added introductory examples;
authorwenzelm
Mon, 09 Feb 2009 21:09:24 +0100
changeset 29721 df4e53d18ebc
parent 29720 020861892625
child 29722 a06894e9b6e3
added introductory examples;
doc-src/IsarRef/Thy/Framework.thy
--- a/doc-src/IsarRef/Thy/Framework.thy	Mon Feb 09 21:08:59 2009 +0100
+++ b/doc-src/IsarRef/Thy/Framework.thy	Mon Feb 09 21:09:24 2009 +0100
@@ -51,6 +51,182 @@
   set-theory) is being used most of the time; Isabelle/ZF
   \cite{isabelle-ZF} is less extensively developed, although it would
   probably fit better for classical mathematics.
+
+  \medskip In order to illustrate typical natural deduction reasoning
+  in Isar, we shall refer to the background theory and library of
+  Isabelle/HOL.  This includes common notions of predicate logic,
+  naive set-theory etc.\ using fairly standard mathematical notation.
+  From the perspective of generic natural deduction there is nothing
+  special about the logical connectives of HOL (@{text "\<and>"}, @{text
+  "\<or>"}, @{text "\<forall>"}, @{text "\<exists>"}, etc.), only the resulting reasoning
+  principles are relevant to the user.  There are similar rules
+  available for set-theory operators (@{text "\<inter>"}, @{text "\<union>"}, @{text
+  "\<Inter>"}, @{text "\<Union>"}, etc.), or any other theory developed in the
+  library (lattice theory, topology etc.).
+
+  Subsequently we briefly review fragments of Isar proof texts
+  corresponding directly to such general natural deduction schemes.
+  The examples shall refer to set-theory, to minimize the danger of
+  understanding connectives of predicate logic as something special.
+
+  \medskip The following deduction performs @{text "\<inter>"}-introduction,
+  working forwards from assumptions towards the conclusion.  We give
+  both the Isar text, and depict the primitive rule involved, as
+  determined by unification of the problem against rules from the
+  context.
+*}
+
+text_raw {*\medskip\begin{minipage}{0.6\textwidth}*}
+
+(*<*)
+lemma True
+proof
+(*>*)
+    assume "x \<in> A" and "x \<in> B"
+    then have "x \<in> A \<inter> B" ..
+(*<*)
+qed
+(*>*)
+
+text_raw {*\end{minipage}\begin{minipage}{0.4\textwidth}*}
+
+text {*
+  \infer{@{prop "x \<in> A \<inter> B"}}{@{prop "x \<in> A"} & @{prop "x \<in> B"}}
+*}
+
+text_raw {*\end{minipage}*}
+
+text {*
+  \medskip\noindent Note that @{command "assume"} augments the
+  context, @{command "then"} indicates that the current facts shall be
+  used in the next step, and @{command "have"} states a local claim.
+  The two dots ``@{command ".."}'' above refer to a complete proof of
+  the claim, using the indicated facts and a canonical rule from the
+  context.  We could have been more explicit here by spelling out the
+  final proof step via the @{command "by"} command:
+*}
+
+(*<*)
+lemma True
+proof
+(*>*)
+    assume "x \<in> A" and "x \<in> B"
+    then have "x \<in> A \<inter> B" by (rule IntI)
+(*<*)
+qed
+(*>*)
+
+text {*
+  \noindent The format of the @{text "\<inter>"}-introduction rule represents
+  the most basic inference, which proceeds from given premises to a
+  conclusion, without any additional context involved.
+
+  \medskip The next example performs backwards introduction on @{term
+  "\<Inter>\<A>"}, the intersection of all sets within a given set.  This
+  requires a nested proof of set membership within a local context of
+  an arbitrary-but-fixed member of the collection:
+*}
+
+text_raw {*\medskip\begin{minipage}{0.6\textwidth}*}
+
+(*<*)
+lemma True
+proof
+(*>*)
+    have "x \<in> \<Inter>\<A>"
+    proof
+      fix A
+      assume "A \<in> \<A>"
+      show "x \<in> A" sorry
+    qed
+(*<*)
+qed
+(*>*)
+
+text_raw {*\end{minipage}\begin{minipage}{0.4\textwidth}*}
+
+text {*
+  \infer{@{prop "x \<in> \<Inter>\<A>"}}{\infer*{@{prop "x \<in> A"}}{@{text "[A][A \<in> \<A>]"}}}
+*}
+
+text_raw {*\end{minipage}*}
+
+text {*
+  \medskip\noindent This Isar reasoning pattern again refers to the
+  primitive rule depicted above.  The system determines it in the
+  ``@{command "proof"}'' step, which could have been spelt out more
+  explicitly as ``@{command "proof"}~@{text "("}@{method rule}~@{fact
+  InterI}@{text ")"}''.  Note that this rule involves both a local
+  parameter @{term "A"} and an assumption @{prop "A \<in> \<A>"} in the
+  nested reasoning.  This kind of compound rule typically demands a
+  genuine sub-proof in Isar, working backwards rather than forwards as
+  seen before.  In the proof body we encounter the @{command
+  "fix"}-@{command "assume"}-@{command "show"} skeleton of nested
+  sub-proofs that is typical for Isar.  The final @{command "show"} is
+  like @{command "have"} followed by an additional refinement of the
+  enclosing claim, using the rule derived from the proof body.  The
+  @{command "sorry"} command stands for a hole in the proof -- it may
+  be understood as an excuse for not providing a proper proof yet.
+
+  \medskip The next example involves @{term "\<Union>\<A>"}, which can be
+  characterized as the set of all @{term "x"} such that @{prop "\<exists>A. x
+  \<in> A \<and> A \<in> \<A>"}.  The elimination rule for @{prop "x \<in> \<Union>\<A>"} does
+  not mention @{text "\<exists>"} and @{text "\<and>"} at all, but admits to obtain
+  directly a local @{term "A"} such that @{prop "x \<in> A"} and @{prop "A
+  \<in> \<A>"} hold.  This corresponds to the following Isar proof and
+  inference rule, respectively:
+*}
+
+text_raw {*\medskip\begin{minipage}{0.6\textwidth}*}
+
+(*<*)
+lemma True
+proof
+(*>*)
+    assume "x \<in> \<Union>\<A>"
+    then have C
+    proof
+      fix A
+      assume "x \<in> A" and "A \<in> \<A>"
+      show C sorry
+    qed
+(*<*)
+qed
+(*>*)
+
+text_raw {*\end{minipage}\begin{minipage}{0.4\textwidth}*}
+
+text {*
+  \infer{@{prop "C"}}{@{prop "x \<in> \<Union>\<A>"} & \infer*{@{prop "C"}~}{@{text "[A][x \<in> A, A \<in> \<A>]"}}}
+*}
+
+text_raw {*\end{minipage}*}
+
+text {*
+  \medskip\noindent Although the Isar proof follows the natural
+  deduction rule closely, the text reads not as natural as
+  anticipated.  There is a double occurrence of an arbitrary
+  conclusion @{prop "C"}, which represents the final result, but is
+  irrelevant for now.  This issue arises for any elimination rule
+  involving local parameters.  Isar provides the derived language
+  element @{command "obtain"}, which is able to perform the same
+  elimination proof more conveniently:
+*}
+
+(*<*)
+lemma True
+proof
+(*>*)
+    assume "x \<in> \<Union>\<A>"
+    then obtain A where "x \<in> A" and "A \<in> \<A>" ..
+(*<*)
+qed
+(*>*)
+
+text {*
+  \noindent Here we avoid to mention the final conclusion @{prop "C"}
+  and return to plain forward reasoning.  The rule involved in the
+  ``@{command ".."}'' proof is the same as before.
 *}
 
 end