*** empty log message ***
authornipkow
Fri, 28 Jun 2002 20:01:09 +0200
changeset 13258 8f394f266025
parent 13257 1b7104a1c0bd
child 13259 01fa0c8dbc92
*** empty log message ***
doc-src/TutorialI/Overview/Isar0.thy
doc-src/TutorialI/Overview/delete-verbatim
doc-src/TutorialI/Overview/makeDemo
--- /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
+++ b/doc-src/TutorialI/Overview/Isar0.thy	Fri Jun 28 20:01:09 2002 +0200
@@ -0,0 +1,308 @@
+theory Isar0 = Main:
+
+(*
+proof ::= "proof" [method] statement* "qed"
+        | "by" method
+statement ::= "fix" variables
+            | "assume" proposition*
+            | ["then"] ("show" | "have") proposition proof
+proposition ::= [label":"] string
+
+Typical skelton:
+
+proof
+assume <assumptions>
+have <formula1> -- intermediate result
+:
+have <formulan> -- intermediate result
+show ?thesis -- the conclusion
+end
+*)
+
+lemma "A \<longrightarrow> A"
+proof (rule impI)
+  assume A: "A"
+  show "A" by(rule A)
+qed
+
+(* Operational reading: assume A - show A proves "A \<Longrightarrow> A", which rule impI
+turns into the desired "A \<longrightarrow> A".  Too much (operational) text *)
+
+(* 1st Principle: let "proof" select the rule automatically; based on the
+goal and a predefined list of (introduction) rules. Here: impI is found
+automatically: *)
+
+lemma "A \<longrightarrow> A"
+proof
+  assume A: "A"
+  show "A" by(rule A)
+qed
+
+(* Proof by assumption should be trivial. Method "." does just that (and a
+bit more - see later). Thus naming of assumptions is often superfluous. *)
+
+lemma "A \<longrightarrow> A"
+proof
+  assume "A"
+  have "A" .
+qed
+
+(* To hide proofs by assumption, by(method) first applies method and then
+tries to solve all remaining subgoals by assumption. *)
+
+lemma "A \<longrightarrow> A & A"
+proof
+  assume A
+  show "A & A" by(rule conjI)
+qed
+
+(* Proofs of the form by(rule <rule>) can be abbreviated to ".." if <rule> is
+one of the predefined introduction rules (for user supplied rules see below).
+Thus
+*)
+
+lemma "A \<longrightarrow> A & A"
+proof
+  assume A
+  show "A & A" ..
+qed
+
+(* What happens: applies "conj" (first "."), then solves the two subgoals by
+assumptions (second ".") *)
+
+(* Now: elimination *)
+
+lemma "A & B \<longrightarrow> B & A"
+proof
+  assume AB: "A & B"
+  show "B & A"
+  proof (rule conjE[OF AB])
+    assume A and B
+    show ?thesis .. --"thesis = statement in previous show"
+  qed
+qed
+
+(* Again: too much text.
+
+Elimination rules are used to conclude new stuff from old. In Isar they are
+triggered by propositions being fed INTO a proof block. Syntax:
+from <previously proved propositions> show \<dots>
+applies an elimination rule whose first premise matches one of the <previously proved propositions>. Thus:
+*)
+
+lemma "A & B \<longrightarrow> B & A"
+proof
+  assume AB: "A & B"
+  from AB show "B & A"
+  proof
+    assume A and B
+    show ?thesis ..
+  qed
+qed
+
+(* 
+2nd principle: try to arrange sequence of propositions in a UNIX like
+pipe, such that the proof of the next proposition uses the previous
+one. The previous proposition can be referred to via "this".
+This greatly reduces the need for explicit naming of propositions.
+*)
+lemma "A & B \<longrightarrow> B & A"
+proof
+  assume "A & B"
+  from this show "B & A"
+  proof
+    assume A and B
+    show ?thesis ..
+  qed
+qed
+
+(* Final simplification: "from this" = "thus".
+
+Alternative: pure forward reasoning: *)
+
+lemma "A & B --> B & A"
+proof
+  assume ab: "A & B"
+  from ab have a: A ..
+  from ab have b: B ..
+  from b a show "B & A" ..
+qed
+
+(* New: itermediate haves *)
+
+(* The predefined introduction and elimination rules include all the usual
+natural deduction rules for propositional logic. Here is a longer example: *)
+
+lemma "~(A & B) \<longrightarrow> ~A | ~B"
+proof
+  assume n: "~(A & B)"
+  show "~A | ~B"
+  proof (rule ccontr)
+    assume nn: "~(~ A | ~B)"
+    from n show False
+    proof
+      show "A & B"
+      proof
+	show A
+	proof (rule ccontr)
+	  assume "~A"
+	  have "\<not> A \<or> \<not> B" ..
+	  from nn this show False ..
+	qed
+      next
+	show B
+	proof (rule ccontr)
+	  assume "~B"
+	  have "\<not> A \<or> \<not> B" ..
+	  from nn this show False ..
+	qed
+      qed
+    qed
+  qed
+qed;
+
+(* New:
+
+1. Multiple subgoals. When showing "A & B" we need to show both A and B.
+Each subgoal is proved separately, in ANY order. The individual proofs are
+separated by "next".
+
+2.  "have" for proving an intermediate fact
+*)
+
+subsection{*Becoming more concise*}
+
+(* Normally want to prove rules expressed with \<Longrightarrow>, not \<longrightarrow> *)
+
+lemma "\<lbrakk> A \<Longrightarrow> False \<rbrakk> \<Longrightarrow> \<not> A"
+proof
+  assume "A \<Longrightarrow> False" A
+  thus False .
+qed
+
+(* In this case the "proof" works on the "~A", thus selecting notI
+
+Now: avoid repeating formulae (which may be large). *)
+
+lemma "(large_formula \<Longrightarrow> False) \<Longrightarrow> ~ large_formula"
+      (is "(?P \<Longrightarrow> _) \<Longrightarrow> _")
+proof
+  assume "?P \<Longrightarrow> False" ?P
+  thus False .
+qed
+
+(* Even better: can state assumptions directly *)
+
+lemma assumes A: "large_formula \<Longrightarrow> False"
+      shows "~ large_formula" (is "~ ?P")
+proof
+  assume ?P
+  from A show False .
+qed;
+
+
+(* Predicate calculus. Keyword fix introduces new local variables into a
+proof. Corresponds to !! just like assume-show corresponds to \<Longrightarrow> *)
+
+lemma assumes P: "!x. P x" shows "!x. P(f x)"
+proof --"allI"
+  fix x
+  from P show "P(f x)" .. --"allE"
+qed
+
+lemma assumes Pf: "EX x. P (f x)" shows "EX y. P y"
+proof -
+  from Pf show ?thesis
+  proof  --"exE"
+    fix a
+    assume "P(f a)"
+    show ?thesis ..  --"exI"
+  qed
+qed
+
+text {*
+ Explicit $\exists$-elimination as seen above can become quite
+ cumbersome in practice.  The derived Isar language element
+ ``\isakeyword{obtain}'' provides a more handsome way to do
+ generalized existence reasoning.
+*}
+
+lemma assumes Pf: "EX x. P (f x)" shows "EX y. P y"
+proof -
+  from Pf obtain a where "P (f a)" ..  --"exE"
+  thus "EX y. P y" ..  --"exI"
+qed
+
+text {*
+ Technically, \isakeyword{obtain} is similar to \isakeyword{fix} and
+ \isakeyword{assume} together with a soundness proof of the
+ elimination involved.  Thus it behaves similar to any other forward
+ proof element.  Also note that due to the nature of general existence
+ reasoning involved here, any result exported from the context of an
+ \isakeyword{obtain} statement may \emph{not} refer to the parameters
+ introduced there.
+*}
+
+lemma assumes ex: "EX x. ALL y. P x y" shows "ALL y. EX x. P x y"
+proof  --"allI"
+  fix y
+  from ex obtain x where "ALL y. P x y" ..  --"exE"
+  from this have "P x y" ..  --"allE"
+  thus "EX x. P x y" ..  --"exI"
+qed
+
+(* some example with blast, if . and .. fail *)
+
+theorem "EX S. S ~: range (f :: 'a => 'a set)"
+proof
+  let ?S = "{x. x ~: f x}"
+  show "?S ~: range f"
+  proof
+    assume "?S : range f"
+    then obtain y where fy: "?S = f y" ..
+    show False
+    proof (cases)
+      assume "y : ?S"
+      with fy show False by blast
+    next
+      assume "y ~: ?S"
+      with fy show False by blast
+    qed
+  qed
+qed
+
+theorem "EX S. S ~: range (f :: 'a => 'a set)"
+proof
+  let ?S = "{x. x ~: f x}"
+  show "?S ~: range f"
+  proof
+    assume "?S : range f"
+    then obtain y where eq: "?S = f y" ..
+    show False
+    proof (cases)
+      assume A: "y : ?S"
+      hence isin: "y : f y"   by(simp add:eq)
+      from A have "y ~: f y"  by simp
+      with isin show False    by contradiction
+    next
+      assume A: "y ~: ?S"
+      hence notin: "y ~: f y"  by(simp add:eq)
+      from A have "y : f y"    by simp
+      with notin show False    by contradiction
+    qed
+  qed
+qed
+
+text {*
+  How much creativity is required?  As it happens, Isabelle can prove
+  this theorem automatically using best-first search.  Depth-first
+  search would diverge, but best-first search successfully navigates
+  through the large search space.  The context of Isabelle's classical
+  prover contains rules for the relevant constructs of HOL's set
+  theory.
+*}
+
+theorem "EX S. S ~: range (f :: 'a => 'a set)"
+  by best
+
+end
--- a/doc-src/TutorialI/Overview/delete-verbatim	Fri Jun 28 19:51:40 2002 +0200
+++ /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
@@ -1,34 +0,0 @@
-#!/usr/bin/perl -w
-
-sub doit {
-    my ($file) = @_;
-
-    open (FILE, $file) || die $!;
-    undef $/; $text = <FILE>; $/ = "\n";
-    close FILE || die $!;
-
-    $_ = $text;
-
-    s/text_raw\{\*([^*]|\*[^}])*\*\}//sg;       # actual work done here
-    s/text\{\*([^*]|\*[^}])*\*\}//sg;       # actual work done here
-    s/\(\*<\*\)//sg;
-    s/\(\*>\*\)//sg;
-
-    $result = $_;
-
-    if ($text ne $result) {
-        print STDERR "fixing $file\n";
-#        if (! -f "$file~~") {
-#            rename $file, "$file~~" || die $!;
-#        }
-        open (FILE, "> Demo/$file") || die $!;
-        print FILE $result;
-        close FILE || die $!;
-    }
-}
-
-
-foreach $file (@ARGV) {
-  eval { &doit($file); };
-  if ($@) { print STDERR "*** doit $file: ", $@, "\n"; }
-}
--- /dev/null	Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000
+++ b/doc-src/TutorialI/Overview/makeDemo	Fri Jun 28 20:01:09 2002 +0200
@@ -0,0 +1,34 @@
+#!/usr/bin/perl -w
+
+sub doit {
+    my ($file) = @_;
+
+    open (FILE, $file) || die $!;
+    undef $/; $text = <FILE>; $/ = "\n";
+    close FILE || die $!;
+
+    $_ = $text;
+
+    s/text_raw\{\*([^*]|\*[^}])*\*\}//sg;       # actual work done here
+    s/text\{\*([^*]|\*[^}])*\*\}//sg;       # actual work done here
+    s/\(\*<\*\)//sg;
+    s/\(\*>\*\)//sg;
+
+    $result = $_;
+
+    if ($text ne $result) {
+        print STDERR "fixing $file\n";
+#        if (! -f "$file~~") {
+#            rename $file, "$file~~" || die $!;
+#        }
+        open (FILE, "> Demo/$file") || die $!;
+        print FILE $result;
+        close FILE || die $!;
+    }
+}
+
+
+foreach $file (@ARGV) {
+  eval { &doit($file); };
+  if ($@) { print STDERR "*** doit $file: ", $@, "\n"; }
+}