*** empty log message ***
authornipkow
Fri, 13 Oct 2000 18:25:34 +0200
changeset 10218 54411746c549
parent 10217 e61e7e1eacaf
child 10219 eb28637c72ce
*** empty log message ***
doc-src/TutorialI/CTL/CTLind.thy
doc-src/TutorialI/Inductive/document/root.tex
--- /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
+++ b/doc-src/TutorialI/CTL/CTLind.thy	Fri Oct 13 18:25:34 2000 +0200
@@ -0,0 +1,136 @@
+(*<*)theory CTLind = CTL:(*>*)
+
+subsection{*CTL revisited*}
+
+text{*\label{sec:CTL-revisited}
+In \S\ref{sec:CTL} we gave a fairly involved proof of the correctness of a
+model checker for CTL. In particular the proof of the
+@{thm[source]infinity_lemma} on the way to @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} is not as
+simple as one might intuitively expect, due to the @{text SOME} operator
+involved. The purpose of this section is to show how an inductive definition
+can help to simplify the proof of @{thm[source]AF_lemma2}.
+
+Let us call a (finite or infinite) path \emph{@{term A}-avoiding} if it does
+not touch any node in the set @{term A}. Then @{thm[source]AF_lemma2} says
+that if no infinite path from some state @{term s} is @{term A}-avoiding,
+then @{prop"s \<in> lfp(af A)"}. We prove this by inductively defining the set
+@{term"Avoid s A"} of states reachable from @{term s} by a finite @{term
+A}-avoiding path:
+% Second proof of opposite direction, directly by wellfounded induction
+% on the initial segment of M that avoids A.
+*}
+
+consts Avoid :: "state \<Rightarrow> state set \<Rightarrow> state set";
+inductive "Avoid s A"
+intros "s \<in> Avoid s A"
+       "\<lbrakk> t \<in> Avoid s A; t \<notin> A; (t,u) \<in> M \<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> u \<in> Avoid s A";
+
+text{*
+It is easy to see that for any infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f}
+with @{prop"f 0 \<in> Avoid s A"} there is an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path
+starting with @{term s} because (by definition of @{term Avoid}) there is a
+finite @{term A}-avoiding path from @{term s} to @{term"f 0"}.
+The proof is by induction on @{prop"f 0 \<in> Avoid s A"}. However,
+this requires the following
+reformulation, as explained in \S\ref{sec:ind-var-in-prems} above;
+the @{text rule_format} directive undoes the reformulation after the proof.
+*}
+
+lemma ex_infinite_path[rule_format]:
+  "t \<in> Avoid s A  \<Longrightarrow>
+   \<forall>f\<in>Paths t. (\<forall>i. f i \<notin> A) \<longrightarrow> (\<exists>p\<in>Paths s. \<forall>i. p i \<notin> A)";
+apply(erule Avoid.induct);
+ apply(blast);
+apply(clarify);
+apply(drule_tac x = "\<lambda>i. case i of 0 \<Rightarrow> t | Suc i \<Rightarrow> f i" in bspec);
+apply(simp_all add:Paths_def split:nat.split);
+done
+
+text{*\noindent
+The base case (@{prop"t = s"}) is trivial (@{text blast}).
+In the induction step, we have an infinite @{term A}-avoiding path @{term f}
+starting from @{term u}, a successor of @{term t}. Now we simply instantiate
+the @{text"\<forall>f\<in>Paths t"} in the induction hypothesis by the path starting with
+@{term t} and continuing with @{term f}. That is what the above $\lambda$-term
+expresses. That fact that this is a path starting with @{term t} and that
+the instantiated induction hypothesis implies the conclusion is shown by
+simplification.
+
+Now we come to the key lemma. It says that if @{term t} can be reached by a
+finite @{term A}-avoiding path from @{term s}, then @{prop"t \<in> lfp(af A)"},
+provided there is no infinite @{term A}-avoiding path starting from @{term
+s}.
+*}
+
+lemma Avoid_in_lfp[rule_format(no_asm)]:
+  "\<forall>p\<in>Paths s. \<exists>i. p i \<in> A \<Longrightarrow> t \<in> Avoid s A \<longrightarrow> t \<in> lfp(af A)";
+txt{*\noindent
+The trick is not to induct on @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"}, as already the base
+case would be a problem, but to proceed by wellfounded induction @{term
+t}. Hence @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"} needs to be brought into the conclusion as
+well, which the directive @{text rule_format} undoes at the end (see below).
+But induction with respect to which wellfounded relation? The restriction
+of @{term M} to @{term"Avoid s A"}:
+@{term[display]"{(y,x). (x,y) \<in> M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> y \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}"}
+As we shall see in a moment, the absence of infinite @{term A}-avoiding paths
+starting from @{term s} implies wellfoundedness of this relation. For the
+moment we assume this and proceed with the induction:
+*}
+
+apply(subgoal_tac
+  "wf{(y,x). (x,y)\<in>M \<and> x \<in> Avoid s A \<and> y \<in> Avoid s A \<and> x \<notin> A}");
+ apply(erule_tac a = t in wf_induct);
+ apply(clarsimp);
+
+txt{*\noindent
+Now can assume additionally (induction hypothesis) that if @{prop"t \<notin> A"}
+then all successors of @{term t} that are in @{term"Avoid s A"} are in
+@{term"lfp (af A)"}. To prove the actual goal we unfold @{term lfp} once. Now
+we have to prove that @{term t} is in @{term A} or all successors of @{term
+t} are in @{term"lfp (af A)"}. If @{term t} is not in @{term A}, the second
+@{term Avoid}-rule implies that all successors of @{term t} are in
+@{term"Avoid s A"} (because we also assume @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"}), and
+hence, by the induction hypothesis, all successors of @{term t} are indeed in
+@{term"lfp(af A)"}. Mechanically:
+*}
+
+ apply(rule ssubst [OF lfp_unfold[OF mono_af]]);
+ apply(simp only: af_def);
+ apply(blast intro:Avoid.intros);
+
+txt{*
+Having proved the main goal we return to the proof obligation that the above
+relation is indeed wellfounded. This is proved by contraposition: we assume
+the relation is not wellfounded. Thus there exists an infinite @{term
+A}-avoiding path all in @{term"Avoid s A"}, by theorem
+@{thm[source]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain}:
+@{thm[display]wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain[no_vars]}
+From lemma @{thm[source]ex_infinite_path} the existence of an infinite
+@{term A}-avoiding path starting in @{term s} follows, just as required for
+the contraposition.
+*}
+
+apply(erule contrapos2);
+apply(simp add:wf_iff_no_infinite_down_chain);
+apply(erule exE);
+apply(rule ex_infinite_path);
+apply(auto simp add:Paths_def);
+done
+
+text{*
+The @{text"(no_asm)"} modifier of the @{text"rule_format"} directive means
+that the assumption is left unchanged---otherwise the @{text"\<forall>p"} is turned
+into a @{text"\<And>p"}, which would complicate matters below. As it is,
+@{thm[source]Avoid_in_lfp} is now
+@{thm[display]Avoid_in_lfp[no_vars]}
+The main theorem is simply the corollary where @{prop"t = s"},
+in which case the assumption @{prop"t \<in> Avoid s A"} is trivially true
+by the first @{term Avoid}-rule). Isabelle confirms this:
+*}
+
+theorem AF_lemma2:
+  "{s. \<forall>p \<in> Paths s. \<exists> i. p i \<in> A} \<subseteq> lfp(af A)";
+by(auto elim:Avoid_in_lfp intro:Avoid.intros);
+
+
+(*<*)end(*>*)
--- /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
+++ b/doc-src/TutorialI/Inductive/document/root.tex	Fri Oct 13 18:25:34 2000 +0200
@@ -0,0 +1,4 @@
+\documentclass{article}
+\begin{document}
+xxx
+\end{document}