author | blanchet |
Thu, 30 Sep 2010 19:15:47 +0200 | |
changeset 39895 | a91a84b1dfdd |
parent 23733 | 3f8ad7418e55 |
permissions | -rw-r--r-- |
(*<*)theory CTLind imports CTL begin(*>*) subsection{*CTL Revisited*} text{*\label{sec:CTL-revisited} \index{CTL|(}% The purpose of this section is twofold: to demonstrate some of the induction principles and heuristics discussed above and to show how inductive definitions can simplify proofs. In \S\ref{sec:CTL} we gave a fairly involved proof of the correctness of a model checker for CTL\@. In particular the proof of the @{thm[source]infinity_lemma} on the way to @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} is not as simple as one might expect, due to the @{text SOME} operator involved. Below we give a simpler proof of @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} based on an auxiliary inductive definition. Let us call a (finite or infinite) path \emph{@{term A}-avoiding} if it does not touch any node in the set @{term A}. Then @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} says that if no infinite path from some state @{term s} is @{term A}-avoiding, then @{prop"s \<in> lfp(af A)"}. We prove this by inductively defining the set @{term"Avoid s A"} of states reachable from @{term s} by a finite @{term A}-avoiding path: % Second proof of opposite direction, directly by well-founded induction % on the initial segment of M that avoids A. *} inductive_set Avoid :: "state \<Rightarrow> state set \<Rightarrow> state set" for s :: state and A :: "state set" where "s \<in> Avoid s A" | "\<lbrakk> t \<in> Avoid s A; t \<notin> A; (t,u) \<in> M \<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> u \<in> Avoid s A"; text{* It is easy to see that for any infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f} with @{prop"f(0::nat) \<in> Avoid s A"} there is an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path starting with @{term s} because (by definition of @{const Avoid}) there is a finite @{term A}-avoiding path from @{term s} to @{term"f(0::nat)"}. The proof is by induction on @{prop"f(0::nat) \<in> Avoid s A"}. However, this requires the following reformulation, as explained in \S\ref{sec:ind-var-in-prems} above; the @{text rule_format} directive undoes the reformulation after the proof. *} lemma ex_infinite_path[rule_format]: "t \<in> Avoid s A \<Longrightarrow> \<forall>f\<in>Paths t. (\<forall>i. f i \<notin> A) \<longrightarrow> (\<exists>p\<in>Paths s. \<forall>i. p i \<notin> A)"; apply(erule Avoid.induct); apply(blast); apply(clarify); apply(drule_tac x = "\<lambda>i. case i of 0 \<Rightarrow> t | Suc i \<Rightarrow> f i" in bspec); apply(simp_all add: Paths_def split: nat.split); done text{*\noindent The base case (@{prop"t = s"}) is trivial and proved by @{text blast}. In the induction step, we have an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f} starting from @{term u}, a successor of @{term t}. Now we simply instantiate the @{text"\<forall>f\<in>Paths t"} in the induction hypothesis by the path starting with @{term t} and continuing with @{term f}. That is what the above $\lambda$-term expresses. Simplification shows that this is a path starting with @{term t} and that the instantiated induction hypothesis implies the conclusion. Now we come to the key lemma. Assuming that no infinite @{term A}-avoiding path starts from @{term s}, we want to show @{prop"s \<in> lfp(af A)"}. For the inductive proof this must be generalized to the statement that every point @{term t} ``between'' @{term s} and @{term A}, in other words all of @{term"Avoid s A"}, is contained in @{term"lfp(af A)"}: *} lemma Avoid_in_lfp[rule_format(no_asm)]: "\<forall>p\<in>Paths s. \<exists>i. p i \<in> A \<Longrightarrow> t \<in> Avoid s A \<longrightarrow> t \<in> lfp(af A)"; txt{*\noindent The proof is by induction on the ``distance'' between @{term t} and @{term A}. Remember that @{prop"lfp(af A) = A \<union> M\<inverse> `` lfp(af A)"}. If @{term t} is already in @{term A}, then @{prop"t \<in> lfp(af A)"} is trivial. If @{term t} is not in @{term A} but all successors are in @{term"lfp(af A)"} (induction hypothesis), then @{prop"t \<in> lfp(af A)"} is again trivial. The formal counterpart of this proof sketch is a well-founded induction on~@{term M} restricted to @{term"Avoid s A - A"}, roughly speaking: @{term[display]"{(y,x). (x,y) \<in> M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}"} As we shall see presently, the absence of infinite @{term A}-avoiding paths starting from @{term s} implies well-foundedness of this relation. For the moment we assume this and proceed with the induction: *} apply(subgoal_tac "wf{(y,x). (x,y) \<in> M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}"); apply(erule_tac a = t in wf_induct); apply(clarsimp); (*<*)apply(rename_tac t)(*>*) txt{*\noindent @{subgoals[display,indent=0,margin=65]} Now the induction hypothesis states that if @{prop"t \<notin> A"} then all successors of @{term t} that are in @{term"Avoid s A"} are in @{term"lfp (af A)"}. Unfolding @{term lfp} in the conclusion of the first subgoal once, we have to prove that @{term t} is in @{term A} or all successors of @{term t} are in @{term"lfp (af A)"}. But if @{term t} is not in @{term A}, the second @{const Avoid}-rule implies that all successors of @{term t} are in @{term"Avoid s A"}, because we also assume @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"}. Hence, by the induction hypothesis, all successors of @{term t} are indeed in @{term"lfp(af A)"}. Mechanically: *} apply(subst lfp_unfold[OF mono_af]); apply(simp (no_asm) add: af_def); apply(blast intro: Avoid.intros); txt{* Having proved the main goal, we return to the proof obligation that the relation used above is indeed well-founded. This is proved by contradiction: if the relation is not well-founded then there exists an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path all in @{term"Avoid s A"}, by theorem @{thm[source]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain}: @{thm[display]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain[no_vars]} From lemma @{thm[source]ex_infinite_path} the existence of an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path starting in @{term s} follows, contradiction. *} apply(erule contrapos_pp); apply(simp add: wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain); apply(erule exE); apply(rule ex_infinite_path); apply(auto simp add: Paths_def); done text{* The @{text"(no_asm)"} modifier of the @{text"rule_format"} directive in the statement of the lemma means that the assumption is left unchanged; otherwise the @{text"\<forall>p"} would be turned into a @{text"\<And>p"}, which would complicate matters below. As it is, @{thm[source]Avoid_in_lfp} is now @{thm[display]Avoid_in_lfp[no_vars]} The main theorem is simply the corollary where @{prop"t = s"}, when the assumption @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"} is trivially true by the first @{const Avoid}-rule. Isabelle confirms this:% \index{CTL|)}*} theorem AF_lemma2: "{s. \<forall>p \<in> Paths s. \<exists> i. p i \<in> A} \<subseteq> lfp(af A)"; by(auto elim: Avoid_in_lfp intro: Avoid.intros); (*<*)end(*>*)