{Simplification methods}
\indexisarmeth{simp}\indexisarmeth{simp-all}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
simp & : & \isarmeth \\
simp_all & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
\railalias{simpall}{simp\_all}
\railterm{simpall}
\railalias{noasm}{no\_asm}
\railterm{noasm}
\railalias{noasmsimp}{no\_asm\_simp}
\railterm{noasmsimp}
\railalias{noasmuse}{no\_asm\_use}
\railterm{noasmuse}
\railalias{asmlr}{asm\_lr}
\railterm{asmlr}
\indexouternonterm{simpmod}
\begin{rail}
('simp' | simpall) ('!' ?) opt? (simpmod *)
;
opt: '(' (noasm | noasmsimp | noasmuse | asmlr) ')'
;
simpmod: ('add' | 'del' | 'only' | 'cong' (() | 'add' | 'del') |
'split' (() | 'add' | 'del')) ':' thmrefs
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$simp$] invokes Isabelle's simplifier, after declaring additional rules
according to the arguments given. Note that the \railtterm{only} modifier
first removes all other rewrite rules, congruences, and looper tactics
(including splits), and then behaves like \railtterm{add}.
\medskip The \railtterm{cong} modifiers add or delete Simplifier congruence
rules (see also \cite{isabelle-ref}), the default is to add.
\medskip The \railtterm{split} modifiers add or delete rules for the
Splitter (see also \cite{isabelle-ref}), the default is to add. This works
only if the Simplifier method has been properly setup to include the
Splitter (all major object logics such HOL, HOLCF, FOL, ZF do this already).
\item [$simp_all$] is similar to $simp$, but acts on all goals (backwards from
the last to the first one).
\end{descr}
By default the Simplifier methods take local assumptions fully into account,
using equational assumptions in the subsequent normalization process, or
simplifying assumptions themselves (cf.\ \texttt{asm_full_simp_tac} in
\cite[\S10]{isabelle-ref}). In structured proofs this is usually quite well
behaved in practice: just the local premises of the actual goal are involved,
additional facts may be inserted via explicit forward-chaining (using $\THEN$,
$\FROMNAME$ etc.). The full context of assumptions is only included if the
``$!$'' (bang) argument is given, which should be used with some care, though.
Additional Simplifier options may be specified to tune the behavior further
(mostly for unstructured scripts with many accidental local facts):
``$(no_asm)$'' means assumptions are ignored completely (cf.\
\texttt{simp_tac}), ``$(no_asm_simp)$'' means assumptions are used in the
simplification of the conclusion but are not themselves simplified (cf.\
\texttt{asm_simp_tac}), and ``$(no_asm_use)$'' means assumptions are
simplified but are not used in the simplification of each other or the
conclusion (cf.\ \texttt{full_simp_tac}).
For compatibility reasons, there is also an option ``$(asm_lr)$'',
which means that an assumption is only used for simplifying assumptions
which are to the right of it (cf.\ \texttt{asm_lr_simp_tac}).
\medskip
The Splitter package is usually configured to work as part of the Simplifier.
The effect of repeatedly applying \texttt{split_tac} can be simulated by
``$(simp~only\colon~split\colon~\vec a)$''. There is also a separate $split$
method available for single-step case splitting.
\subsubsection{Declaring rules}
\indexisarcmd{print-simpset}
\indexisaratt{simp}\indexisaratt{split}\indexisaratt{cong}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{print_simpset}^* & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
simp & : & \isaratt \\
cong & : & \isaratt \\
split & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
('simp' | 'cong' | 'split') (() | 'add' | 'del')
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\isarcmd{print_simpset}$] prints the collection of rules declared to
the Simplifier, which is also known as ``simpset'' internally
\cite{isabelle-ref}. This is a diagnostic command; $undo$ does not apply.
\item [$simp$] declares simplification rules.
\item [$cong$] declares congruence rules.
\item [$split$] declares case split rules.
\end{descr}
\subsubsection{Forward simplification}
\indexisaratt{simplified}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
simplified & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
'simplified' opt? thmrefs?
;
opt: '(' (noasm | noasmsimp | noasmuse) ')'
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$simplified~\vec a$] causes a theorem to be simplified, either by
exactly the specified rules $\vec a$, or the implicit Simplifier context if
no arguments are given. The result is fully simplified by default,
including assumptions and conclusion; the options $no_asm$ etc.\ tune the
Simplifier in the same way as the for the $simp$ method.
Note that forward simplification restricts the simplifier to its most basic
operation of term rewriting; solver and looper tactics \cite{isabelle-ref}
are \emph{not} involved here. The $simplified$ attribute should be only
rarely required under normal circumstances.
\end{descr}
\subsubsection{Low-level equational reasoning}
\indexisarmeth{subst}\indexisarmeth{hypsubst}\indexisarmeth{split}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
subst^* & : & \isarmeth \\
hypsubst^* & : & \isarmeth \\
split^* & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
'subst' ('(' 'asm' ')')? ('(' (nat+) ')')? thmref
;
'split' ('(' 'asm' ')')? thmrefs
;
\end{rail}
These methods provide low-level facilities for equational reasoning that are
intended for specialized applications only. Normally, single step
calculations would be performed in a structured text (see also
\S\ref{sec:calculation}), while the Simplifier methods provide the canonical
way for automated normalization (see \S\ref{sec:simplifier}).
\begin{descr}
\item [$subst~eq$] performs a single substitution step using rule $eq$, which
may be either a meta or object equality.
\item [$subst~(asm)~eq$] substitutes in an assumption.
\item [$subst~(i \dots j)~eq$] performs several substitutions in the
conclusion. The numbers $i$ to $j$ indicate the positions to substitute at.
Positions are ordered from the top of the term tree moving down from left to
right. For example, in $(a+b)+(c+d)$ there are three positions where
commutativity of $+$ is applicable: 1 refers to the whole term, 2 to $a+b$
and 3 to $c+d$. If the positions in the list $(i \dots j)$ are
non-overlapping (e.g. $(2~3)$ in $(a+b)+(c+d)$) you may assume all
substitutions are performed simultaneously. Otherwise the behaviour of
$subst$ is not specified.
\item [$subst~(asm)~(i \dots j)~eq$] performs the substitutions in the
assumptions. Positions $1 \dots i@1$ refer
to assumption 1, positions $i@1+1 \dots i@2$ to assumption 2, and so on.
\item [$hypsubst$] performs substitution using some assumption; this only
works for equations of the form $x = t$ where $x$ is a free or bound
variable.
\item [$split~\vec a$] performs single-step case splitting using rules $thms$.
By default, splitting is performed in the conclusion of a goal; the $asm$
option indicates to operate on assumptions instead.
Note that the $simp$ method already involves repeated application of split
rules as declared in the current context.
\end{descr}
\subsection{The Classical Reasoner}\label{sec:classical}
\subsubsection{Basic methods}
\indexisarmeth{rule}\indexisarmeth{default}\indexisarmeth{contradiction}
\indexisarmeth{intro}\indexisarmeth{elim}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
rule & : & \isarmeth \\
contradiction & : & \isarmeth \\
intro & : & \isarmeth \\
elim & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
('rule' | 'intro' | 'elim') thmrefs?
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$rule$] as offered by the classical reasoner is a refinement over the
primitive one (see \S\ref{sec:pure-meth-att}). Both versions essentially
work the same, but the classical version observes the classical rule context
in addition to that of Isabelle/Pure.
Common object logics (HOL, ZF, etc.) declare a rich collection of classical
rules (even if these would qualify as intuitionistic ones), but only few
declarations to the rule context of Isabelle/Pure
(\S\ref{sec:pure-meth-att}).
\item [$contradiction$] solves some goal by contradiction, deriving any result
from both $\neg A$ and $A$. Chained facts, which are guaranteed to
participate, may appear in either order.
\item [$intro$ and $elim$] repeatedly refine some goal by intro- or
elim-resolution, after having inserted any chained facts. Exactly the rules
given as arguments are taken into account; this allows fine-tuned
decomposition of a proof problem, in contrast to common automated tools.
\end{descr}
\subsubsection{Automated methods}
\indexisarmeth{blast}\indexisarmeth{fast}\indexisarmeth{slow}
\indexisarmeth{best}\indexisarmeth{safe}\indexisarmeth{clarify}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
blast & : & \isarmeth \\
fast & : & \isarmeth \\
slow & : & \isarmeth \\
best & : & \isarmeth \\
safe & : & \isarmeth \\
clarify & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
\indexouternonterm{clamod}
\begin{rail}
'blast' ('!' ?) nat? (clamod *)
;
('fast' | 'slow' | 'best' | 'safe' | 'clarify') ('!' ?) (clamod *)
;
clamod: (('intro' | 'elim' | 'dest') ('!' | () | '?') | 'del') ':' thmrefs
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$blast$] refers to the classical tableau prover (see \texttt{blast_tac}
in \cite[\S11]{isabelle-ref}). The optional argument specifies a
user-supplied search bound (default 20).
\item [$fast$, $slow$, $best$, $safe$, and $clarify$] refer to the generic
classical reasoner. See \texttt{fast_tac}, \texttt{slow_tac},
\texttt{best_tac}, \texttt{safe_tac}, and \texttt{clarify_tac} in
\cite[\S11]{isabelle-ref} for more information.
\end{descr}
Any of the above methods support additional modifiers of the context of
classical rules. Their semantics is analogous to the attributes given before.
Facts provided by forward chaining are inserted into the goal before
commencing proof search. The ``!''~argument causes the full context of
assumptions to be included as well.
\subsubsection{Combined automated methods}\label{sec:clasimp}
\indexisarmeth{auto}\indexisarmeth{force}\indexisarmeth{clarsimp}
\indexisarmeth{fastsimp}\indexisarmeth{slowsimp}\indexisarmeth{bestsimp}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
auto & : & \isarmeth \\
force & : & \isarmeth \\
clarsimp & : & \isarmeth \\
fastsimp & : & \isarmeth \\
slowsimp & : & \isarmeth \\
bestsimp & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
\indexouternonterm{clasimpmod}
\begin{rail}
'auto' '!'? (nat nat)? (clasimpmod *)
;
('force' | 'clarsimp' | 'fastsimp' | 'slowsimp' | 'bestsimp') '!'? (clasimpmod *)
;
clasimpmod: ('simp' (() | 'add' | 'del' | 'only') |
('cong' | 'split') (() | 'add' | 'del') |
'iff' (((() | 'add') '?'?) | 'del') |
(('intro' | 'elim' | 'dest') ('!' | () | '?') | 'del')) ':' thmrefs
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$auto$, $force$, $clarsimp$, $fastsimp$, $slowsimp$, and $bestsimp$]
provide access to Isabelle's combined simplification and classical reasoning
tactics. These correspond to \texttt{auto_tac}, \texttt{force_tac},
\texttt{clarsimp_tac}, and Classical Reasoner tactics with the Simplifier
added as wrapper, see \cite[\S11]{isabelle-ref} for more information. The
modifier arguments correspond to those given in \S\ref{sec:simplifier} and
\S\ref{sec:classical}. Just note that the ones related to the Simplifier
are prefixed by \railtterm{simp} here.
Facts provided by forward chaining are inserted into the goal before doing
the search. The ``!''~argument causes the full context of assumptions to be
included as well.
\end{descr}
\subsubsection{Declaring rules}
\indexisarcmd{print-claset}
\indexisaratt{intro}\indexisaratt{elim}\indexisaratt{dest}
\indexisaratt{iff}\indexisaratt{rule}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{print_claset}^* & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
intro & : & \isaratt \\
elim & : & \isaratt \\
dest & : & \isaratt \\
rule & : & \isaratt \\
iff & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
('intro' | 'elim' | 'dest') ('!' | () | '?')
;
'rule' 'del'
;
'iff' (((() | 'add') '?'?) | 'del')
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\isarcmd{print_claset}$] prints the collection of rules declared to
the Classical Reasoner, which is also known as ``simpset'' internally
\cite{isabelle-ref}. This is a diagnostic command; $undo$ does not apply.
\item [$intro$, $elim$, and $dest$] declare introduction, elimination, and
destruction rules, respectively. By default, rules are considered as
\emph{unsafe} (i.e.\ not applied blindly without backtracking), while a
single ``!'' classifies as \emph{safe}. Rule declarations marked by ``?''
coincide with those of Isabelle/Pure, cf.\ \S\ref{sec:pure-meth-att} (i.e.\
are only applied in single steps of the $rule$ method).
\item [$rule~del$] deletes introduction, elimination, or destruction rules from
the context.
\item [$iff$] declares logical equivalences to the Simplifier and the
Classical reasoner at the same time. Non-conditional rules result in a
``safe'' introduction and elimination pair; conditional ones are considered
``unsafe''. Rules with negative conclusion are automatically inverted
(using $\neg$ elimination internally).
The ``?'' version of $iff$ declares rules to the Isabelle/Pure context only,
and omits the Simplifier declaration.
\end{descr}
\subsubsection{Classical operations}
\indexisaratt{elim-format}\indexisaratt{swapped}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
elim_format & : & \isaratt \\
swapped & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{descr}
\item [$elim_format$] turns a destruction rule into elimination rule format;
this operation is similar to the the intuitionistic version
(\S\ref{sec:misc-meth-att}), but each premise of the resulting rule acquires
an additional local fact of the negated main thesis; according to the
classical principle $(\neg A \Imp A) \Imp A$.
\item [$swapped$] turns an introduction rule into an elimination, by resolving
with the classical swap principle $(\neg B \Imp A) \Imp (\neg A \Imp B)$.
\end{descr}
\subsection{Proof by cases and induction}\label{sec:cases-induct}
\subsubsection{Rule contexts}
\indexisarcmd{case}\indexisarcmd{print-cases}
\indexisaratt{case-names}\indexisaratt{params}\indexisaratt{consumes}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{case} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
\isarcmd{print_cases}^* & : & \isarkeep{proof} \\
case_names & : & \isaratt \\
params & : & \isaratt \\
consumes & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
Basically, Isar proof contexts are built up explicitly using commands like
$\FIXNAME$, $\ASSUMENAME$ etc.\ (see \S\ref{sec:proof-context}). In typical
verification tasks this can become hard to manage, though. In particular, a
large number of local contexts may emerge from case analysis or induction over
inductive sets and types.
\medskip
The $\CASENAME$ command provides a shorthand to refer to certain parts of
logical context symbolically. Proof methods may provide an environment of
named ``cases'' of the form $c\colon \vec x, \vec \phi$. Then the effect of
``$\CASE{c}$'' is that of ``$\FIX{\vec x}~\ASSUME{c}{\vec\phi}$''. Term
bindings may be covered as well, such as $\Var{case}$ for the intended
conclusion.
Normally the ``terminology'' of a case value (i.e.\ the parameters $\vec x$)
are marked as hidden. Using the explicit form ``$\CASE{(c~\vec x)}$'' enables
proof writers to choose their own names for the subsequent proof text.
\medskip
It is important to note that $\CASENAME$ does \emph{not} provide direct means
to peek at the current goal state, which is generally considered
non-observable in Isar. The text of the cases basically emerge from standard
elimination or induction rules, which in turn are derived from previous theory
specifications in a canonical way (say from $\isarkeyword{inductive}$
definitions).
Named cases may be exhibited in the current proof context only if both the
proof method and the rules involved support this. Case names and parameters
of basic rules may be declared by hand as well, by using appropriate
attributes. Thus variant versions of rules that have been derived manually
may be used in advanced case analysis later.
\railalias{casenames}{case\_names}
\railterm{casenames}
\begin{rail}
'case' (caseref | '(' caseref ((name | underscore) +) ')')
;
caseref: nameref attributes?
;
casenames (name +)
;
'params' ((name *) + 'and')
;
'consumes' nat?
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\CASE{(c~\vec x)}$] invokes a named local context $c\colon \vec x,
\vec \phi$, as provided by an appropriate proof method (such as $cases$ and
$induct$, see \S\ref{sec:cases-induct-meth}). The command ``$\CASE{(c~\vec
x)}$'' abbreviates ``$\FIX{\vec x}~\ASSUME{c}{\vec\phi}$''.
\item [$\isarkeyword{print_cases}$] prints all local contexts of the current
state, using Isar proof language notation. This is a diagnostic command;
$undo$ does not apply.
\item [$case_names~\vec c$] declares names for the local contexts of premises
of some theorem; $\vec c$ refers to the \emph{suffix} of the list of
premises.
\item [$params~\vec p@1 \dots \vec p@n$] renames the innermost parameters of
premises $1, \dots, n$ of some theorem. An empty list of names may be given
to skip positions, leaving the present parameters unchanged.
Note that the default usage of case rules does \emph{not} directly expose
parameters to the proof context (see also \S\ref{sec:cases-induct-meth}).
\item [$consumes~n$] declares the number of ``major premises'' of a rule,
i.e.\ the number of facts to be consumed when it is applied by an
appropriate proof method (cf.\ \S\ref{sec:cases-induct-meth}). The default
value of $consumes$ is $n = 1$, which is appropriate for the usual kind of
cases and induction rules for inductive sets (cf.\
\S\ref{sec:hol-inductive}). Rules without any $consumes$ declaration given
are treated as if $consumes~0$ had been specified.
Note that explicit $consumes$ declarations are only rarely needed; this is
already taken care of automatically by the higher-level $cases$ and $induct$
declarations, see also \S\ref{sec:cases-induct-att}.
\end{descr}
\subsubsection{Proof methods}\label{sec:cases-induct-meth}
\indexisarmeth{cases}\indexisarmeth{induct}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
cases & : & \isarmeth \\
induct & : & \isarmeth \\
\end{matharray}
The $cases$ and $induct$ methods provide a uniform interface to case analysis
and induction over datatypes, inductive sets, and recursive functions. The
corresponding rules may be specified and instantiated in a casual manner.
Furthermore, these methods provide named local contexts that may be invoked
via the $\CASENAME$ proof command within the subsequent proof text. This
accommodates compact proof texts even when reasoning about large
specifications.
\begin{rail}
'cases' spec
;
'induct' spec
;
spec: open? args rule?
;
open: '(' 'open' ')'
;
args: (insts * 'and')
;
rule: ('type' | 'set') ':' nameref | 'rule' ':' thmref
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$cases~insts~R$] applies method $rule$ with an appropriate case
distinction theorem, instantiated to the subjects $insts$. Symbolic case
names are bound according to the rule's local contexts.
The rule is determined as follows, according to the facts and arguments
passed to the $cases$ method:
\begin{matharray}{llll}
\Text{facts} & & \Text{arguments} & \Text{rule} \\\hline
& cases & & \Text{classical case split} \\
& cases & t & \Text{datatype exhaustion (type of $t$)} \\
\edrv a \in A & cases & \dots & \Text{inductive set elimination (of $A$)} \\
\dots & cases & \dots ~ R & \Text{explicit rule $R$} \\
\end{matharray}
Several instantiations may be given, referring to the \emph{suffix} of
premises of the case rule; within each premise, the \emph{prefix} of
variables is instantiated. In most situations, only a single term needs to
be specified; this refers to the first variable of the last premise (it is
usually the same for all cases).
The ``$(open)$'' option causes the parameters of the new local contexts to
be exposed to the current proof context. Thus local variables stemming from
distant parts of the theory development may be introduced in an implicit
manner, which can be quite confusing to the reader. Furthermore, this
option may cause unwanted hiding of existing local variables, resulting in
less robust proof texts.
\item [$induct~insts~R$] is analogous to the $cases$ method, but refers to
induction rules, which are determined as follows:
\begin{matharray}{llll}
\Text{facts} & & \Text{arguments} & \Text{rule} \\\hline
& induct & P ~ x ~ \dots & \Text{datatype induction (type of $x$)} \\
\edrv x \in A & induct & \dots & \Text{set induction (of $A$)} \\
\dots & induct & \dots ~ R & \Text{explicit rule $R$} \\
\end{matharray}
Several instantiations may be given, each referring to some part of a mutual
inductive definition or datatype --- only related partial induction rules
may be used together, though. Any of the lists of terms $P, x, \dots$
refers to the \emph{suffix} of variables present in the induction rule.
This enables the writer to specify only induction variables, or both
predicates and variables, for example.
The ``$(open)$'' option works the same way as for $cases$.
\end{descr}
Above methods produce named local contexts, as determined by the instantiated
rule as specified in the text. Beyond that, the $induct$ method guesses
further instantiations from the goal specification itself. Any persisting
unresolved schematic variables of the resulting rule will render the the
corresponding case invalid. The term binding $\Var{case}$\indexisarvar{case}
for the conclusion will be provided with each case, provided that term is
fully specified.
The $\isarkeyword{print_cases}$ command prints all named cases present in the
current proof state.
\medskip
It is important to note that there is a fundamental difference of the $cases$
and $induct$ methods in handling of non-atomic goal statements: $cases$ just
applies a certain rule in backward fashion, splitting the result into new
goals with the local contexts being augmented in a purely monotonic manner.
In contrast, $induct$ passes the full goal statement through the
``recursive'' course involved in the induction. Thus the original statement
is basically replaced by separate copies, corresponding to the induction
hypotheses and conclusion; the original goal context is no longer available.
This behavior allows \emph{strengthened induction predicates} to be expressed
concisely as meta-level rule statements, i.e.\ $\All{\vec x} \vec\phi \Imp
\psi$ to indicate ``variable'' parameters $\vec x$ and ``recursive''
assumptions $\vec\phi$. Note that ``$\isarcmd{case}~c$'' already performs
``$\FIX{\vec x}$''. Also note that local definitions may be expressed as
$\All{\vec x} n \equiv t[\vec x] \Imp \phi[n]$, with induction over $n$.
In induction proofs, local assumptions introduced by cases are split into two
different kinds: $hyps$ stemming from the rule and $prems$ from the goal
statement. This is reflected in the extracted cases accordingly, so invoking
``$\isarcmd{case}~c$'' will provide separate facts $c\mathord.hyps$ and
$c\mathord.prems$, as well as fact $c$ to hold the all-inclusive list.
\medskip
Facts presented to either method are consumed according to the number of
``major premises'' of the rule involved (see also \S\ref{sec:cases-induct}),
which is usually $0$ for plain cases and induction rules of datatypes etc.\
and $1$ for rules of inductive sets and the like. The remaining facts are
inserted into the goal verbatim before the actual $cases$ or $induct$ rule is
applied (thus facts may be even passed through an induction).
\subsubsection{Declaring rules}\label{sec:cases-induct-att}
\indexisarcmd{print-induct-rules}\indexisaratt{cases}\indexisaratt{induct}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
\isarcmd{print_induct_rules}^* & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
cases & : & \isaratt \\
induct & : & \isaratt \\
\end{matharray}
\begin{rail}
'cases' spec
;
'induct' spec
;
spec: ('type' | 'set') ':' nameref
;
\end{rail}
\begin{descr}
\item [$\isarkeyword{print_induct_rules}$] prints cases and induct rules for
sets and types of the current context.
\item [$cases$ and $induct$] (as attributes) augment the corresponding context
of rules for reasoning about inductive sets and types, using the
corresponding methods of the same name. Certain definitional packages of
object-logics usually declare emerging cases and induction rules as
expected, so users rarely need to intervene.
Manual rule declarations usually include the the $case_names$ and $ps$
attributes to adjust names of cases and parameters of a rule (see
\S\ref{sec:cases-induct}); the $consumes$ declaration is taken care of
automatically: $consumes~0$ is specified for ``type'' rules and $consumes~1$
for ``set'' rules.
\end{descr}
%%% Local Variables:
%%% mode: latex
%%% TeX-master: "isar-ref"
%%% End: