(*<*)theory CTLind = CTL:(*>*)
subsection{*CTL revisited*}
text{*\label{sec:CTL-revisited}
In \S\ref{sec:CTL} we gave a fairly involved proof of the correctness of a
model checker for CTL. In particular the proof of the
@{thm[source]infinity_lemma} on the way to @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} is not as
simple as one might intuitively expect, due to the @{text SOME} operator
involved. The purpose of this section is to show how an inductive definition
can help to simplify the proof of @{thm[source]AF_lemma2}.
Let us call a (finite or infinite) path \emph{@{term A}-avoiding} if it does
not touch any node in the set @{term A}. Then @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} says
that if no infinite path from some state @{term s} is @{term A}-avoiding,
then @{prop"s \<in> lfp(af A)"}. We prove this by inductively defining the set
@{term"Avoid s A"} of states reachable from @{term s} by a finite @{term
A}-avoiding path:
% Second proof of opposite direction, directly by wellfounded induction
% on the initial segment of M that avoids A.
*}
consts Avoid :: "state \<Rightarrow> state set \<Rightarrow> state set";
inductive "Avoid s A"
intros "s \<in> Avoid s A"
"\<lbrakk> t \<in> Avoid s A; t \<notin> A; (t,u) \<in> M \<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> u \<in> Avoid s A";
text{*
It is easy to see that for any infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f}
with @{prop"f 0 \<in> Avoid s A"} there is an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path
starting with @{term s} because (by definition of @{term Avoid}) there is a
finite @{term A}-avoiding path from @{term s} to @{term"f 0"}.
The proof is by induction on @{prop"f 0 \<in> Avoid s A"}. However,
this requires the following
reformulation, as explained in \S\ref{sec:ind-var-in-prems} above;
the @{text rule_format} directive undoes the reformulation after the proof.
*}
lemma ex_infinite_path[rule_format]:
"t \<in> Avoid s A \<Longrightarrow>
\<forall>f\<in>Paths t. (\<forall>i. f i \<notin> A) \<longrightarrow> (\<exists>p\<in>Paths s. \<forall>i. p i \<notin> A)";
apply(erule Avoid.induct);
apply(blast);
apply(clarify);
apply(drule_tac x = "\<lambda>i. case i of 0 \<Rightarrow> t | Suc i \<Rightarrow> f i" in bspec);
apply(simp_all add:Paths_def split:nat.split);
done
text{*\noindent
The base case (@{prop"t = s"}) is trivial (@{text blast}).
In the induction step, we have an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f}
starting from @{term u}, a successor of @{term t}. Now we simply instantiate
the @{text"\<forall>f\<in>Paths t"} in the induction hypothesis by the path starting with
@{term t} and continuing with @{term f}. That is what the above $\lambda$-term
expresses. That fact that this is a path starting with @{term t} and that
the instantiated induction hypothesis implies the conclusion is shown by
simplification.
Now we come to the key lemma. It says that if @{term t} can be reached by a
finite @{term A}-avoiding path from @{term s}, then @{prop"t \<in> lfp(af A)"},
provided there is no infinite @{term A}-avoiding path starting from @{term
s}.
*}
lemma Avoid_in_lfp[rule_format(no_asm)]:
"\<forall>p\<in>Paths s. \<exists>i. p i \<in> A \<Longrightarrow> t \<in> Avoid s A \<longrightarrow> t \<in> lfp(af A)";
txt{*\noindent
The trick is not to induct on @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"}, as already the base
case would be a problem, but to proceed by wellfounded induction @{term
t}. Hence @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"} needs to be brought into the conclusion as
well, which the directive @{text rule_format} undoes at the end (see below).
But induction with respect to which wellfounded relation? The restriction
of @{term M} to @{term"Avoid s A"}:
@{term[display]"{(y,x). (x,y) \<in> M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> y \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}"}
As we shall see in a moment, the absence of infinite @{term A}-avoiding paths
starting from @{term s} implies wellfoundedness of this relation. For the
moment we assume this and proceed with the induction:
*}
apply(subgoal_tac
"wf{(y,x). (x,y)\<in>M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> y \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}");
apply(erule_tac a = t in wf_induct);
apply(clarsimp);
txt{*\noindent
Now can assume additionally (induction hypothesis) that if @{prop"t \<notin> A"}
then all successors of @{term t} that are in @{term"Avoid s A"} are in
@{term"lfp (af A)"}. To prove the actual goal we unfold @{term lfp} once. Now
we have to prove that @{term t} is in @{term A} or all successors of @{term
t} are in @{term"lfp (af A)"}. If @{term t} is not in @{term A}, the second
@{term Avoid}-rule implies that all successors of @{term t} are in
@{term"Avoid s A"} (because we also assume @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"}), and
hence, by the induction hypothesis, all successors of @{term t} are indeed in
@{term"lfp(af A)"}. Mechanically:
*}
apply(rule ssubst [OF lfp_unfold[OF mono_af]]);
apply(simp only: af_def);
apply(blast intro:Avoid.intros);
txt{*
Having proved the main goal we return to the proof obligation that the above
relation is indeed wellfounded. This is proved by contraposition: we assume
the relation is not wellfounded. Thus there exists an infinite @{term
A}-avoiding path all in @{term"Avoid s A"}, by theorem
@{thm[source]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain}:
@{thm[display]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain[no_vars]}
From lemma @{thm[source]ex_infinite_path} the existence of an infinite
@{term A}-avoiding path starting in @{term s} follows, just as required for
the contraposition.
*}
apply(erule contrapos2);
apply(simp add:wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain);
apply(erule exE);
apply(rule ex_infinite_path);
apply(auto simp add:Paths_def);
done
text{*
The @{text"(no_asm)"} modifier of the @{text"rule_format"} directive means
that the assumption is left unchanged---otherwise the @{text"\<forall>p"} is turned
into a @{text"\<And>p"}, which would complicate matters below. As it is,
@{thm[source]Avoid_in_lfp} is now
@{thm[display]Avoid_in_lfp[no_vars]}
The main theorem is simply the corollary where @{prop"t = s"},
in which case the assumption @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"} is trivially true
by the first @{term Avoid}-rule). Isabelle confirms this:
*}
theorem AF_lemma2:
"{s. \<forall>p \<in> Paths s. \<exists> i. p i \<in> A} \<subseteq> lfp(af A)";
by(auto elim:Avoid_in_lfp intro:Avoid.intros);
(*<*)end(*>*)