theory Generic
imports Base Main
begin
chapter \<open>Generic tools and packages \label{ch:gen-tools}\<close>
section \<open>Configuration options \label{sec:config}\<close>
text \<open>Isabelle/Pure maintains a record of named configuration
options within the theory or proof context, with values of type
@{ML_type bool}, @{ML_type int}, @{ML_type real}, or @{ML_type
string}. Tools may declare options in ML, and then refer to these
values (relative to the context). Thus global reference variables
are easily avoided. The user may change the value of a
configuration option by means of an associated attribute of the same
name. This form of context declaration works particularly well with
commands such as @{command "declare"} or @{command "using"} like
this:
\<close>
declare [[show_main_goal = false]]
notepad
begin
note [[show_main_goal = true]]
end
text \<open>For historical reasons, some tools cannot take the full proof
context into account and merely refer to the background theory.
This is accommodated by configuration options being declared as
``global'', which may not be changed within a local context.
\begin{matharray}{rcll}
@{command_def "print_options"} & : & @{text "context \<rightarrow>"} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
@{syntax name} ('=' ('true' | 'false' | @{syntax int} | @{syntax float} | @{syntax name}))?
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{command "print_options"} prints the available configuration
options, with names, types, and current values.
\item @{text "name = value"} as an attribute expression modifies the
named option, with the syntax of the value depending on the option's
type. For @{ML_type bool} the default value is @{text true}. Any
attempt to change a global option in a local context is ignored.
\end{description}
\<close>
section \<open>Basic proof tools\<close>
subsection \<open>Miscellaneous methods and attributes \label{sec:misc-meth-att}\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{method_def unfold} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def fold} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def insert} & : & @{text method} \\[0.5ex]
@{method_def erule}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def drule}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def frule}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def intro} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def elim} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def succeed} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def fail} & : & @{text method} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
(@@{method fold} | @@{method unfold} | @@{method insert}) @{syntax thmrefs}
;
(@@{method erule} | @@{method drule} | @@{method frule})
('(' @{syntax nat} ')')? @{syntax thmrefs}
;
(@@{method intro} | @@{method elim}) @{syntax thmrefs}?
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{method unfold}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} and @{method fold}~@{text
"a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} expand (or fold back) the given definitions throughout
all goals; any chained facts provided are inserted into the goal and
subject to rewriting as well.
\item @{method insert}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} inserts theorems as facts
into all goals of the proof state. Note that current facts
indicated for forward chaining are ignored.
\item @{method erule}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"}, @{method
drule}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"}, and @{method frule}~@{text
"a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} are similar to the basic @{method rule}
method (see \secref{sec:pure-meth-att}), but apply rules by
elim-resolution, destruct-resolution, and forward-resolution,
respectively @{cite "isabelle-implementation"}. The optional natural
number argument (default 0) specifies additional assumption steps to
be performed here.
Note that these methods are improper ones, mainly serving for
experimentation and tactic script emulation. Different modes of
basic rule application are usually expressed in Isar at the proof
language level, rather than via implicit proof state manipulations.
For example, a proper single-step elimination would be done using
the plain @{method rule} method, with forward chaining of current
facts.
\item @{method intro} and @{method elim} repeatedly refine some goal
by intro- or elim-resolution, after having inserted any chained
facts. Exactly the rules given as arguments are taken into account;
this allows fine-tuned decomposition of a proof problem, in contrast
to common automated tools.
\item @{method succeed} yields a single (unchanged) result; it is
the identity of the ``@{text ","}'' method combinator (cf.\
\secref{sec:proof-meth}).
\item @{method fail} yields an empty result sequence; it is the
identity of the ``@{text "|"}'' method combinator (cf.\
\secref{sec:proof-meth}).
\end{description}
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{attribute_def tagged} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def untagged} & : & @{text attribute} \\[0.5ex]
@{attribute_def THEN} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def unfolded} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def folded} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def abs_def} & : & @{text attribute} \\[0.5ex]
@{attribute_def rotated} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def (Pure) elim_format} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def no_vars}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text attribute} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
@@{attribute tagged} @{syntax name} @{syntax name}
;
@@{attribute untagged} @{syntax name}
;
@@{attribute THEN} ('[' @{syntax nat} ']')? @{syntax thmref}
;
(@@{attribute unfolded} | @@{attribute folded}) @{syntax thmrefs}
;
@@{attribute rotated} @{syntax int}?
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{attribute tagged}~@{text "name value"} and @{attribute
untagged}~@{text name} add and remove \emph{tags} of some theorem.
Tags may be any list of string pairs that serve as formal comment.
The first string is considered the tag name, the second its value.
Note that @{attribute untagged} removes any tags of the same name.
\item @{attribute THEN}~@{text a} composes rules by resolution; it
resolves with the first premise of @{text a} (an alternative
position may be also specified). See also @{ML_op "RS"} in
@{cite "isabelle-implementation"}.
\item @{attribute unfolded}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} and @{attribute
folded}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} expand and fold back again the given
definitions throughout a rule.
\item @{attribute abs_def} turns an equation of the form @{prop "f x
y \<equiv> t"} into @{prop "f \<equiv> \<lambda>x y. t"}, which ensures that @{method
simp} or @{method unfold} steps always expand it. This also works
for object-logic equality.
\item @{attribute rotated}~@{text n} rotate the premises of a
theorem by @{text n} (default 1).
\item @{attribute (Pure) elim_format} turns a destruction rule into
elimination rule format, by resolving with the rule @{prop "PROP A \<Longrightarrow>
(PROP A \<Longrightarrow> PROP B) \<Longrightarrow> PROP B"}.
Note that the Classical Reasoner (\secref{sec:classical}) provides
its own version of this operation.
\item @{attribute no_vars} replaces schematic variables by free
ones; this is mainly for tuning output of pretty printed theorems.
\end{description}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Low-level equational reasoning\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{method_def subst} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def hypsubst} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def split} & : & @{text method} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
@@{method subst} ('(' 'asm' ')')? \<newline> ('(' (@{syntax nat}+) ')')? @{syntax thmref}
;
@@{method split} @{syntax thmrefs}
\<close>}
These methods provide low-level facilities for equational reasoning
that are intended for specialized applications only. Normally,
single step calculations would be performed in a structured text
(see also \secref{sec:calculation}), while the Simplifier methods
provide the canonical way for automated normalization (see
\secref{sec:simplifier}).
\begin{description}
\item @{method subst}~@{text eq} performs a single substitution step
using rule @{text eq}, which may be either a meta or object
equality.
\item @{method subst}~@{text "(asm) eq"} substitutes in an
assumption.
\item @{method subst}~@{text "(i \<dots> j) eq"} performs several
substitutions in the conclusion. The numbers @{text i} to @{text j}
indicate the positions to substitute at. Positions are ordered from
the top of the term tree moving down from left to right. For
example, in @{text "(a + b) + (c + d)"} there are three positions
where commutativity of @{text "+"} is applicable: 1 refers to @{text
"a + b"}, 2 to the whole term, and 3 to @{text "c + d"}.
If the positions in the list @{text "(i \<dots> j)"} are non-overlapping
(e.g.\ @{text "(2 3)"} in @{text "(a + b) + (c + d)"}) you may
assume all substitutions are performed simultaneously. Otherwise
the behaviour of @{text subst} is not specified.
\item @{method subst}~@{text "(asm) (i \<dots> j) eq"} performs the
substitutions in the assumptions. The positions refer to the
assumptions in order from left to right. For example, given in a
goal of the form @{text "P (a + b) \<Longrightarrow> P (c + d) \<Longrightarrow> \<dots>"}, position 1 of
commutativity of @{text "+"} is the subterm @{text "a + b"} and
position 2 is the subterm @{text "c + d"}.
\item @{method hypsubst} performs substitution using some
assumption; this only works for equations of the form @{text "x =
t"} where @{text x} is a free or bound variable.
\item @{method split}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} performs single-step case
splitting using the given rules. Splitting is performed in the
conclusion or some assumption of the subgoal, depending of the
structure of the rule.
Note that the @{method simp} method already involves repeated
application of split rules as declared in the current context, using
@{attribute split}, for example.
\end{description}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Further tactic emulations \label{sec:tactics}\<close>
text \<open>
The following improper proof methods emulate traditional tactics.
These admit direct access to the goal state, which is normally
considered harmful! In particular, this may involve both numbered
goal addressing (default 1), and dynamic instantiation within the
scope of some subgoal.
\begin{warn}
Dynamic instantiations refer to universally quantified parameters
of a subgoal (the dynamic context) rather than fixed variables and
term abbreviations of a (static) Isar context.
\end{warn}
Tactic emulation methods, unlike their ML counterparts, admit
simultaneous instantiation from both dynamic and static contexts.
If names occur in both contexts goal parameters hide locally fixed
variables. Likewise, schematic variables refer to term
abbreviations, if present in the static context. Otherwise the
schematic variable is interpreted as a schematic variable and left
to be solved by unification with certain parts of the subgoal.
Note that the tactic emulation proof methods in Isabelle/Isar are
consistently named @{text foo_tac}. Note also that variable names
occurring on left hand sides of instantiations must be preceded by a
question mark if they coincide with a keyword or contain dots. This
is consistent with the attribute @{attribute "where"} (see
\secref{sec:pure-meth-att}).
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{method_def rule_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def erule_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def drule_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def frule_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def cut_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def thin_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def subgoal_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def rename_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def rotate_tac}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def tactic}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def raw_tactic}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text method} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
(@@{method rule_tac} | @@{method erule_tac} | @@{method drule_tac} |
@@{method frule_tac} | @@{method cut_tac}) @{syntax goal_spec}? \<newline>
( dynamic_insts @'in' @{syntax thmref} | @{syntax thmrefs} )
;
@@{method thin_tac} @{syntax goal_spec}? @{syntax prop}
(@'for' (@{syntax vars} + @'and'))?
;
@@{method subgoal_tac} @{syntax goal_spec}? (@{syntax prop} +)
(@'for' (@{syntax vars} + @'and'))?
;
@@{method rename_tac} @{syntax goal_spec}? (@{syntax name} +)
;
@@{method rotate_tac} @{syntax goal_spec}? @{syntax int}?
;
(@@{method tactic} | @@{method raw_tactic}) @{syntax text}
;
dynamic_insts: ((@{syntax name} '=' @{syntax term}) + @'and')
(@'for' (@{syntax vars} + @'and'))?
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{method rule_tac} etc. do resolution of rules with explicit
instantiation. This works the same way as the ML tactics @{ML
Rule_Insts.res_inst_tac} etc.\ (see @{cite "isabelle-implementation"}).
Multiple rules may be only given if there is no instantiation; then
@{method rule_tac} is the same as @{ML resolve_tac} in ML (see
@{cite "isabelle-implementation"}).
\item @{method cut_tac} inserts facts into the proof state as
assumption of a subgoal; instantiations may be given as well. Note
that the scope of schematic variables is spread over the main goal
statement and rule premises are turned into new subgoals. This is
in contrast to the regular method @{method insert} which inserts
closed rule statements.
\item @{method thin_tac}~@{text \<phi>} deletes the specified premise
from a subgoal. Note that @{text \<phi>} may contain schematic
variables, to abbreviate the intended proposition; the first
matching subgoal premise will be deleted. Removing useless premises
from a subgoal increases its readability and can make search tactics
run faster.
\item @{method subgoal_tac}~@{text "\<phi>\<^sub>1 \<dots> \<phi>\<^sub>n"} adds the propositions
@{text "\<phi>\<^sub>1 \<dots> \<phi>\<^sub>n"} as local premises to a subgoal, and poses the same
as new subgoals (in the original context).
\item @{method rename_tac}~@{text "x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>n"} renames parameters of a
goal according to the list @{text "x\<^sub>1, \<dots>, x\<^sub>n"}, which refers to the
\emph{suffix} of variables.
\item @{method rotate_tac}~@{text n} rotates the premises of a
subgoal by @{text n} positions: from right to left if @{text n} is
positive, and from left to right if @{text n} is negative; the
default value is 1.
\item @{method tactic}~@{text "text"} produces a proof method from
any ML text of type @{ML_type tactic}. Apart from the usual ML
environment and the current proof context, the ML code may refer to
the locally bound values @{ML_text facts}, which indicates any
current facts used for forward-chaining.
\item @{method raw_tactic} is similar to @{method tactic}, but
presents the goal state in its raw internal form, where simultaneous
subgoals appear as conjunction of the logical framework instead of
the usual split into several subgoals. While feature this is useful
for debugging of complex method definitions, it should not never
appear in production theories.
\end{description}
\<close>
section \<open>The Simplifier \label{sec:simplifier}\<close>
text \<open>The Simplifier performs conditional and unconditional
rewriting and uses contextual information: rule declarations in the
background theory or local proof context are taken into account, as
well as chained facts and subgoal premises (``local assumptions'').
There are several general hooks that allow to modify the
simplification strategy, or incorporate other proof tools that solve
sub-problems, produce rewrite rules on demand etc.
The rewriting strategy is always strictly bottom up, except for
congruence rules, which are applied while descending into a term.
Conditions in conditional rewrite rules are solved recursively
before the rewrite rule is applied.
The default Simplifier setup of major object logics (HOL, HOLCF,
FOL, ZF) makes the Simplifier ready for immediate use, without
engaging into the internal structures. Thus it serves as
general-purpose proof tool with the main focus on equational
reasoning, and a bit more than that.
\<close>
subsection \<open>Simplification methods \label{sec:simp-meth}\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{tabular}{rcll}
@{method_def simp} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def simp_all} & : & @{text method} \\
@{attribute_def simp_depth_limit} & : & @{text attribute} & default @{text 100} \\
\end{tabular}
\medskip
@{rail \<open>
(@@{method simp} | @@{method simp_all}) opt? (@{syntax simpmod} * )
;
opt: '(' ('no_asm' | 'no_asm_simp' | 'no_asm_use' | 'asm_lr' ) ')'
;
@{syntax_def simpmod}: ('add' | 'del' | 'only' | 'split' (() | 'add' | 'del') |
'cong' (() | 'add' | 'del')) ':' @{syntax thmrefs}
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{method simp} invokes the Simplifier on the first subgoal,
after inserting chained facts as additional goal premises; further
rule declarations may be included via @{text "(simp add: facts)"}.
The proof method fails if the subgoal remains unchanged after
simplification.
Note that the original goal premises and chained facts are subject
to simplification themselves, while declarations via @{text
"add"}/@{text "del"} merely follow the policies of the object-logic
to extract rewrite rules from theorems, without further
simplification. This may lead to slightly different behavior in
either case, which might be required precisely like that in some
boundary situations to perform the intended simplification step!
\medskip The @{text only} modifier first removes all other rewrite
rules, looper tactics (including split rules), congruence rules, and
then behaves like @{text add}. Implicit solvers remain, which means
that trivial rules like reflexivity or introduction of @{text
"True"} are available to solve the simplified subgoals, but also
non-trivial tools like linear arithmetic in HOL. The latter may
lead to some surprise of the meaning of ``only'' in Isabelle/HOL
compared to English!
\medskip The @{text split} modifiers add or delete rules for the
Splitter (see also \secref{sec:simp-strategies} on the looper).
This works only if the Simplifier method has been properly setup to
include the Splitter (all major object logics such HOL, HOLCF, FOL,
ZF do this already).
There is also a separate @{method_ref split} method available for
single-step case splitting. The effect of repeatedly applying
@{text "(split thms)"} can be imitated by ``@{text "(simp only:
split: thms)"}''.
\medskip The @{text cong} modifiers add or delete Simplifier
congruence rules (see also \secref{sec:simp-rules}); the default is
to add.
\item @{method simp_all} is similar to @{method simp}, but acts on
all goals, working backwards from the last to the first one as usual
in Isabelle.\footnote{The order is irrelevant for goals without
schematic variables, so simplification might actually be performed
in parallel here.}
Chained facts are inserted into all subgoals, before the
simplification process starts. Further rule declarations are the
same as for @{method simp}.
The proof method fails if all subgoals remain unchanged after
simplification.
\item @{attribute simp_depth_limit} limits the number of recursive
invocations of the Simplifier during conditional rewriting.
\end{description}
By default the Simplifier methods above take local assumptions fully
into account, using equational assumptions in the subsequent
normalization process, or simplifying assumptions themselves.
Further options allow to fine-tune the behavior of the Simplifier
in this respect, corresponding to a variety of ML tactics as
follows.\footnote{Unlike the corresponding Isar proof methods, the
ML tactics do not insist in changing the goal state.}
\begin{center}
\small
\begin{tabular}{|l|l|p{0.3\textwidth}|}
\hline
Isar method & ML tactic & behavior \\\hline
@{text "(simp (no_asm))"} & @{ML simp_tac} & assumptions are ignored
completely \\\hline
@{text "(simp (no_asm_simp))"} & @{ML asm_simp_tac} & assumptions
are used in the simplification of the conclusion but are not
themselves simplified \\\hline
@{text "(simp (no_asm_use))"} & @{ML full_simp_tac} & assumptions
are simplified but are not used in the simplification of each other
or the conclusion \\\hline
@{text "(simp)"} & @{ML asm_full_simp_tac} & assumptions are used in
the simplification of the conclusion and to simplify other
assumptions \\\hline
@{text "(simp (asm_lr))"} & @{ML asm_lr_simp_tac} & compatibility
mode: an assumption is only used for simplifying assumptions which
are to the right of it \\\hline
\end{tabular}
\end{center}
\<close>
subsubsection \<open>Examples\<close>
text \<open>We consider basic algebraic simplifications in Isabelle/HOL.
The rather trivial goal @{prop "0 + (x + 0) = x + 0 + 0"} looks like
a good candidate to be solved by a single call of @{method simp}:
\<close>
lemma "0 + (x + 0) = x + 0 + 0" apply simp? oops
text \<open>The above attempt \emph{fails}, because @{term "0"} and @{term
"op +"} in the HOL library are declared as generic type class
operations, without stating any algebraic laws yet. More specific
types are required to get access to certain standard simplifications
of the theory context, e.g.\ like this:\<close>
lemma fixes x :: nat shows "0 + (x + 0) = x + 0 + 0" by simp
lemma fixes x :: int shows "0 + (x + 0) = x + 0 + 0" by simp
lemma fixes x :: "'a :: monoid_add" shows "0 + (x + 0) = x + 0 + 0" by simp
text \<open>
\medskip In many cases, assumptions of a subgoal are also needed in
the simplification process. For example:
\<close>
lemma fixes x :: nat shows "x = 0 \<Longrightarrow> x + x = 0" by simp
lemma fixes x :: nat assumes "x = 0" shows "x + x = 0" apply simp oops
lemma fixes x :: nat assumes "x = 0" shows "x + x = 0" using assms by simp
text \<open>As seen above, local assumptions that shall contribute to
simplification need to be part of the subgoal already, or indicated
explicitly for use by the subsequent method invocation. Both too
little or too much information can make simplification fail, for
different reasons.
In the next example the malicious assumption @{prop "\<And>x::nat. f x =
g (f (g x))"} does not contribute to solve the problem, but makes
the default @{method simp} method loop: the rewrite rule @{text "f
?x \<equiv> g (f (g ?x))"} extracted from the assumption does not
terminate. The Simplifier notices certain simple forms of
nontermination, but not this one. The problem can be solved
nonetheless, by ignoring assumptions via special options as
explained before:
\<close>
lemma "(\<And>x::nat. f x = g (f (g x))) \<Longrightarrow> f 0 = f 0 + 0"
by (simp (no_asm))
text \<open>The latter form is typical for long unstructured proof
scripts, where the control over the goal content is limited. In
structured proofs it is usually better to avoid pushing too many
facts into the goal state in the first place. Assumptions in the
Isar proof context do not intrude the reasoning if not used
explicitly. This is illustrated for a toplevel statement and a
local proof body as follows:
\<close>
lemma
assumes "\<And>x::nat. f x = g (f (g x))"
shows "f 0 = f 0 + 0" by simp
notepad
begin
assume "\<And>x::nat. f x = g (f (g x))"
have "f 0 = f 0 + 0" by simp
end
text \<open>\medskip Because assumptions may simplify each other, there
can be very subtle cases of nontermination. For example, the regular
@{method simp} method applied to @{prop "P (f x) \<Longrightarrow> y = x \<Longrightarrow> f x = f y
\<Longrightarrow> Q"} gives rise to the infinite reduction sequence
\[
@{text "P (f x)"} \stackrel{@{text "f x \<equiv> f y"}}{\longmapsto}
@{text "P (f y)"} \stackrel{@{text "y \<equiv> x"}}{\longmapsto}
@{text "P (f x)"} \stackrel{@{text "f x \<equiv> f y"}}{\longmapsto} \cdots
\]
whereas applying the same to @{prop "y = x \<Longrightarrow> f x = f y \<Longrightarrow> P (f x) \<Longrightarrow>
Q"} terminates (without solving the goal):
\<close>
lemma "y = x \<Longrightarrow> f x = f y \<Longrightarrow> P (f x) \<Longrightarrow> Q"
apply simp
oops
text \<open>See also \secref{sec:simp-trace} for options to enable
Simplifier trace mode, which often helps to diagnose problems with
rewrite systems.
\<close>
subsection \<open>Declaring rules \label{sec:simp-rules}\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{attribute_def simp} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def split} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def cong} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{command_def "print_simpset"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text "context \<rightarrow>"} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
(@@{attribute simp} | @@{attribute split} | @@{attribute cong})
(() | 'add' | 'del')
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{attribute simp} declares rewrite rules, by adding or
deleting them from the simpset within the theory or proof context.
Rewrite rules are theorems expressing some form of equality, for
example:
@{text "Suc ?m + ?n = ?m + Suc ?n"} \\
@{text "?P \<and> ?P \<longleftrightarrow> ?P"} \\
@{text "?A \<union> ?B \<equiv> {x. x \<in> ?A \<or> x \<in> ?B}"}
\smallskip
Conditional rewrites such as @{text "?m < ?n \<Longrightarrow> ?m div ?n = 0"} are
also permitted; the conditions can be arbitrary formulas.
\medskip Internally, all rewrite rules are translated into Pure
equalities, theorems with conclusion @{text "lhs \<equiv> rhs"}. The
simpset contains a function for extracting equalities from arbitrary
theorems, which is usually installed when the object-logic is
configured initially. For example, @{text "\<not> ?x \<in> {}"} could be
turned into @{text "?x \<in> {} \<equiv> False"}. Theorems that are declared as
@{attribute simp} and local assumptions within a goal are treated
uniformly in this respect.
The Simplifier accepts the following formats for the @{text "lhs"}
term:
\begin{enumerate}
\item First-order patterns, considering the sublanguage of
application of constant operators to variable operands, without
@{text "\<lambda>"}-abstractions or functional variables.
For example:
@{text "(?x + ?y) + ?z \<equiv> ?x + (?y + ?z)"} \\
@{text "f (f ?x ?y) ?z \<equiv> f ?x (f ?y ?z)"}
\item Higher-order patterns in the sense of @{cite "nipkow-patterns"}.
These are terms in @{text "\<beta>"}-normal form (this will always be the
case unless you have done something strange) where each occurrence
of an unknown is of the form @{text "?F x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>n"}, where the
@{text "x\<^sub>i"} are distinct bound variables.
For example, @{text "(\<forall>x. ?P x \<and> ?Q x) \<equiv> (\<forall>x. ?P x) \<and> (\<forall>x. ?Q x)"}
or its symmetric form, since the @{text "rhs"} is also a
higher-order pattern.
\item Physical first-order patterns over raw @{text "\<lambda>"}-term
structure without @{text "\<alpha>\<beta>\<eta>"}-equality; abstractions and bound
variables are treated like quasi-constant term material.
For example, the rule @{text "?f ?x \<in> range ?f = True"} rewrites the
term @{text "g a \<in> range g"} to @{text "True"}, but will fail to
match @{text "g (h b) \<in> range (\<lambda>x. g (h x))"}. However, offending
subterms (in our case @{text "?f ?x"}, which is not a pattern) can
be replaced by adding new variables and conditions like this: @{text
"?y = ?f ?x \<Longrightarrow> ?y \<in> range ?f = True"} is acceptable as a conditional
rewrite rule of the second category since conditions can be
arbitrary terms.
\end{enumerate}
\item @{attribute split} declares case split rules.
\item @{attribute cong} declares congruence rules to the Simplifier
context.
Congruence rules are equalities of the form @{text [display]
"\<dots> \<Longrightarrow> f ?x\<^sub>1 \<dots> ?x\<^sub>n = f ?y\<^sub>1 \<dots> ?y\<^sub>n"}
This controls the simplification of the arguments of @{text f}. For
example, some arguments can be simplified under additional
assumptions: @{text [display] "?P\<^sub>1 \<longleftrightarrow> ?Q\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> (?Q\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> ?P\<^sub>2 \<longleftrightarrow> ?Q\<^sub>2) \<Longrightarrow>
(?P\<^sub>1 \<longrightarrow> ?P\<^sub>2) \<longleftrightarrow> (?Q\<^sub>1 \<longrightarrow> ?Q\<^sub>2)"}
Given this rule, the Simplifier assumes @{text "?Q\<^sub>1"} and extracts
rewrite rules from it when simplifying @{text "?P\<^sub>2"}. Such local
assumptions are effective for rewriting formulae such as @{text "x =
0 \<longrightarrow> y + x = y"}.
%FIXME
%The local assumptions are also provided as theorems to the solver;
%see \secref{sec:simp-solver} below.
\medskip The following congruence rule for bounded quantifiers also
supplies contextual information --- about the bound variable:
@{text [display] "(?A = ?B) \<Longrightarrow> (\<And>x. x \<in> ?B \<Longrightarrow> ?P x \<longleftrightarrow> ?Q x) \<Longrightarrow>
(\<forall>x \<in> ?A. ?P x) \<longleftrightarrow> (\<forall>x \<in> ?B. ?Q x)"}
\medskip This congruence rule for conditional expressions can
supply contextual information for simplifying the arms:
@{text [display] "?p = ?q \<Longrightarrow> (?q \<Longrightarrow> ?a = ?c) \<Longrightarrow> (\<not> ?q \<Longrightarrow> ?b = ?d) \<Longrightarrow>
(if ?p then ?a else ?b) = (if ?q then ?c else ?d)"}
A congruence rule can also \emph{prevent} simplification of some
arguments. Here is an alternative congruence rule for conditional
expressions that conforms to non-strict functional evaluation:
@{text [display] "?p = ?q \<Longrightarrow> (if ?p then ?a else ?b) = (if ?q then ?a else ?b)"}
Only the first argument is simplified; the others remain unchanged.
This can make simplification much faster, but may require an extra
case split over the condition @{text "?q"} to prove the goal.
\item @{command "print_simpset"} prints the collection of rules
declared to the Simplifier, which is also known as ``simpset''
internally.
For historical reasons, simpsets may occur independently from the
current context, but are conceptually dependent on it. When the
Simplifier is invoked via one of its main entry points in the Isar
source language (as proof method \secref{sec:simp-meth} or rule
attribute \secref{sec:simp-meth}), its simpset is derived from the
current proof context, and carries a back-reference to that for
other tools that might get invoked internally (e.g.\ simplification
procedures \secref{sec:simproc}). A mismatch of the context of the
simpset and the context of the problem being simplified may lead to
unexpected results.
\end{description}
The implicit simpset of the theory context is propagated
monotonically through the theory hierarchy: forming a new theory,
the union of the simpsets of its imports are taken as starting
point. Also note that definitional packages like @{command
"datatype"}, @{command "primrec"}, @{command "fun"} routinely
declare Simplifier rules to the target context, while plain
@{command "definition"} is an exception in \emph{not} declaring
anything.
\medskip It is up the user to manipulate the current simpset further
by explicitly adding or deleting theorems as simplification rules,
or installing other tools via simplification procedures
(\secref{sec:simproc}). Good simpsets are hard to design. Rules
that obviously simplify, like @{text "?n + 0 \<equiv> ?n"} are good
candidates for the implicit simpset, unless a special
non-normalizing behavior of certain operations is intended. More
specific rules (such as distributive laws, which duplicate subterms)
should be added only for specific proof steps. Conversely,
sometimes a rule needs to be deleted just for some part of a proof.
The need of frequent additions or deletions may indicate a poorly
designed simpset.
\begin{warn}
The union of simpsets from theory imports (as described above) is
not always a good starting point for the new theory. If some
ancestors have deleted simplification rules because they are no
longer wanted, while others have left those rules in, then the union
will contain the unwanted rules, and thus have to be deleted again
in the theory body.
\end{warn}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Ordered rewriting with permutative rules\<close>
text \<open>A rewrite rule is \emph{permutative} if the left-hand side and
right-hand side are the equal up to renaming of variables. The most
common permutative rule is commutativity: @{text "?x + ?y = ?y +
?x"}. Other examples include @{text "(?x - ?y) - ?z = (?x - ?z) -
?y"} in arithmetic and @{text "insert ?x (insert ?y ?A) = insert ?y
(insert ?x ?A)"} for sets. Such rules are common enough to merit
special attention.
Because ordinary rewriting loops given such rules, the Simplifier
employs a special strategy, called \emph{ordered rewriting}.
Permutative rules are detected and only applied if the rewriting
step decreases the redex wrt.\ a given term ordering. For example,
commutativity rewrites @{text "b + a"} to @{text "a + b"}, but then
stops, because the redex cannot be decreased further in the sense of
the term ordering.
The default is lexicographic ordering of term structure, but this
could be also changed locally for special applications via
@{index_ML Simplifier.set_termless} in Isabelle/ML.
\medskip Permutative rewrite rules are declared to the Simplifier
just like other rewrite rules. Their special status is recognized
automatically, and their application is guarded by the term ordering
accordingly.\<close>
subsubsection \<open>Rewriting with AC operators\<close>
text \<open>Ordered rewriting is particularly effective in the case of
associative-commutative operators. (Associativity by itself is not
permutative.) When dealing with an AC-operator @{text "f"}, keep
the following points in mind:
\begin{itemize}
\item The associative law must always be oriented from left to
right, namely @{text "f (f x y) z = f x (f y z)"}. The opposite
orientation, if used with commutativity, leads to looping in
conjunction with the standard term order.
\item To complete your set of rewrite rules, you must add not just
associativity (A) and commutativity (C) but also a derived rule
\emph{left-commutativity} (LC): @{text "f x (f y z) = f y (f x z)"}.
\end{itemize}
Ordered rewriting with the combination of A, C, and LC sorts a term
lexicographically --- the rewriting engine imitates bubble-sort.
\<close>
locale AC_example =
fixes f :: "'a \<Rightarrow> 'a \<Rightarrow> 'a" (infix "\<bullet>" 60)
assumes assoc: "(x \<bullet> y) \<bullet> z = x \<bullet> (y \<bullet> z)"
assumes commute: "x \<bullet> y = y \<bullet> x"
begin
lemma left_commute: "x \<bullet> (y \<bullet> z) = y \<bullet> (x \<bullet> z)"
proof -
have "(x \<bullet> y) \<bullet> z = (y \<bullet> x) \<bullet> z" by (simp only: commute)
then show ?thesis by (simp only: assoc)
qed
lemmas AC_rules = assoc commute left_commute
text \<open>Thus the Simplifier is able to establish equalities with
arbitrary permutations of subterms, by normalizing to a common
standard form. For example:\<close>
lemma "(b \<bullet> c) \<bullet> a = xxx"
apply (simp only: AC_rules)
txt \<open>@{subgoals}\<close>
oops
lemma "(b \<bullet> c) \<bullet> a = a \<bullet> (b \<bullet> c)" by (simp only: AC_rules)
lemma "(b \<bullet> c) \<bullet> a = c \<bullet> (b \<bullet> a)" by (simp only: AC_rules)
lemma "(b \<bullet> c) \<bullet> a = (c \<bullet> b) \<bullet> a" by (simp only: AC_rules)
end
text \<open>Martin and Nipkow @{cite "martin-nipkow"} discuss the theory and
give many examples; other algebraic structures are amenable to
ordered rewriting, such as Boolean rings. The Boyer-Moore theorem
prover @{cite bm88book} also employs ordered rewriting.
\<close>
subsubsection \<open>Re-orienting equalities\<close>
text \<open>Another application of ordered rewriting uses the derived rule
@{thm [source] eq_commute}: @{thm [source = false] eq_commute} to
reverse equations.
This is occasionally useful to re-orient local assumptions according
to the term ordering, when other built-in mechanisms of
reorientation and mutual simplification fail to apply.\<close>
subsection \<open>Simplifier tracing and debugging \label{sec:simp-trace}\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{tabular}{rcll}
@{attribute_def simp_trace} & : & @{text attribute} & default @{text false} \\
@{attribute_def simp_trace_depth_limit} & : & @{text attribute} & default @{text 1} \\
@{attribute_def simp_debug} & : & @{text attribute} & default @{text false} \\
@{attribute_def simp_trace_new} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def simp_break} & : & @{text attribute} \\
\end{tabular}
\medskip
@{rail \<open>
@@{attribute simp_trace_new} ('interactive')? \<newline>
('mode' '=' ('full' | 'normal'))? \<newline>
('depth' '=' @{syntax nat})?
;
@@{attribute simp_break} (@{syntax term}*)
\<close>}
These attributes and configurations options control various aspects of
Simplifier tracing and debugging.
\begin{description}
\item @{attribute simp_trace} makes the Simplifier output internal
operations. This includes rewrite steps, but also bookkeeping like
modifications of the simpset.
\item @{attribute simp_trace_depth_limit} limits the effect of
@{attribute simp_trace} to the given depth of recursive Simplifier
invocations (when solving conditions of rewrite rules).
\item @{attribute simp_debug} makes the Simplifier output some extra
information about internal operations. This includes any attempted
invocation of simplification procedures.
\item @{attribute simp_trace_new} controls Simplifier tracing within
Isabelle/PIDE applications, notably Isabelle/jEdit @{cite "isabelle-jedit"}.
This provides a hierarchical representation of the rewriting steps
performed by the Simplifier.
Users can configure the behaviour by specifying breakpoints, verbosity and
enabling or disabling the interactive mode. In normal verbosity (the
default), only rule applications matching a breakpoint will be shown to
the user. In full verbosity, all rule applications will be logged.
Interactive mode interrupts the normal flow of the Simplifier and defers
the decision how to continue to the user via some GUI dialog.
\item @{attribute simp_break} declares term or theorem breakpoints for
@{attribute simp_trace_new} as described above. Term breakpoints are
patterns which are checked for matches on the redex of a rule application.
Theorem breakpoints trigger when the corresponding theorem is applied in a
rewrite step. For example:
\end{description}
\<close>
declare conjI [simp_break]
declare [[simp_break "?x \<and> ?y"]]
subsection \<open>Simplification procedures \label{sec:simproc}\<close>
text \<open>Simplification procedures are ML functions that produce proven
rewrite rules on demand. They are associated with higher-order
patterns that approximate the left-hand sides of equations. The
Simplifier first matches the current redex against one of the LHS
patterns; if this succeeds, the corresponding ML function is
invoked, passing the Simplifier context and redex term. Thus rules
may be specifically fashioned for particular situations, resulting
in a more powerful mechanism than term rewriting by a fixed set of
rules.
Any successful result needs to be a (possibly conditional) rewrite
rule @{text "t \<equiv> u"} that is applicable to the current redex. The
rule will be applied just as any ordinary rewrite rule. It is
expected to be already in \emph{internal form}, bypassing the
automatic preprocessing of object-level equivalences.
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{command_def "simproc_setup"} & : & @{text "local_theory \<rightarrow> local_theory"} \\
simproc & : & @{text attribute} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
@@{command simproc_setup} @{syntax name} '(' (@{syntax term} + '|') ')' '='
@{syntax text} \<newline> (@'identifier' (@{syntax nameref}+))?
;
@@{attribute simproc} (('add' ':')? | 'del' ':') (@{syntax name}+)
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{command "simproc_setup"} defines a named simplification
procedure that is invoked by the Simplifier whenever any of the
given term patterns match the current redex. The implementation,
which is provided as ML source text, needs to be of type @{ML_type
"morphism -> simpset -> cterm -> thm option"}, where the @{ML_type
cterm} represents the current redex @{text r} and the result is
supposed to be some proven rewrite rule @{text "r \<equiv> r'"} (or a
generalized version), or @{ML NONE} to indicate failure. The
@{ML_type simpset} argument holds the full context of the current
Simplifier invocation, including the actual Isar proof context. The
@{ML_type morphism} informs about the difference of the original
compilation context wrt.\ the one of the actual application later
on. The optional @{keyword "identifier"} specifies theorems that
represent the logical content of the abstract theory of this
simproc.
Morphisms and identifiers are only relevant for simprocs that are
defined within a local target context, e.g.\ in a locale.
\item @{text "simproc add: name"} and @{text "simproc del: name"}
add or delete named simprocs to the current Simplifier context. The
default is to add a simproc. Note that @{command "simproc_setup"}
already adds the new simproc to the subsequent context.
\end{description}
\<close>
subsubsection \<open>Example\<close>
text \<open>The following simplification procedure for @{thm
[source=false, show_types] unit_eq} in HOL performs fine-grained
control over rule application, beyond higher-order pattern matching.
Declaring @{thm unit_eq} as @{attribute simp} directly would make
the Simplifier loop! Note that a version of this simplification
procedure is already active in Isabelle/HOL.\<close>
simproc_setup unit ("x::unit") =
\<open>fn _ => fn _ => fn ct =>
if HOLogic.is_unit (Thm.term_of ct) then NONE
else SOME (mk_meta_eq @{thm unit_eq})\<close>
text \<open>Since the Simplifier applies simplification procedures
frequently, it is important to make the failure check in ML
reasonably fast.\<close>
subsection \<open>Configurable Simplifier strategies \label{sec:simp-strategies}\<close>
text \<open>The core term-rewriting engine of the Simplifier is normally
used in combination with some add-on components that modify the
strategy and allow to integrate other non-Simplifier proof tools.
These may be reconfigured in ML as explained below. Even if the
default strategies of object-logics like Isabelle/HOL are used
unchanged, it helps to understand how the standard Simplifier
strategies work.\<close>
subsubsection \<open>The subgoaler\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{mldecls}
@{index_ML Simplifier.set_subgoaler: "(Proof.context -> int -> tactic) ->
Proof.context -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML Simplifier.prems_of: "Proof.context -> thm list"} \\
\end{mldecls}
The subgoaler is the tactic used to solve subgoals arising out of
conditional rewrite rules or congruence rules. The default should
be simplification itself. In rare situations, this strategy may
need to be changed. For example, if the premise of a conditional
rule is an instance of its conclusion, as in @{text "Suc ?m < ?n \<Longrightarrow>
?m < ?n"}, the default strategy could loop. % FIXME !??
\begin{description}
\item @{ML Simplifier.set_subgoaler}~@{text "tac ctxt"} sets the
subgoaler of the context to @{text "tac"}. The tactic will
be applied to the context of the running Simplifier instance.
\item @{ML Simplifier.prems_of}~@{text "ctxt"} retrieves the current
set of premises from the context. This may be non-empty only if
the Simplifier has been told to utilize local assumptions in the
first place (cf.\ the options in \secref{sec:simp-meth}).
\end{description}
As an example, consider the following alternative subgoaler:
\<close>
ML \<open>
fun subgoaler_tac ctxt =
assume_tac ctxt ORELSE'
resolve_tac ctxt (Simplifier.prems_of ctxt) ORELSE'
asm_simp_tac ctxt
\<close>
text \<open>This tactic first tries to solve the subgoal by assumption or
by resolving with with one of the premises, calling simplification
only if that fails.\<close>
subsubsection \<open>The solver\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{mldecls}
@{index_ML_type solver} \\
@{index_ML Simplifier.mk_solver: "string ->
(Proof.context -> int -> tactic) -> solver"} \\
@{index_ML_op setSolver: "Proof.context * solver -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op addSolver: "Proof.context * solver -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op setSSolver: "Proof.context * solver -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op addSSolver: "Proof.context * solver -> Proof.context"} \\
\end{mldecls}
A solver is a tactic that attempts to solve a subgoal after
simplification. Its core functionality is to prove trivial subgoals
such as @{prop "True"} and @{text "t = t"}, but object-logics might
be more ambitious. For example, Isabelle/HOL performs a restricted
version of linear arithmetic here.
Solvers are packaged up in abstract type @{ML_type solver}, with
@{ML Simplifier.mk_solver} as the only operation to create a solver.
\medskip Rewriting does not instantiate unknowns. For example,
rewriting alone cannot prove @{text "a \<in> ?A"} since this requires
instantiating @{text "?A"}. The solver, however, is an arbitrary
tactic and may instantiate unknowns as it pleases. This is the only
way the Simplifier can handle a conditional rewrite rule whose
condition contains extra variables. When a simplification tactic is
to be combined with other provers, especially with the Classical
Reasoner, it is important whether it can be considered safe or not.
For this reason a simpset contains two solvers: safe and unsafe.
The standard simplification strategy solely uses the unsafe solver,
which is appropriate in most cases. For special applications where
the simplification process is not allowed to instantiate unknowns
within the goal, simplification starts with the safe solver, but may
still apply the ordinary unsafe one in nested simplifications for
conditional rules or congruences. Note that in this way the overall
tactic is not totally safe: it may instantiate unknowns that appear
also in other subgoals.
\begin{description}
\item @{ML Simplifier.mk_solver}~@{text "name tac"} turns @{text
"tac"} into a solver; the @{text "name"} is only attached as a
comment and has no further significance.
\item @{text "ctxt setSSolver solver"} installs @{text "solver"} as
the safe solver of @{text "ctxt"}.
\item @{text "ctxt addSSolver solver"} adds @{text "solver"} as an
additional safe solver; it will be tried after the solvers which had
already been present in @{text "ctxt"}.
\item @{text "ctxt setSolver solver"} installs @{text "solver"} as the
unsafe solver of @{text "ctxt"}.
\item @{text "ctxt addSolver solver"} adds @{text "solver"} as an
additional unsafe solver; it will be tried after the solvers which
had already been present in @{text "ctxt"}.
\end{description}
\medskip The solver tactic is invoked with the context of the
running Simplifier. Further operations
may be used to retrieve relevant information, such as the list of
local Simplifier premises via @{ML Simplifier.prems_of} --- this
list may be non-empty only if the Simplifier runs in a mode that
utilizes local assumptions (see also \secref{sec:simp-meth}). The
solver is also presented the full goal including its assumptions in
any case. Thus it can use these (e.g.\ by calling @{ML
assume_tac}), even if the Simplifier proper happens to ignore local
premises at the moment.
\medskip As explained before, the subgoaler is also used to solve
the premises of congruence rules. These are usually of the form
@{text "s = ?x"}, where @{text "s"} needs to be simplified and
@{text "?x"} needs to be instantiated with the result. Typically,
the subgoaler will invoke the Simplifier at some point, which will
eventually call the solver. For this reason, solver tactics must be
prepared to solve goals of the form @{text "t = ?x"}, usually by
reflexivity. In particular, reflexivity should be tried before any
of the fancy automated proof tools.
It may even happen that due to simplification the subgoal is no
longer an equality. For example, @{text "False \<longleftrightarrow> ?Q"} could be
rewritten to @{text "\<not> ?Q"}. To cover this case, the solver could
try resolving with the theorem @{text "\<not> False"} of the
object-logic.
\medskip
\begin{warn}
If a premise of a congruence rule cannot be proved, then the
congruence is ignored. This should only happen if the rule is
\emph{conditional} --- that is, contains premises not of the form
@{text "t = ?x"}. Otherwise it indicates that some congruence rule,
or possibly the subgoaler or solver, is faulty.
\end{warn}
\<close>
subsubsection \<open>The looper\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{mldecls}
@{index_ML_op setloop: "Proof.context *
(Proof.context -> int -> tactic) -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op addloop: "Proof.context *
(string * (Proof.context -> int -> tactic))
-> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op delloop: "Proof.context * string -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML Splitter.add_split: "thm -> Proof.context -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML Splitter.del_split: "thm -> Proof.context -> Proof.context"} \\
\end{mldecls}
The looper is a list of tactics that are applied after
simplification, in case the solver failed to solve the simplified
goal. If the looper succeeds, the simplification process is started
all over again. Each of the subgoals generated by the looper is
attacked in turn, in reverse order.
A typical looper is \emph{case splitting}: the expansion of a
conditional. Another possibility is to apply an elimination rule on
the assumptions. More adventurous loopers could start an induction.
\begin{description}
\item @{text "ctxt setloop tac"} installs @{text "tac"} as the only
looper tactic of @{text "ctxt"}.
\item @{text "ctxt addloop (name, tac)"} adds @{text "tac"} as an
additional looper tactic with name @{text "name"}, which is
significant for managing the collection of loopers. The tactic will
be tried after the looper tactics that had already been present in
@{text "ctxt"}.
\item @{text "ctxt delloop name"} deletes the looper tactic that was
associated with @{text "name"} from @{text "ctxt"}.
\item @{ML Splitter.add_split}~@{text "thm ctxt"} adds split tactics
for @{text "thm"} as additional looper tactics of @{text "ctxt"}.
\item @{ML Splitter.del_split}~@{text "thm ctxt"} deletes the split
tactic corresponding to @{text thm} from the looper tactics of
@{text "ctxt"}.
\end{description}
The splitter replaces applications of a given function; the
right-hand side of the replacement can be anything. For example,
here is a splitting rule for conditional expressions:
@{text [display] "?P (if ?Q ?x ?y) \<longleftrightarrow> (?Q \<longrightarrow> ?P ?x) \<and> (\<not> ?Q \<longrightarrow> ?P ?y)"}
Another example is the elimination operator for Cartesian products
(which happens to be called @{text split} in Isabelle/HOL:
@{text [display] "?P (split ?f ?p) \<longleftrightarrow> (\<forall>a b. ?p = (a, b) \<longrightarrow> ?P (f a b))"}
For technical reasons, there is a distinction between case splitting
in the conclusion and in the premises of a subgoal. The former is
done by @{ML Splitter.split_tac} with rules like @{thm [source]
split_if} or @{thm [source] option.split}, which do not split the
subgoal, while the latter is done by @{ML Splitter.split_asm_tac}
with rules like @{thm [source] split_if_asm} or @{thm [source]
option.split_asm}, which split the subgoal. The function @{ML
Splitter.add_split} automatically takes care of which tactic to
call, analyzing the form of the rules given as argument; it is the
same operation behind @{text "split"} attribute or method modifier
syntax in the Isar source language.
Case splits should be allowed only when necessary; they are
expensive and hard to control. Case-splitting on if-expressions in
the conclusion is usually beneficial, so it is enabled by default in
Isabelle/HOL and Isabelle/FOL/ZF.
\begin{warn}
With @{ML Splitter.split_asm_tac} as looper component, the
Simplifier may split subgoals! This might cause unexpected problems
in tactic expressions that silently assume 0 or 1 subgoals after
simplification.
\end{warn}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Forward simplification \label{sec:simp-forward}\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{attribute_def simplified} & : & @{text attribute} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
@@{attribute simplified} opt? @{syntax thmrefs}?
;
opt: '(' ('no_asm' | 'no_asm_simp' | 'no_asm_use') ')'
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{attribute simplified}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"} causes a theorem to
be simplified, either by exactly the specified rules @{text "a\<^sub>1, \<dots>,
a\<^sub>n"}, or the implicit Simplifier context if no arguments are given.
The result is fully simplified by default, including assumptions and
conclusion; the options @{text no_asm} etc.\ tune the Simplifier in
the same way as the for the @{text simp} method.
Note that forward simplification restricts the Simplifier to its
most basic operation of term rewriting; solver and looper tactics
(\secref{sec:simp-strategies}) are \emph{not} involved here. The
@{attribute simplified} attribute should be only rarely required
under normal circumstances.
\end{description}
\<close>
section \<open>The Classical Reasoner \label{sec:classical}\<close>
subsection \<open>Basic concepts\<close>
text \<open>Although Isabelle is generic, many users will be working in
some extension of classical first-order logic. Isabelle/ZF is built
upon theory FOL, while Isabelle/HOL conceptually contains
first-order logic as a fragment. Theorem-proving in predicate logic
is undecidable, but many automated strategies have been developed to
assist in this task.
Isabelle's classical reasoner is a generic package that accepts
certain information about a logic and delivers a suite of automatic
proof tools, based on rules that are classified and declared in the
context. These proof procedures are slow and simplistic compared
with high-end automated theorem provers, but they can save
considerable time and effort in practice. They can prove theorems
such as Pelletier's @{cite pelletier86} problems 40 and 41 in a few
milliseconds (including full proof reconstruction):\<close>
lemma "(\<exists>y. \<forall>x. F x y \<longleftrightarrow> F x x) \<longrightarrow> \<not> (\<forall>x. \<exists>y. \<forall>z. F z y \<longleftrightarrow> \<not> F z x)"
by blast
lemma "(\<forall>z. \<exists>y. \<forall>x. f x y \<longleftrightarrow> f x z \<and> \<not> f x x) \<longrightarrow> \<not> (\<exists>z. \<forall>x. f x z)"
by blast
text \<open>The proof tools are generic. They are not restricted to
first-order logic, and have been heavily used in the development of
the Isabelle/HOL library and applications. The tactics can be
traced, and their components can be called directly; in this manner,
any proof can be viewed interactively.\<close>
subsubsection \<open>The sequent calculus\<close>
text \<open>Isabelle supports natural deduction, which is easy to use for
interactive proof. But natural deduction does not easily lend
itself to automation, and has a bias towards intuitionism. For
certain proofs in classical logic, it can not be called natural.
The \emph{sequent calculus}, a generalization of natural deduction,
is easier to automate.
A \textbf{sequent} has the form @{text "\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>"}, where @{text "\<Gamma>"}
and @{text "\<Delta>"} are sets of formulae.\footnote{For first-order
logic, sequents can equivalently be made from lists or multisets of
formulae.} The sequent @{text "P\<^sub>1, \<dots>, P\<^sub>m \<turnstile> Q\<^sub>1, \<dots>, Q\<^sub>n"} is
\textbf{valid} if @{text "P\<^sub>1 \<and> \<dots> \<and> P\<^sub>m"} implies @{text "Q\<^sub>1 \<or> \<dots> \<or>
Q\<^sub>n"}. Thus @{text "P\<^sub>1, \<dots>, P\<^sub>m"} represent assumptions, each of which
is true, while @{text "Q\<^sub>1, \<dots>, Q\<^sub>n"} represent alternative goals. A
sequent is \textbf{basic} if its left and right sides have a common
formula, as in @{text "P, Q \<turnstile> Q, R"}; basic sequents are trivially
valid.
Sequent rules are classified as \textbf{right} or \textbf{left},
indicating which side of the @{text "\<turnstile>"} symbol they operate on.
Rules that operate on the right side are analogous to natural
deduction's introduction rules, and left rules are analogous to
elimination rules. The sequent calculus analogue of @{text "(\<longrightarrow>I)"}
is the rule
\[
\infer[@{text "(\<longrightarrow>R)"}]{@{text "\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>, P \<longrightarrow> Q"}}{@{text "P, \<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>, Q"}}
\]
Applying the rule backwards, this breaks down some implication on
the right side of a sequent; @{text "\<Gamma>"} and @{text "\<Delta>"} stand for
the sets of formulae that are unaffected by the inference. The
analogue of the pair @{text "(\<or>I1)"} and @{text "(\<or>I2)"} is the
single rule
\[
\infer[@{text "(\<or>R)"}]{@{text "\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>, P \<or> Q"}}{@{text "\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>, P, Q"}}
\]
This breaks down some disjunction on the right side, replacing it by
both disjuncts. Thus, the sequent calculus is a kind of
multiple-conclusion logic.
To illustrate the use of multiple formulae on the right, let us
prove the classical theorem @{text "(P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<or> (Q \<longrightarrow> P)"}. Working
backwards, we reduce this formula to a basic sequent:
\[
\infer[@{text "(\<or>R)"}]{@{text "\<turnstile> (P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<or> (Q \<longrightarrow> P)"}}
{\infer[@{text "(\<longrightarrow>R)"}]{@{text "\<turnstile> (P \<longrightarrow> Q), (Q \<longrightarrow> P)"}}
{\infer[@{text "(\<longrightarrow>R)"}]{@{text "P \<turnstile> Q, (Q \<longrightarrow> P)"}}
{@{text "P, Q \<turnstile> Q, P"}}}}
\]
This example is typical of the sequent calculus: start with the
desired theorem and apply rules backwards in a fairly arbitrary
manner. This yields a surprisingly effective proof procedure.
Quantifiers add only few complications, since Isabelle handles
parameters and schematic variables. See @{cite \<open>Chapter 10\<close>
"paulson-ml2"} for further discussion.\<close>
subsubsection \<open>Simulating sequents by natural deduction\<close>
text \<open>Isabelle can represent sequents directly, as in the
object-logic LK. But natural deduction is easier to work with, and
most object-logics employ it. Fortunately, we can simulate the
sequent @{text "P\<^sub>1, \<dots>, P\<^sub>m \<turnstile> Q\<^sub>1, \<dots>, Q\<^sub>n"} by the Isabelle formula
@{text "P\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<Longrightarrow> P\<^sub>m \<Longrightarrow> \<not> Q\<^sub>2 \<Longrightarrow> ... \<Longrightarrow> \<not> Q\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> Q\<^sub>1"} where the order of
the assumptions and the choice of @{text "Q\<^sub>1"} are arbitrary.
Elim-resolution plays a key role in simulating sequent proofs.
We can easily handle reasoning on the left. Elim-resolution with
the rules @{text "(\<or>E)"}, @{text "(\<bottom>E)"} and @{text "(\<exists>E)"} achieves
a similar effect as the corresponding sequent rules. For the other
connectives, we use sequent-style elimination rules instead of
destruction rules such as @{text "(\<and>E1, 2)"} and @{text "(\<forall>E)"}.
But note that the rule @{text "(\<not>L)"} has no effect under our
representation of sequents!
\[
\infer[@{text "(\<not>L)"}]{@{text "\<not> P, \<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>"}}{@{text "\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>, P"}}
\]
What about reasoning on the right? Introduction rules can only
affect the formula in the conclusion, namely @{text "Q\<^sub>1"}. The
other right-side formulae are represented as negated assumptions,
@{text "\<not> Q\<^sub>2, \<dots>, \<not> Q\<^sub>n"}. In order to operate on one of these, it
must first be exchanged with @{text "Q\<^sub>1"}. Elim-resolution with the
@{text swap} rule has this effect: @{text "\<not> P \<Longrightarrow> (\<not> R \<Longrightarrow> P) \<Longrightarrow> R"}
To ensure that swaps occur only when necessary, each introduction
rule is converted into a swapped form: it is resolved with the
second premise of @{text "(swap)"}. The swapped form of @{text
"(\<and>I)"}, which might be called @{text "(\<not>\<and>E)"}, is
@{text [display] "\<not> (P \<and> Q) \<Longrightarrow> (\<not> R \<Longrightarrow> P) \<Longrightarrow> (\<not> R \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> R"}
Similarly, the swapped form of @{text "(\<longrightarrow>I)"} is
@{text [display] "\<not> (P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> (\<not> R \<Longrightarrow> P \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> R"}
Swapped introduction rules are applied using elim-resolution, which
deletes the negated formula. Our representation of sequents also
requires the use of ordinary introduction rules. If we had no
regard for readability of intermediate goal states, we could treat
the right side more uniformly by representing sequents as @{text
[display] "P\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<Longrightarrow> P\<^sub>m \<Longrightarrow> \<not> Q\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<Longrightarrow> \<not> Q\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> \<bottom>"}
\<close>
subsubsection \<open>Extra rules for the sequent calculus\<close>
text \<open>As mentioned, destruction rules such as @{text "(\<and>E1, 2)"} and
@{text "(\<forall>E)"} must be replaced by sequent-style elimination rules.
In addition, we need rules to embody the classical equivalence
between @{text "P \<longrightarrow> Q"} and @{text "\<not> P \<or> Q"}. The introduction
rules @{text "(\<or>I1, 2)"} are replaced by a rule that simulates
@{text "(\<or>R)"}: @{text [display] "(\<not> Q \<Longrightarrow> P) \<Longrightarrow> P \<or> Q"}
The destruction rule @{text "(\<longrightarrow>E)"} is replaced by @{text [display]
"(P \<longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> (\<not> P \<Longrightarrow> R) \<Longrightarrow> (Q \<Longrightarrow> R) \<Longrightarrow> R"}
Quantifier replication also requires special rules. In classical
logic, @{text "\<exists>x. P x"} is equivalent to @{text "\<not> (\<forall>x. \<not> P x)"};
the rules @{text "(\<exists>R)"} and @{text "(\<forall>L)"} are dual:
\[
\infer[@{text "(\<exists>R)"}]{@{text "\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>, \<exists>x. P x"}}{@{text "\<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>, \<exists>x. P x, P t"}}
\qquad
\infer[@{text "(\<forall>L)"}]{@{text "\<forall>x. P x, \<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>"}}{@{text "P t, \<forall>x. P x, \<Gamma> \<turnstile> \<Delta>"}}
\]
Thus both kinds of quantifier may be replicated. Theorems requiring
multiple uses of a universal formula are easy to invent; consider
@{text [display] "(\<forall>x. P x \<longrightarrow> P (f x)) \<and> P a \<longrightarrow> P (f\<^sup>n a)"} for any
@{text "n > 1"}. Natural examples of the multiple use of an
existential formula are rare; a standard one is @{text "\<exists>x. \<forall>y. P x
\<longrightarrow> P y"}.
Forgoing quantifier replication loses completeness, but gains
decidability, since the search space becomes finite. Many useful
theorems can be proved without replication, and the search generally
delivers its verdict in a reasonable time. To adopt this approach,
represent the sequent rules @{text "(\<exists>R)"}, @{text "(\<exists>L)"} and
@{text "(\<forall>R)"} by @{text "(\<exists>I)"}, @{text "(\<exists>E)"} and @{text "(\<forall>I)"},
respectively, and put @{text "(\<forall>E)"} into elimination form: @{text
[display] "\<forall>x. P x \<Longrightarrow> (P t \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> Q"}
Elim-resolution with this rule will delete the universal formula
after a single use. To replicate universal quantifiers, replace the
rule by @{text [display] "\<forall>x. P x \<Longrightarrow> (P t \<Longrightarrow> \<forall>x. P x \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> Q"}
To replicate existential quantifiers, replace @{text "(\<exists>I)"} by
@{text [display] "(\<not> (\<exists>x. P x) \<Longrightarrow> P t) \<Longrightarrow> \<exists>x. P x"}
All introduction rules mentioned above are also useful in swapped
form.
Replication makes the search space infinite; we must apply the rules
with care. The classical reasoner distinguishes between safe and
unsafe rules, applying the latter only when there is no alternative.
Depth-first search may well go down a blind alley; best-first search
is better behaved in an infinite search space. However, quantifier
replication is too expensive to prove any but the simplest theorems.
\<close>
subsection \<open>Rule declarations\<close>
text \<open>The proof tools of the Classical Reasoner depend on
collections of rules declared in the context, which are classified
as introduction, elimination or destruction and as \emph{safe} or
\emph{unsafe}. In general, safe rules can be attempted blindly,
while unsafe rules must be used with care. A safe rule must never
reduce a provable goal to an unprovable set of subgoals.
The rule @{text "P \<Longrightarrow> P \<or> Q"} is unsafe because it reduces @{text "P
\<or> Q"} to @{text "P"}, which might turn out as premature choice of an
unprovable subgoal. Any rule is unsafe whose premises contain new
unknowns. The elimination rule @{text "\<forall>x. P x \<Longrightarrow> (P t \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> Q"} is
unsafe, since it is applied via elim-resolution, which discards the
assumption @{text "\<forall>x. P x"} and replaces it by the weaker
assumption @{text "P t"}. The rule @{text "P t \<Longrightarrow> \<exists>x. P x"} is
unsafe for similar reasons. The quantifier duplication rule @{text
"\<forall>x. P x \<Longrightarrow> (P t \<Longrightarrow> \<forall>x. P x \<Longrightarrow> Q) \<Longrightarrow> Q"} is unsafe in a different sense:
since it keeps the assumption @{text "\<forall>x. P x"}, it is prone to
looping. In classical first-order logic, all rules are safe except
those mentioned above.
The safe~/ unsafe distinction is vague, and may be regarded merely
as a way of giving some rules priority over others. One could argue
that @{text "(\<or>E)"} is unsafe, because repeated application of it
could generate exponentially many subgoals. Induction rules are
unsafe because inductive proofs are difficult to set up
automatically. Any inference is unsafe that instantiates an unknown
in the proof state --- thus matching must be used, rather than
unification. Even proof by assumption is unsafe if it instantiates
unknowns shared with other subgoals.
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{command_def "print_claset"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & @{text "context \<rightarrow>"} \\
@{attribute_def intro} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def elim} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def dest} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def rule} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def iff} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def swapped} & : & @{text attribute} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
(@@{attribute intro} | @@{attribute elim} | @@{attribute dest}) ('!' | () | '?') @{syntax nat}?
;
@@{attribute rule} 'del'
;
@@{attribute iff} (((() | 'add') '?'?) | 'del')
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{command "print_claset"} prints the collection of rules
declared to the Classical Reasoner, i.e.\ the @{ML_type claset}
within the context.
\item @{attribute intro}, @{attribute elim}, and @{attribute dest}
declare introduction, elimination, and destruction rules,
respectively. By default, rules are considered as \emph{unsafe}
(i.e.\ not applied blindly without backtracking), while ``@{text
"!"}'' classifies as \emph{safe}. Rule declarations marked by
``@{text "?"}'' coincide with those of Isabelle/Pure, cf.\
\secref{sec:pure-meth-att} (i.e.\ are only applied in single steps
of the @{method rule} method). The optional natural number
specifies an explicit weight argument, which is ignored by the
automated reasoning tools, but determines the search order of single
rule steps.
Introduction rules are those that can be applied using ordinary
resolution. Their swapped forms are generated internally, which
will be applied using elim-resolution. Elimination rules are
applied using elim-resolution. Rules are sorted by the number of
new subgoals they will yield; rules that generate the fewest
subgoals will be tried first. Otherwise, later declarations take
precedence over earlier ones.
Rules already present in the context with the same classification
are ignored. A warning is printed if the rule has already been
added with some other classification, but the rule is added anyway
as requested.
\item @{attribute rule}~@{text del} deletes all occurrences of a
rule from the classical context, regardless of its classification as
introduction~/ elimination~/ destruction and safe~/ unsafe.
\item @{attribute iff} declares logical equivalences to the
Simplifier and the Classical reasoner at the same time.
Non-conditional rules result in a safe introduction and elimination
pair; conditional ones are considered unsafe. Rules with negative
conclusion are automatically inverted (using @{text "\<not>"}-elimination
internally).
The ``@{text "?"}'' version of @{attribute iff} declares rules to
the Isabelle/Pure context only, and omits the Simplifier
declaration.
\item @{attribute swapped} turns an introduction rule into an
elimination, by resolving with the classical swap principle @{text
"\<not> P \<Longrightarrow> (\<not> R \<Longrightarrow> P) \<Longrightarrow> R"} in the second position. This is mainly for
illustrative purposes: the Classical Reasoner already swaps rules
internally as explained above.
\end{description}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Structured methods\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{method_def rule} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def contradiction} & : & @{text method} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
@@{method rule} @{syntax thmrefs}?
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{method rule} as offered by the Classical Reasoner is a
refinement over the Pure one (see \secref{sec:pure-meth-att}). Both
versions work the same, but the classical version observes the
classical rule context in addition to that of Isabelle/Pure.
Common object logics (HOL, ZF, etc.) declare a rich collection of
classical rules (even if these would qualify as intuitionistic
ones), but only few declarations to the rule context of
Isabelle/Pure (\secref{sec:pure-meth-att}).
\item @{method contradiction} solves some goal by contradiction,
deriving any result from both @{text "\<not> A"} and @{text A}. Chained
facts, which are guaranteed to participate, may appear in either
order.
\end{description}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Fully automated methods\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{method_def blast} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def auto} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def force} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def fast} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def slow} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def best} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def fastforce} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def slowsimp} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def bestsimp} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def deepen} & : & @{text method} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
@@{method blast} @{syntax nat}? (@{syntax clamod} * )
;
@@{method auto} (@{syntax nat} @{syntax nat})? (@{syntax clasimpmod} * )
;
@@{method force} (@{syntax clasimpmod} * )
;
(@@{method fast} | @@{method slow} | @@{method best}) (@{syntax clamod} * )
;
(@@{method fastforce} | @@{method slowsimp} | @@{method bestsimp})
(@{syntax clasimpmod} * )
;
@@{method deepen} (@{syntax nat} ?) (@{syntax clamod} * )
;
@{syntax_def clamod}:
(('intro' | 'elim' | 'dest') ('!' | () | '?') | 'del') ':' @{syntax thmrefs}
;
@{syntax_def clasimpmod}: ('simp' (() | 'add' | 'del' | 'only') |
('cong' | 'split') (() | 'add' | 'del') |
'iff' (((() | 'add') '?'?) | 'del') |
(('intro' | 'elim' | 'dest') ('!' | () | '?') | 'del')) ':' @{syntax thmrefs}
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{method blast} is a separate classical tableau prover that
uses the same classical rule declarations as explained before.
Proof search is coded directly in ML using special data structures.
A successful proof is then reconstructed using regular Isabelle
inferences. It is faster and more powerful than the other classical
reasoning tools, but has major limitations too.
\begin{itemize}
\item It does not use the classical wrapper tacticals, such as the
integration with the Simplifier of @{method fastforce}.
\item It does not perform higher-order unification, as needed by the
rule @{thm [source=false] rangeI} in HOL. There are often
alternatives to such rules, for example @{thm [source=false]
range_eqI}.
\item Function variables may only be applied to parameters of the
subgoal. (This restriction arises because the prover does not use
higher-order unification.) If other function variables are present
then the prover will fail with the message \texttt{Function Var's
argument not a bound variable}.
\item Its proof strategy is more general than @{method fast} but can
be slower. If @{method blast} fails or seems to be running forever,
try @{method fast} and the other proof tools described below.
\end{itemize}
The optional integer argument specifies a bound for the number of
unsafe steps used in a proof. By default, @{method blast} starts
with a bound of 0 and increases it successively to 20. In contrast,
@{text "(blast lim)"} tries to prove the goal using a search bound
of @{text "lim"}. Sometimes a slow proof using @{method blast} can
be made much faster by supplying the successful search bound to this
proof method instead.
\item @{method auto} combines classical reasoning with
simplification. It is intended for situations where there are a lot
of mostly trivial subgoals; it proves all the easy ones, leaving the
ones it cannot prove. Occasionally, attempting to prove the hard
ones may take a long time.
The optional depth arguments in @{text "(auto m n)"} refer to its
builtin classical reasoning procedures: @{text m} (default 4) is for
@{method blast}, which is tried first, and @{text n} (default 2) is
for a slower but more general alternative that also takes wrappers
into account.
\item @{method force} is intended to prove the first subgoal
completely, using many fancy proof tools and performing a rather
exhaustive search. As a result, proof attempts may take rather long
or diverge easily.
\item @{method fast}, @{method best}, @{method slow} attempt to
prove the first subgoal using sequent-style reasoning as explained
before. Unlike @{method blast}, they construct proofs directly in
Isabelle.
There is a difference in search strategy and back-tracking: @{method
fast} uses depth-first search and @{method best} uses best-first
search (guided by a heuristic function: normally the total size of
the proof state).
Method @{method slow} is like @{method fast}, but conducts a broader
search: it may, when backtracking from a failed proof attempt, undo
even the step of proving a subgoal by assumption.
\item @{method fastforce}, @{method slowsimp}, @{method bestsimp}
are like @{method fast}, @{method slow}, @{method best},
respectively, but use the Simplifier as additional wrapper. The name
@{method fastforce}, reflects the behaviour of this popular method
better without requiring an understanding of its implementation.
\item @{method deepen} works by exhaustive search up to a certain
depth. The start depth is 4 (unless specified explicitly), and the
depth is increased iteratively up to 10. Unsafe rules are modified
to preserve the formula they act on, so that it be used repeatedly.
This method can prove more goals than @{method fast}, but is much
slower, for example if the assumptions have many universal
quantifiers.
\end{description}
Any of the above methods support additional modifiers of the context
of classical (and simplifier) rules, but the ones related to the
Simplifier are explicitly prefixed by @{text simp} here. The
semantics of these ad-hoc rule declarations is analogous to the
attributes given before. Facts provided by forward chaining are
inserted into the goal before commencing proof search.
\<close>
subsection \<open>Partially automated methods\<close>
text \<open>These proof methods may help in situations when the
fully-automated tools fail. The result is a simpler subgoal that
can be tackled by other means, such as by manual instantiation of
quantifiers.
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{method_def safe} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def clarify} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def clarsimp} & : & @{text method} \\
\end{matharray}
@{rail \<open>
(@@{method safe} | @@{method clarify}) (@{syntax clamod} * )
;
@@{method clarsimp} (@{syntax clasimpmod} * )
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{method safe} repeatedly performs safe steps on all subgoals.
It is deterministic, with at most one outcome.
\item @{method clarify} performs a series of safe steps without
splitting subgoals; see also @{method clarify_step}.
\item @{method clarsimp} acts like @{method clarify}, but also does
simplification. Note that if the Simplifier context includes a
splitter for the premises, the subgoal may still be split.
\end{description}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Single-step tactics\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{method_def safe_step} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def inst_step} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def step} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def slow_step} & : & @{text method} \\
@{method_def clarify_step} & : & @{text method} \\
\end{matharray}
These are the primitive tactics behind the automated proof methods
of the Classical Reasoner. By calling them yourself, you can
execute these procedures one step at a time.
\begin{description}
\item @{method safe_step} performs a safe step on the first subgoal.
The safe wrapper tacticals are applied to a tactic that may include
proof by assumption or Modus Ponens (taking care not to instantiate
unknowns), or substitution.
\item @{method inst_step} is like @{method safe_step}, but allows
unknowns to be instantiated.
\item @{method step} is the basic step of the proof procedure, it
operates on the first subgoal. The unsafe wrapper tacticals are
applied to a tactic that tries @{method safe}, @{method inst_step},
or applies an unsafe rule from the context.
\item @{method slow_step} resembles @{method step}, but allows
backtracking between using safe rules with instantiation (@{method
inst_step}) and using unsafe rules. The resulting search space is
larger.
\item @{method clarify_step} performs a safe step on the first
subgoal; no splitting step is applied. For example, the subgoal
@{text "A \<and> B"} is left as a conjunction. Proof by assumption,
Modus Ponens, etc., may be performed provided they do not
instantiate unknowns. Assumptions of the form @{text "x = t"} may
be eliminated. The safe wrapper tactical is applied.
\end{description}
\<close>
subsection \<open>Modifying the search step\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{mldecls}
@{index_ML_type wrapper: "(int -> tactic) -> (int -> tactic)"} \\[0.5ex]
@{index_ML_op addSWrapper: "Proof.context *
(string * (Proof.context -> wrapper)) -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op addSbefore: "Proof.context *
(string * (Proof.context -> int -> tactic)) -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op addSafter: "Proof.context *
(string * (Proof.context -> int -> tactic)) -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op delSWrapper: "Proof.context * string -> Proof.context"} \\[0.5ex]
@{index_ML_op addWrapper: "Proof.context *
(string * (Proof.context -> wrapper)) -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op addbefore: "Proof.context *
(string * (Proof.context -> int -> tactic)) -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op addafter: "Proof.context *
(string * (Proof.context -> int -> tactic)) -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML_op delWrapper: "Proof.context * string -> Proof.context"} \\[0.5ex]
@{index_ML addSss: "Proof.context -> Proof.context"} \\
@{index_ML addss: "Proof.context -> Proof.context"} \\
\end{mldecls}
The proof strategy of the Classical Reasoner is simple. Perform as
many safe inferences as possible; or else, apply certain safe rules,
allowing instantiation of unknowns; or else, apply an unsafe rule.
The tactics also eliminate assumptions of the form @{text "x = t"}
by substitution if they have been set up to do so. They may perform
a form of Modus Ponens: if there are assumptions @{text "P \<longrightarrow> Q"} and
@{text "P"}, then replace @{text "P \<longrightarrow> Q"} by @{text "Q"}.
The classical reasoning tools --- except @{method blast} --- allow
to modify this basic proof strategy by applying two lists of
arbitrary \emph{wrapper tacticals} to it. The first wrapper list,
which is considered to contain safe wrappers only, affects @{method
safe_step} and all the tactics that call it. The second one, which
may contain unsafe wrappers, affects the unsafe parts of @{method
step}, @{method slow_step}, and the tactics that call them. A
wrapper transforms each step of the search, for example by
attempting other tactics before or after the original step tactic.
All members of a wrapper list are applied in turn to the respective
step tactic.
Initially the two wrapper lists are empty, which means no
modification of the step tactics. Safe and unsafe wrappers are added
to a claset with the functions given below, supplying them with
wrapper names. These names may be used to selectively delete
wrappers.
\begin{description}
\item @{text "ctxt addSWrapper (name, wrapper)"} adds a new wrapper,
which should yield a safe tactic, to modify the existing safe step
tactic.
\item @{text "ctxt addSbefore (name, tac)"} adds the given tactic as a
safe wrapper, such that it is tried \emph{before} each safe step of
the search.
\item @{text "ctxt addSafter (name, tac)"} adds the given tactic as a
safe wrapper, such that it is tried when a safe step of the search
would fail.
\item @{text "ctxt delSWrapper name"} deletes the safe wrapper with
the given name.
\item @{text "ctxt addWrapper (name, wrapper)"} adds a new wrapper to
modify the existing (unsafe) step tactic.
\item @{text "ctxt addbefore (name, tac)"} adds the given tactic as an
unsafe wrapper, such that it its result is concatenated
\emph{before} the result of each unsafe step.
\item @{text "ctxt addafter (name, tac)"} adds the given tactic as an
unsafe wrapper, such that it its result is concatenated \emph{after}
the result of each unsafe step.
\item @{text "ctxt delWrapper name"} deletes the unsafe wrapper with
the given name.
\item @{text "addSss"} adds the simpset of the context to its
classical set. The assumptions and goal will be simplified, in a
rather safe way, after each safe step of the search.
\item @{text "addss"} adds the simpset of the context to its
classical set. The assumptions and goal will be simplified, before
the each unsafe step of the search.
\end{description}
\<close>
section \<open>Object-logic setup \label{sec:object-logic}\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
@{command_def "judgment"} & : & @{text "theory \<rightarrow> theory"} \\
@{method_def atomize} & : & @{text method} \\
@{attribute_def atomize} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def rule_format} & : & @{text attribute} \\
@{attribute_def rulify} & : & @{text attribute} \\
\end{matharray}
The very starting point for any Isabelle object-logic is a ``truth
judgment'' that links object-level statements to the meta-logic
(with its minimal language of @{text prop} that covers universal
quantification @{text "\<And>"} and implication @{text "\<Longrightarrow>"}).
Common object-logics are sufficiently expressive to internalize rule
statements over @{text "\<And>"} and @{text "\<Longrightarrow>"} within their own
language. This is useful in certain situations where a rule needs
to be viewed as an atomic statement from the meta-level perspective,
e.g.\ @{text "\<And>x. x \<in> A \<Longrightarrow> P x"} versus @{text "\<forall>x \<in> A. P x"}.
From the following language elements, only the @{method atomize}
method and @{attribute rule_format} attribute are occasionally
required by end-users, the rest is for those who need to setup their
own object-logic. In the latter case existing formulations of
Isabelle/FOL or Isabelle/HOL may be taken as realistic examples.
Generic tools may refer to the information provided by object-logic
declarations internally.
@{rail \<open>
@@{command judgment} @{syntax name} '::' @{syntax type} @{syntax mixfix}?
;
@@{attribute atomize} ('(' 'full' ')')?
;
@@{attribute rule_format} ('(' 'noasm' ')')?
\<close>}
\begin{description}
\item @{command "judgment"}~@{text "c :: \<sigma> (mx)"} declares constant
@{text c} as the truth judgment of the current object-logic. Its
type @{text \<sigma>} should specify a coercion of the category of
object-level propositions to @{text prop} of the Pure meta-logic;
the mixfix annotation @{text "(mx)"} would typically just link the
object language (internally of syntactic category @{text logic})
with that of @{text prop}. Only one @{command "judgment"}
declaration may be given in any theory development.
\item @{method atomize} (as a method) rewrites any non-atomic
premises of a sub-goal, using the meta-level equations declared via
@{attribute atomize} (as an attribute) beforehand. As a result,
heavily nested goals become amenable to fundamental operations such
as resolution (cf.\ the @{method (Pure) rule} method). Giving the ``@{text
"(full)"}'' option here means to turn the whole subgoal into an
object-statement (if possible), including the outermost parameters
and assumptions as well.
A typical collection of @{attribute atomize} rules for a particular
object-logic would provide an internalization for each of the
connectives of @{text "\<And>"}, @{text "\<Longrightarrow>"}, and @{text "\<equiv>"}.
Meta-level conjunction should be covered as well (this is
particularly important for locales, see \secref{sec:locale}).
\item @{attribute rule_format} rewrites a theorem by the equalities
declared as @{attribute rulify} rules in the current object-logic.
By default, the result is fully normalized, including assumptions
and conclusions at any depth. The @{text "(no_asm)"} option
restricts the transformation to the conclusion of a rule.
In common object-logics (HOL, FOL, ZF), the effect of @{attribute
rule_format} is to replace (bounded) universal quantification
(@{text "\<forall>"}) and implication (@{text "\<longrightarrow>"}) by the corresponding
rule statements over @{text "\<And>"} and @{text "\<Longrightarrow>"}.
\end{description}
\<close>
section \<open>Tracing higher-order unification\<close>
text \<open>
\begin{tabular}{rcll}
@{attribute_def unify_trace_simp} & : & @{text "attribute"} & default @{text "false"} \\
@{attribute_def unify_trace_types} & : & @{text "attribute"} & default @{text "false"} \\
@{attribute_def unify_trace_bound} & : & @{text "attribute"} & default @{text "50"} \\
@{attribute_def unify_search_bound} & : & @{text "attribute"} & default @{text "60"} \\
\end{tabular}
\medskip
Higher-order unification works well in most practical situations,
but sometimes needs extra care to identify problems. These tracing
options may help.
\begin{description}
\item @{attribute unify_trace_simp} controls tracing of the
simplification phase of higher-order unification.
\item @{attribute unify_trace_types} controls warnings of
incompleteness, when unification is not considering all possible
instantiations of schematic type variables.
\item @{attribute unify_trace_bound} determines the depth where
unification starts to print tracing information once it reaches
depth; 0 for full tracing. At the default value, tracing
information is almost never printed in practice.
\item @{attribute unify_search_bound} prevents unification from
searching past the given depth. Because of this bound, higher-order
unification cannot return an infinite sequence, though it can return
an exponentially long one. The search rarely approaches the default
value in practice. If the search is cut off, unification prints a
warning ``Unification bound exceeded''.
\end{description}
\begin{warn}
Options for unification cannot be modified in a local context. Only
the global theory content is taken into account.
\end{warn}
\<close>
end