doc-src/TutorialI/Rules/rules.tex
author paulson
Tue, 05 Dec 2000 18:56:18 +0100
changeset 10596 77951eaeb5b0
parent 10578 b32513971481
child 10792 78dfc5904eea
permissions -rw-r--r--
tidying
Ignore whitespace changes - Everywhere: Within whitespace: At end of lines:
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     1
\chapter{The Rules of the Game}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     2
\label{chap:rules}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     3
 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     4
Until now, we have proved everything using only induction and simplification.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     5
Substantial proofs require more elaborate forms of inference.  This chapter
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     6
outlines the concepts and techniques that underlie reasoning in Isabelle. The examples
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     7
are mainly drawn from predicate logic.  The first examples in this
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     8
chapter will consist of detailed, low-level proof steps.  Later, we shall
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
     9
see how to automate such reasoning using the methods \isa{blast},
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    10
\isa{auto} and others. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    11
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    12
\section{Natural deduction}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    13
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    14
In Isabelle, proofs are constructed using inference rules. The 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    15
most familiar inference rule is probably \emph{modus ponens}: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    16
\[ \infer{Q}{P\imp Q & P} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    17
This rule says that from $P\imp Q$ and $P$  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    18
we may infer~$Q$.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    19
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    20
%Early logical formalisms had this  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    21
%rule and at most one or two others, along with many complicated 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    22
%axioms. Any desired theorem could be obtained by applying \emph{modus 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    23
%ponens} or other rules to the axioms, but proofs were 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    24
%hard to find. For example, a standard inference system has 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    25
%these two axioms (amongst others): 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    26
%\begin{gather*}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    27
%  P\imp(Q\imp P) \tag{K}\\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    28
%  (P\imp(Q\imp R))\imp ((P\imp Q)\imp(P\imp R))  \tag{S}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    29
%\end{gather*}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    30
%Try proving the trivial fact $P\imp P$ using these axioms and \emph{modus
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    31
%ponens}!
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    32
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    33
\textbf{Natural deduction} is an attempt to formalize logic in a way 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    34
that mirrors human reasoning patterns. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    35
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    36
%Instead of having a few 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    37
%inference rules and many axioms, it has many inference rules 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    38
%and few axioms. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    39
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    40
For each logical symbol (say, $\conj$), there 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    41
are two kinds of rules: \textbf{introduction} and \textbf{elimination} rules. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    42
The introduction rules allow us to infer this symbol (say, to 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    43
infer conjunctions). The elimination rules allow us to deduce 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    44
consequences from this symbol. Ideally each rule should mention 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    45
one symbol only.  For predicate logic this can be 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    46
done, but when users define their own concepts they typically 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    47
have to refer to other symbols as well.  It is best not be dogmatic.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    48
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    49
Natural deduction generally deserves its name.  It is easy to use.  Each
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    50
proof step consists of identifying the outermost symbol of a formula and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    51
applying the corresponding rule.  It creates new subgoals in
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    52
an obvious way from parts of the chosen formula.  Expanding the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    53
definitions of constants can blow up the goal enormously.  Deriving natural
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    54
deduction rules for such constants lets us reason in terms of their key
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    55
properties, which might otherwise be obscured by the technicalities of its
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    56
definition.  Natural deduction rules also lend themselves to automation.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    57
Isabelle's
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    58
\textbf{classical  reasoner} accepts any suitable  collection of natural deduction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    59
rules and uses them to search for proofs automatically.  Isabelle is designed around
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    60
natural deduction and many of its  tools use the terminology of introduction and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    61
elimination rules.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    62
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    63
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    64
\section{Introduction rules}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    65
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    66
An \textbf{introduction} rule tells us when we can infer a formula 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    67
containing a specific logical symbol. For example, the conjunction 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    68
introduction rule says that if we have $P$ and if we have $Q$ then 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    69
we have $P\conj Q$. In a mathematics text, it is typically shown 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    70
like this:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    71
\[  \infer{P\conj Q}{P & Q} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    72
The rule introduces the conjunction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    73
symbol~($\conj$) in its conclusion.  Of course, in Isabelle proofs we
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    74
mainly  reason backwards.  When we apply this rule, the subgoal already has
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    75
the form of a conjunction; the proof step makes this conjunction symbol
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    76
disappear. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    77
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    78
In Isabelle notation, the rule looks like this:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    79
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    80
\isasymlbrakk?P;\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P\ \isasymand\ ?Q\rulename{conjI}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    81
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    82
Carefully examine the syntax.  The premises appear to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    83
left of the arrow and the conclusion to the right.  The premises (if 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    84
more than one) are grouped using the fat brackets.  The question marks
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    85
indicate \textbf{schematic variables} (also called \textbf{unknowns}): they may
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    86
be replaced by arbitrary formulas.  If we use the rule backwards, Isabelle
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    87
tries to unify the current subgoal with the conclusion of the rule, which
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    88
has the form \isa{?P\ \isasymand\ ?Q}.  (Unification is discussed below,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    89
\S\ref{sec:unification}.)  If successful,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    90
it yields new subgoals given by the formulas assigned to 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    91
\isa{?P} and \isa{?Q}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    92
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    93
The following trivial proof illustrates this point. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    94
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
    95
\isacommand{lemma}\ conj_rule:\ "\isasymlbrakk P;\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    96
Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ \isasymand\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
    97
(Q\ \isasymand\ P)"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    98
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ conjI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
    99
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   100
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ conjI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   101
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   102
\isacommand{apply}\ assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   103
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   104
At the start, Isabelle presents 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   105
us with the assumptions (\isa{P} and~\isa{Q}) and with the goal to be proved,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   106
\isa{P\ \isasymand\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   107
(Q\ \isasymand\ P)}.  We are working backwards, so when we
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   108
apply conjunction introduction, the rule removes the outermost occurrence
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   109
of the \isa{\isasymand} symbol.  To apply a  rule to a subgoal, we apply
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   110
the proof method \isa{rule} --- here with {\isa{conjI}}, the  conjunction
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   111
introduction rule. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   112
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   113
%\isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ \isasymand\ Q\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   114
%\isasymand\ P\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   115
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   116
\ 2.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymand\ P
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   117
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   118
Isabelle leaves two new subgoals: the two halves of the original conjunction. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   119
The first is simply \isa{P}, which is trivial, since \isa{P} is among 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   120
the assumptions.  We can apply the \isa{assumption} 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   121
method, which proves a subgoal by finding a matching assumption.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   122
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   123
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   124
Q\ \isasymand\ P
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   125
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   126
We are left with the subgoal of proving  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   127
\isa{Q\ \isasymand\ P} from the assumptions \isa{P} and~\isa{Q}.  We apply
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   128
\isa{rule conjI} again. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   129
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   130
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   131
\ 2.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   132
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   133
We are left with two new subgoals, \isa{Q} and~\isa{P}, each of which can be proved
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   134
using the \isa{assumption} method. 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   135
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   136
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   137
\section{Elimination rules}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   138
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   139
\textbf{Elimination} rules work in the opposite direction from introduction 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   140
rules. In the case of conjunction, there are two such rules. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   141
From $P\conj Q$ we infer $P$. also, from $P\conj Q$  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   142
we infer $Q$:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   143
\[ \infer{P}{P\conj Q} \qquad \infer{Q}{P\conj Q}  \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   144
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   145
Now consider disjunction. There are two introduction rules, which resemble inverted forms of the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   146
conjunction elimination rules:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   147
\[ \infer{P\disj Q}{P} \qquad \infer{P\disj Q}{Q}  \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   148
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   149
What is the disjunction elimination rule?  The situation is rather different from 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   150
conjunction.  From $P\disj Q$ we cannot conclude  that $P$ is true and we
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   151
cannot conclude that $Q$ is true; there are no direct
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   152
elimination rules of the sort that we have seen for conjunction.  Instead,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   153
there is an elimination  rule that works indirectly.  If we are trying  to prove
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   154
something else, say $R$, and we know that $P\disj Q$ holds,  then we have to consider
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   155
two cases.  We can assume that $P$ is true  and prove $R$ and then assume that $Q$ is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   156
true and prove $R$ a second  time.  Here we see a fundamental concept used in natural
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   157
deduction:  that of the \textbf{assumptions}. We have to prove $R$ twice, under
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   158
different assumptions.  The assumptions are local to these subproofs and are visible 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   159
nowhere else. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   160
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   161
In a logic text, the disjunction elimination rule might be shown 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   162
like this:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   163
\[ \infer{R}{P\disj Q & \infer*{R}{[P]} & \infer*{R}{[Q]}} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   164
The assumptions $[P]$ and $[Q]$ are bracketed 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   165
to emphasize that they are local to their subproofs.  In Isabelle 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   166
notation, the already-familiar \isa\isasymLongrightarrow syntax serves the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   167
same  purpose:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   168
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   169
\isasymlbrakk?P\ \isasymor\ ?Q;\ ?P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?R;\ ?Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?R\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?R\rulename{disjE}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   170
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   171
When we use this sort of elimination rule backwards, it produces 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   172
a case split.  (We have this before, in proofs by induction.)  The following  proof
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   173
illustrates the use of disjunction elimination.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   174
\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
   175
\isacommand{lemma}\ disj_swap:\ "P\ \isasymor\ Q\ 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   176
\isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymor\ P"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   177
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ disjE)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   178
\ \isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ disjI2)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   179
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   180
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ disjI1)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   181
\isacommand{apply}\ assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   182
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   183
We assume \isa{P\ \isasymor\ Q} and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   184
must prove \isa{Q\ \isasymor\ P}\@.  Our first step uses the disjunction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   185
elimination rule, \isa{disjE}.  The method {\isa{erule}}  applies an
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   186
elimination rule to the assumptions, searching for one that matches the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   187
rule's first premise.  Deleting that assumption, it
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   188
return the subgoals for the remaining premises.  Most of the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   189
time, this is  the best way to use elimination rules; only rarely is there
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   190
any  point in keeping the assumption.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   191
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   192
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   193
%P\ \isasymor\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymor\ P\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   194
\ 1.\ P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymor\ P\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   195
\ 2.\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymor\ P
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   196
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   197
Here it leaves us with two subgoals.  The first assumes \isa{P} and the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   198
second assumes \isa{Q}.  Tackling the first subgoal, we need to 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   199
show \isa{Q\ \isasymor\ P}\@.  The second introduction rule (\isa{disjI2})
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   200
can reduce this  to \isa{P}, which matches the assumption. So, we apply the
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   201
\isa{rule}  method with \isa{disjI2} \ldots
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   202
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   203
\ 1.\ P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   204
\ 2.\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymor\ P
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   205
\end{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   206
\ldots and finish off with the \isa{assumption} 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   207
method.  We are left with the other subgoal, which 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   208
assumes \isa{Q}.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   209
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   210
\ 1.\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymor\ P
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   211
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   212
Its proof is similar, using the introduction 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   213
rule \isa{disjI1}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   214
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   215
The result of this proof is a new inference rule \isa{disj_swap}, which is neither 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   216
an introduction nor an elimination rule, but which might 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   217
be useful.  We can use it to replace any goal of the form $Q\disj P$
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   218
by a one of the form $P\disj Q$.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   219
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   220
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   221
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   222
\section{Destruction rules: some examples}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   223
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   224
Now let us examine the analogous proof for conjunction. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   225
\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
   226
\isacommand{lemma}\ conj_swap:\ "P\ \isasymand\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymand\ P"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   227
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ conjI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   228
\ \isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ conjunct2)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   229
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   230
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ conjunct1)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   231
\isacommand{apply}\ assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   232
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   233
Recall that the conjunction elimination rules --- whose Isabelle names are 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   234
\isa{conjunct1} and \isa{conjunct2} --- simply return the first or second half
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   235
of a conjunction.  Rules of this sort (where the conclusion is a subformula of a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   236
premise) are called \textbf{destruction} rules, by analogy with the destructor
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
   237
functions of functional programming.%
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   238
\footnote{This Isabelle terminology has no counterpart in standard logic texts, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   239
although the distinction between the two forms of elimination rule is well known. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   240
Girard \cite[page 74]{girard89}, for example, writes ``The elimination rules are very
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   241
bad.  What is catastrophic about them is the parasitic presence of a formula [$R$]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   242
which has no structural link with the formula which is eliminated.''}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   243
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   244
The first proof step applies conjunction introduction, leaving 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   245
two subgoals: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   246
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   247
%P\ \isasymand\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymand\ P\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   248
\ 1.\ P\ \isasymand\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   249
\ 2.\ P\ \isasymand\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   250
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   251
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   252
To invoke the elimination rule, we apply a new method, \isa{drule}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   253
Think of the \isa{d} as standing for \textbf{destruction} (or \textbf{direct}, if
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   254
you prefer).   Applying the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   255
second conjunction rule using \isa{drule} replaces the assumption 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   256
\isa{P\ \isasymand\ Q} by \isa{Q}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   257
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   258
\ 1.\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   259
\ 2.\ P\ \isasymand\ Q\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   260
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   261
The resulting subgoal can be proved by applying \isa{assumption}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   262
The other subgoal is similarly proved, using the \isa{conjunct1} rule and the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   263
\isa{assumption} method.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   264
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   265
Choosing among the methods \isa{rule}, \isa{erule} and \isa{drule} is up to 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   266
you.  Isabelle does not attempt to work out whether a rule 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   267
is an introduction rule or an elimination rule.  The 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   268
method determines how the rule will be interpreted. Many rules 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   269
can be used in more than one way.  For example, \isa{disj_swap} can 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   270
be applied to assumptions as well as to goals; it replaces any
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   271
assumption of the form
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   272
$P\disj Q$ by a one of the form $Q\disj P$.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   273
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   274
Destruction rules are simpler in form than indirect rules such as \isa{disjE},
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   275
but they can be inconvenient.  Each of the conjunction rules discards half 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   276
of the formula, when usually we want to take both parts of the conjunction as new
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   277
assumptions.  The easiest way to do so is by using an 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   278
alternative conjunction elimination rule that resembles \isa{disjE}.  It is seldom,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   279
if ever, seen in logic books.  In Isabelle syntax it looks like this: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   280
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   281
\isasymlbrakk?P\ \isasymand\ ?Q;\ \isasymlbrakk?P;\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?R\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?R\rulename{conjE}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   282
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   283
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   284
\begin{exercise}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   285
Use the rule {\isa{conjE}} to shorten the proof above. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   286
\end{exercise}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   287
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   288
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   289
\section{Implication}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   290
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   291
At the start of this chapter, we saw the rule \textit{modus ponens}.  It is, in fact,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   292
a destruction rule. The matching introduction rule looks like this 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   293
in Isabelle: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   294
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   295
(?P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?Q)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   296
\isasymlongrightarrow\ ?Q\rulename{impI}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   297
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   298
And this is \textit{modus ponens}:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   299
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   300
\isasymlbrakk?P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ ?Q;\ ?P\isasymrbrakk\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   301
\isasymLongrightarrow\ ?Q
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   302
\rulename{mp}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   303
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   304
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   305
Here is a proof using the rules for implication.  This 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   306
lemma performs a sort of uncurrying, replacing the two antecedents 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   307
of a nested implication by a conjunction. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   308
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   309
\isacommand{lemma}\ imp_uncurry:\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
   310
"P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ (Q\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   311
\isasymlongrightarrow\ R)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   312
\isasymand\ Q\ \isasymlongrightarrow\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   313
R"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   314
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ impI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   315
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ conjE)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   316
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ mp)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   317
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   318
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ mp)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   319
\ \ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   320
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   321
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   322
First, we state the lemma and apply implication introduction (\isa{rule impI}), 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   323
which moves the conjunction to the assumptions. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   324
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   325
%P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ R\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   326
%\isasymand\ Q\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ R\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   327
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ R;\ P\ \isasymand\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ R
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   328
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   329
Next, we apply conjunction elimination (\isa{erule conjE}), which splits this
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   330
conjunction into two  parts. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   331
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   332
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ R;\ P;\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   333
Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ R
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   334
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   335
Now, we work on the assumption \isa{P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ (Q\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   336
\isasymlongrightarrow\ R)}, where the parentheses have been inserted for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   337
clarity.  The nested implication requires two applications of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   338
\textit{modus ponens}: \isa{drule mp}.  The first use  yields the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   339
implication \isa{Q\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   340
\isasymlongrightarrow\ R}, but first we must prove the extra subgoal 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   341
\isa{P}, which we do by assumption. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   342
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   343
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   344
\ 2.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q;\ Q\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ R\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ R
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   345
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   346
Repeating these steps for \isa{Q\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   347
\isasymlongrightarrow\ R} yields the conclusion we seek, namely~\isa{R}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   348
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   349
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q;\ Q\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ R\isasymrbrakk\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   350
\isasymLongrightarrow\ R
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   351
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   352
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   353
The symbols \isa{\isasymLongrightarrow} and \isa{\isasymlongrightarrow}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   354
both stand for implication, but they differ in many respects.  Isabelle
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   355
uses \isa{\isasymLongrightarrow} to express inference rules; the symbol is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   356
built-in and Isabelle's inference mechanisms treat it specially.  On the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   357
other hand, \isa{\isasymlongrightarrow} is just one of the many connectives
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   358
available in higher-order logic.  We reason about it using inference rules
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   359
such as \isa{impI} and \isa{mp}, just as we reason about the other
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   360
connectives.  You will have to use \isa{\isasymlongrightarrow} in any
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   361
context that requires a formula of higher-order logic.  Use
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   362
\isa{\isasymLongrightarrow} to separate a theorem's preconditions from its
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   363
conclusion.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   364
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   365
When using induction, often the desired theorem results in an induction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   366
hypothesis that is too weak.  In such cases you may have to invent a more
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   367
complicated induction formula, typically involving
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   368
\isa{\isasymlongrightarrow} and \isa{\isasymforall}.  From this lemma you
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   369
derive the desired theorem , typically involving
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   370
\isa{\isasymLongrightarrow}.  We shall see an example below,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   371
\S\ref{sec:proving-euclid}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   372
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   373
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   374
\section{Unification and substitution}\label{sec:unification}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   375
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   376
As we have seen, Isabelle rules involve variables that begin  with a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   377
question mark. These are called \textbf{schematic} variables  and act as
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   378
placeholders for terms. \textbf{Unification} refers to  the process of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   379
making two terms identical, possibly by replacing  their variables by
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   380
terms. The simplest case is when the two terms  are already the same. Next
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   381
simplest is when the variables in only one of the term
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   382
 are replaced; this is called \textbf{pattern-matching}.  The
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   383
\isa{rule} method typically  matches the rule's conclusion
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   384
against the current subgoal.  In the most complex case,  variables in both
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   385
terms are replaced; the \isa{rule} method can do this the goal
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   386
itself contains schematic variables.  Other occurrences of the variables in
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   387
the rule or proof state are updated at the same time.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   388
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   389
Schematic variables in goals are sometimes called \textbf{unknowns}.  They
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   390
are useful because they let us proceed with a proof even  when we do not
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   391
know what certain terms should be --- as when the goal is $\exists x.\,P$. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   392
They can be  filled in later, often automatically. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   393
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   394
 Unification is well known to Prolog programmers. Isabelle uses \textbf{higher-order} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   395
unification, which is unification in the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   396
typed $\lambda$-calculus.  The general case is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   397
undecidable, but for our purposes, the differences from ordinary
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   398
unification are straightforward.  It handles bound  variables
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   399
correctly, avoiding capture.  The two terms \isa{{\isasymlambda}x.\ ?P} and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   400
\isa{{\isasymlambda}x.\ t x}  are not unifiable; replacing \isa{?P} by
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   401
\isa{t x} is forbidden because the free occurrence of~\isa{x} would become
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   402
bound.  The two terms
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   403
\isa{{\isasymlambda}x.\ f(x,z)} and \isa{{\isasymlambda}y.\ f(y,z)} are
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   404
trivially unifiable because they differ only by a bound variable renaming.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   405
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   406
Higher-order unification sometimes must invent
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   407
$\lambda$-terms to replace function  variables,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   408
which can lead to a combinatorial explosion. However,  Isabelle proofs tend
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   409
to involve easy cases where there are few possibilities for the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   410
$\lambda$-term being constructed. In the easiest case, the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   411
function variable is applied only to bound variables, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   412
as when we try to unify \isa{{\isasymlambda}x\ y.\ f(?h x y)} and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   413
\isa{{\isasymlambda}x\ y.\ f(x+y+a)}.  The only solution is to replace
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   414
\isa{?h} by \isa{{\isasymlambda}x\ y.\ x+y+a}.  Such cases admit at most
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   415
one unifier, like ordinary unification.  A harder case is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   416
unifying \isa{?h a} with~\isa{a+b}; it admits two solutions for \isa{?h},
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   417
namely \isa{{\isasymlambda}x.~a+b} and \isa{{\isasymlambda}x.~x+b}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   418
Unifying \isa{?h a} with~\isa{a+a+b} admits four solutions; their number is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   419
exponential in the number of occurrences of~\isa{a} in the second term.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   420
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   421
Isabelle also uses function variables to express \textbf{substitution}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   422
A typical substitution rule allows us to replace one term by 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   423
another if we know that two terms are equal. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   424
\[ \infer{P[t/x]}{s=t & P[s/x]} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   425
The conclusion uses a notation for substitution: $P[t/x]$ is the result of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   426
replacing $x$ by~$t$ in~$P$.  The rule only substitutes in the positions
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   427
designated by~$x$, which gives it additional power. For example, it can
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   428
derive symmetry of equality from reflexivity.  Using $x=s$ for~$P$
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   429
replaces just the first $s$ in $s=s$ by~$t$.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   430
\[ \infer{t=s}{s=t & \infer{s=s}{}} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   431
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   432
The Isabelle version of the substitution rule looks like this: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   433
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   434
\isasymlbrakk?t\ =\ ?s;\ ?P\ ?s\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   435
?t
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   436
\rulename{ssubst}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   437
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   438
Crucially, \isa{?P} is a function 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   439
variable: it can be replaced by a $\lambda$-expression 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   440
involving one bound variable whose occurrences identify the places 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   441
in which $s$ will be replaced by~$t$.  The proof above requires
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   442
\isa{{\isasymlambda}x.~x=s}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   443
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   444
The \isa{simp} method replaces equals by equals, but using the substitution
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   445
rule gives us more control. Consider this proof: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   446
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   447
\isacommand{lemma}\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   448
"\isasymlbrakk \ x\ =\ f\ x;\ odd(f\ x)\ \isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   449
odd\ x"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   450
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ ssubst)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   451
\isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   452
\isacommand{done}\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   453
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   454
The simplifier might loop, replacing \isa{x} by \isa{f x} and then by
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   455
\isa{f(f x)} and so forth. (Actually, \isa{simp} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   456
sees the danger and re-orients this equality, but in more complicated cases
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   457
it can be fooled.) When we apply substitution,  Isabelle replaces every
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   458
\isa{x} in the subgoal by \isa{f x} just once: it cannot loop.  The
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   459
resulting subgoal is trivial by assumption. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   460
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   461
We are using the \isa{erule} method it in a novel way. Hitherto, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   462
the conclusion of the rule was just a variable such as~\isa{?R}, but it may
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   463
be any term. The conclusion is unified with the subgoal just as 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   464
it would be with the \isa{rule} method. At the same time \isa{erule} looks 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   465
for an assumption that matches the rule's first premise, as usual.  With
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   466
\isa{ssubst} the effect is to find, use and delete an equality 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   467
assumption.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   468
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   469
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   470
Higher-order unification can be tricky, as this example indicates: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   471
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   472
\isacommand{lemma}\ "\isasymlbrakk \ x\ =\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   473
f\ x;\ triple\ (f\ x)\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   474
(f\ x)\ x\ \isasymrbrakk\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   475
\isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ x\ x\ x"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   476
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ ssubst)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   477
\isacommand{back}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   478
\isacommand{back}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   479
\isacommand{back}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   480
\isacommand{back}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   481
\isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   482
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   483
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   484
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   485
By default, Isabelle tries to substitute for all the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   486
occurrences.  Applying \isa{erule\ ssubst} yields this subgoal:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   487
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   488
\ 1.\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   489
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   490
The substitution should have been done in the first two occurrences 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   491
of~\isa{x} only. Isabelle has gone too far. The \isa{back} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   492
method allows us to reject this possibility and get a new one: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   493
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   494
\ 1.\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ x\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   495
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   496
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   497
Now Isabelle has left the first occurrence of~\isa{x} alone. That is 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   498
promising but it is not the desired combination. So we use \isa{back} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   499
again:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   500
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   501
\ 1.\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ (f\ x)\ x\ (f\ x)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   502
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   503
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   504
This also is wrong, so we use \isa{back} again: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   505
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   506
\ 1.\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ x\ x\ (f\ x)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   507
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   508
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   509
And this one is wrong too. Looking carefully at the series 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   510
of alternatives, we see a binary countdown with reversed bits: 111,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   511
011, 101, 001.  Invoke \isa{back} again: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   512
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   513
\ 1.\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   514
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   515
At last, we have the right combination!  This goal follows by assumption.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   516
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   517
Never use {\isa{back}} in the final version of a proof. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   518
It should only be used for exploration. One way to get rid of {\isa{back}} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   519
to combine two methods in a single \textbf{apply} command. Isabelle 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   520
applies the first method and then the second. If the second method 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   521
fails then Isabelle automatically backtracks. This process continues until 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   522
the first method produces an output that the second method can 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   523
use. We get a one-line proof of our example: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   524
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   525
\isacommand{lemma}\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   526
"\isasymlbrakk \ x\ =\ f\ x;\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   527
\isasymrbrakk\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   528
\isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ x\ x\ x"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   529
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ ssubst,\ assumption)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   530
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   531
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   532
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   533
The most general way to get rid of the {\isa{back}} command is 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   534
to instantiate variables in the rule.  The method \isa{rule_tac} is
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   535
similar to \isa{rule}, but it
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   536
makes some of the rule's variables  denote specified terms.  
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   537
Also available are {\isa{drule_tac}}  and \isa{erule_tac}.  Here we need
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   538
\isa{erule_tac} since above we used
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   539
\isa{erule}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   540
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   541
\isacommand{lemma}\ "\isasymlbrakk \ x\ =\ f\ x;\ triple\ (f\ x)\ (f\ x)\ x\ \isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ triple\ x\ x\ x"\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   542
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule_tac\ P="{\isasymlambda}u.\ triple\ u\ u\ x"\
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   543
\isakeyword{in}\ ssubst)\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   544
\isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   545
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   546
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   547
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   548
To specify a desired substitution 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   549
requires instantiating the variable \isa{?P} with a $\lambda$-expression. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   550
The bound variable occurrences in \isa{{\isasymlambda}u.\ P\ u\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   551
u\ x} indicate that the first two arguments have to be substituted, leaving
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   552
the third unchanged.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   553
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   554
An alternative to \isa{rule_tac} is to use \isa{rule} with the
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   555
\isa{of} directive, described in \S\ref{sec:forward} below.   An
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   556
advantage  of \isa{rule_tac} is that the instantiations may refer to 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   557
variables bound in the current subgoal.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   558
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   559
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   560
\section{Negation}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   561
 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   562
Negation causes surprising complexity in proofs.  Its natural 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   563
deduction rules are straightforward, but additional rules seem 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   564
necessary in order to handle negated assumptions gracefully. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   565
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   566
Negation introduction deduces $\neg P$ if assuming $P$ leads to a 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   567
contradiction. Negation elimination deduces any formula in the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   568
presence of $\neg P$ together with~$P$: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   569
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   570
(?P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ False)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ \isasymnot\ ?P%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   571
\rulename{notI}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   572
\isasymlbrakk{\isasymnot}\ ?P;\ ?P\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?R%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   573
\rulename{notE}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   574
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   575
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   576
Classical logic allows us to assume $\neg P$ 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   577
when attempting to prove~$P$: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   578
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   579
(\isasymnot\ ?P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   580
\rulename{classical}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   581
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   582
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   583
Three further rules are variations on the theme of contrapositive. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   584
They differ in the placement of the negation symbols: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   585
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   586
\isasymlbrakk?Q;\ \isasymnot\ ?P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ \isasymnot\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   587
\rulename{contrapos_pp}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   588
\isasymlbrakk{\isasymnot}\ ?Q;\ \isasymnot\ ?P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   589
\rulename{contrapos_np}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   590
\isasymlbrakk{\isasymnot}\ ?Q;\ ?P\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ \isasymnot\ ?P%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   591
\rulename{contrapos_nn}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   592
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   593
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   594
These rules are typically applied using the {\isa{erule}} method, where 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   595
their effect is to form a contrapositive from an 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   596
assumption and the goal's conclusion.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   597
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   598
The most important of these is \isa{contrapos_np}.  It is useful
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   599
for applying introduction rules to negated assumptions.  For instance, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   600
the assumption $\neg(P\imp Q)$ is equivalent to the conclusion $P\imp Q$ and we 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   601
might want to use conjunction introduction on it. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   602
Before we can do so, we must move that assumption so that it 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   603
becomes the conclusion. The following proof demonstrates this 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   604
technique: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   605
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   606
\isacommand{lemma}\ "\isasymlbrakk{\isasymnot}(P{\isasymlongrightarrow}Q);\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   607
\isasymnot(R{\isasymlongrightarrow}Q)\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   608
R"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   609
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule_tac\ Q="R{\isasymlongrightarrow}Q"\ \isakeyword{in}\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   610
contrapos_np)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   611
\isacommand{apply}\ intro\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   612
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ notE,\ assumption)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   613
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   614
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   615
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   616
There are two negated assumptions and we need to exchange the conclusion with the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   617
second one.  The method \isa{erule contrapos_np} would select the first assumption,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   618
which we do not want.  So we specify the desired assumption explicitly, using
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   619
\isa{erule_tac}.  This is the resulting subgoal: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   620
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   621
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymnot}\ (P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q);\ \isasymnot\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   622
R\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ R\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   623
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   624
The former conclusion, namely \isa{R}, now appears negated among the assumptions,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   625
while the negated formula \isa{R\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q} becomes the new
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   626
conclusion.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   627
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   628
We can now apply introduction rules.  We use the {\isa{intro}} method, which
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   629
repeatedly  applies built-in introduction rules.  Here its effect is equivalent
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   630
to \isa{rule impI}.
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   631
\begin{isabelle}
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   632
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymnot}\ (P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q);\ \isasymnot\ R;\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   633
R\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   634
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   635
We can see a contradiction in the form of assumptions \isa{\isasymnot\ R}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   636
and~\isa{R}, which suggests using negation elimination.  If applied on its own,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   637
however, it will select the first negated assumption, which is useless.   Instead,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   638
we combine the rule with  the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   639
\isa{assumption} method:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   640
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   641
\ \ \ \ \ (erule\ notE,\ assumption)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   642
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   643
Now when Isabelle selects the first assumption, it tries to prove \isa{P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   644
\isasymlongrightarrow\ Q} and fails; it then backtracks, finds the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   645
assumption~\isa{\isasymnot\ R} and finally proves \isa{R} by assumption.  That
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   646
concludes the proof.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   647
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   648
\medskip
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   649
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   650
Here is another example. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   651
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   652
\isacommand{lemma}\ "(P\ \isasymor\ Q)\ \isasymand\ R\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   653
\isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ \isasymor\ Q\ \isasymand\ R"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   654
\isacommand{apply}\ intro%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   655
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   656
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   657
\isacommand{apply}\ (elim\ conjE\ disjE)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   658
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   659
\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   660
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ contrapos_np,\ rule\ conjI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   661
\ \ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   662
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   663
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   664
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   665
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   666
The first proof step applies the {\isa{intro}} method, which repeatedly 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   667
uses built-in introduction rules.  Here it creates the negative assumption \isa{\isasymnot\ (Q\ \isasymand\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   668
R)}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   669
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   670
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk(P\ \isasymor\ Q)\ \isasymand\ R;\ \isasymnot\ (Q\ \isasymand\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   671
R)\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   672
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   673
It comes from \isa{disjCI},  a disjunction introduction rule that is more
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   674
powerful than the separate rules  \isa{disjI1} and  \isa{disjI2}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   675
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   676
Next we apply the {\isa{elim}} method, which repeatedly applies 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   677
elimination rules; here, the elimination rules given 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   678
in the command.  One of the subgoals is trivial, leaving us with one other:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   679
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   680
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymnot}\ (Q\ \isasymand\ R);\ R;\ Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   681
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   682
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   683
Now we must move the formula \isa{Q\ \isasymand\ R} to be the conclusion.  The
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   684
combination 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   685
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   686
\ \ \ \ \ (erule\ contrapos_np,\ rule\ conjI)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   687
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   688
is robust: the \isa{conjI} forces the \isa{erule} to select a
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
   689
conjunction.  The two subgoals are the ones we would expect from applying
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   690
conjunction introduction to
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   691
\isa{Q\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   692
\isasymand\ R}:  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   693
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   694
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk R;\ Q;\ \isasymnot\ P\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   695
Q\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   696
\ 2.\ \isasymlbrakk R;\ Q;\ \isasymnot\ P\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ R%
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   697
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   698
The rest of the proof is trivial.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   699
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   700
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   701
\section{The universal quantifier}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   702
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   703
Quantifiers require formalizing syntactic substitution and the notion of \textbf{arbitrary
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   704
value}.  Consider the universal quantifier.  In a logic book, its
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   705
introduction  rule looks like this: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   706
\[ \infer{\forall x.\,P}{P} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   707
Typically, a proviso written in English says that $x$ must not
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   708
occur in the assumptions.  This proviso guarantees that $x$ can be regarded as
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   709
arbitrary, since it has not been assumed to satisfy any special conditions. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   710
Isabelle's  underlying formalism, called the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   711
\textbf{meta-logic}, eliminates the  need for English.  It provides its own universal
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   712
quantifier (\isasymAnd) to express the notion of an arbitrary value.  We have
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   713
already seen  another symbol of the meta-logic, namely
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   714
\isa\isasymLongrightarrow, which expresses  inference rules and the treatment of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   715
assumptions. The only other  symbol in the meta-logic is \isa\isasymequiv, which
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   716
can be used to define constants.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   717
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   718
Returning to the universal quantifier, we find that having a similar quantifier
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   719
as part of the meta-logic makes the introduction rule trivial to express:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   720
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   721
(\isasymAnd x.\ ?P\ x)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymforall}x.\ ?P\ x\rulename{allI}
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   722
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   723
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   724
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   725
The following trivial proof demonstrates how the universal introduction 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   726
rule works. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   727
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   728
\isacommand{lemma}\ "{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ x"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   729
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ allI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   730
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ impI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   731
\isacommand{apply}\ assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   732
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   733
The first step invokes the rule by applying the method \isa{rule allI}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   734
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   735
%{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ x\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   736
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x.\ P\ x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ x
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   737
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   738
Note  that the resulting proof state has a bound variable,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   739
namely~\bigisa{x}.  The rule has replaced the universal quantifier of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   740
higher-order  logic by Isabelle's meta-level quantifier.  Our goal is to
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   741
prove
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   742
\isa{P\ x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ x} for arbitrary~\isa{x}; it is 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   743
an implication, so we apply the corresponding introduction rule (\isa{impI}). 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   744
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   745
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x.\ P\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ x
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   746
\end{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   747
The \isa{assumption} method proves this last subgoal. 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   748
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   749
\medskip
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   750
Now consider universal elimination. In a logic text, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   751
the rule looks like this: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   752
\[ \infer{P[t/x]}{\forall x.\,P} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   753
The conclusion is $P$ with $t$ substituted for the variable~$x$.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   754
Isabelle expresses substitution using a function variable: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   755
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   756
{\isasymforall}x.\ ?P\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P\ ?x\rulename{spec}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   757
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   758
This destruction rule takes a 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   759
universally quantified formula and removes the quantifier, replacing 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   760
the bound variable \bigisa{x} by the schematic variable \bigisa{?x}.  Recall that a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   761
schematic variable starts with a question mark and acts as a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   762
placeholder: it can be replaced by any term. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   763
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   764
To see how this works, let us derive a rule about reducing 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   765
the scope of a universal quantifier.  In mathematical notation we write
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   766
\[ \infer{P\imp\forall x.\,Q}{\forall x.\,P\imp Q} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   767
with the proviso `$x$ not free in~$P$.'  Isabelle's treatment of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   768
substitution makes the proviso unnecessary.  The conclusion is expressed as
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   769
\isa{P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   770
\isasymlongrightarrow\ ({\isasymforall}x.\ Q\ x)}. No substitution for the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   771
variable \isa{P} can introduce a dependence upon~\isa{x}: that would be a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   772
bound variable capture.  Here is the isabelle proof in full:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   773
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   774
\isacommand{lemma}\ "({\isasymforall}x.\ P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   775
\isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ x)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
   776
\isasymlongrightarrow\ ({\isasymforall}x.\ Q\ x)"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   777
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ impI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   778
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ allI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   779
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ spec)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   780
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ mp)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   781
\ \ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   782
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   783
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   784
First we apply implies introduction (\isa{rule impI}), 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   785
which moves the \isa{P} from the conclusion to the assumptions. Then 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   786
we apply universal introduction (\isa{rule allI}).  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   787
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   788
%{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   789
%\isasymlongrightarrow\ ({\isasymforall}x.\ Q\ x)\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   790
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ x;\ P\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ x
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   791
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   792
As before, it replaces the HOL 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   793
quantifier by a meta-level quantifier, producing a subgoal that 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   794
binds the variable~\bigisa{x}.  The leading bound variables
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   795
(here \isa{x}) and the assumptions (here \isa{{\isasymforall}x.\ P\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   796
\isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ x} and \isa{P}) form the \textbf{context} for the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   797
conclusion, here \isa{Q\ x}.  At each proof step, the subgoals inherit the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   798
previous context, though some context elements may be added or deleted. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   799
Applying \isa{erule} deletes an assumption, while many natural deduction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   800
rules add bound variables or assumptions.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   801
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   802
Now, to reason from the universally quantified 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   803
assumption, we apply the elimination rule using the {\isa{drule}} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   804
method.  This rule is called \isa{spec} because it specializes a universal formula
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   805
to a particular term.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   806
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   807
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ P\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ Q\ (?x2\
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   808
x)\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ x
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   809
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   810
Observe how the context has changed.  The quantified formula is gone,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   811
replaced by a new assumption derived from its body.  Informally, we have
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   812
removed the quantifier.  The quantified variable
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   813
has been replaced by the curious term 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   814
\bigisa{?x2~x}; it acts as a placeholder that may be replaced 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   815
by any term that can be built up from~\bigisa{x}.  (Formally, \bigisa{?x2} is an
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   816
unknown of function type, applied to the argument~\bigisa{x}.)  This new assumption is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   817
an implication, so we can  use \emph{modus ponens} on it. As before, it requires
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   818
proving the  antecedent (in this case \isa{P}) and leaves us with the consequent. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   819
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   820
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x.\ \isasymlbrakk P;\ Q\ (?x2\ x)\isasymrbrakk\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   821
\isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ x
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   822
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   823
The consequent is \isa{Q} applied to that placeholder.  It may be replaced by any
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   824
term built from~\bigisa{x}, and here 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   825
it should simply be~\bigisa{x}.  The \isa{assumption} method will do this.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   826
The assumption need not be identical to the conclusion, provided the two formulas are
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   827
unifiable.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   828
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   829
\medskip
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   830
Note that \isa{drule spec} removes the universal quantifier and --- as
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   831
usual with elimination rules --- discards the original formula.  Sometimes, a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   832
universal formula has to be kept so that it can be used again.  Then we use a new
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   833
method: \isa{frule}.  It acts like \isa{drule} but copies rather than replaces
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   834
the selected assumption.  The \isa{f} is for `forward.'
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   835
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   836
In this example, we intuitively see that to go from \isa{P\ a} to \isa{P(f\ (f\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   837
a))} requires two uses of the quantified assumption, one for each
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   838
additional~\isa{f}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   839
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   840
\isacommand{lemma}\ "\isasymlbrakk{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ (f\ x);
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   841
\ P\ a\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P(f\ (f\ a))"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   842
\isacommand{apply}\ (frule\ spec)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   843
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ mp,\ assumption)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   844
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ spec)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   845
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ mp,\ assumption,\ assumption)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   846
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   847
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   848
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   849
Applying \isa{frule\ spec} leaves this subgoal:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   850
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   851
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ (f\ x);\ P\ a;\ P\ ?x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ (f\ ?x)\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ (f\ (f\ a))
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   852
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   853
It is just what  \isa{drule} would have left except that the quantified
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   854
assumption is still present.  The next step is to apply \isa{mp} to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   855
implication and the assumption \isa{P\ a}, which leaves this subgoal:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   856
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   857
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ P\ (f\ x);\ P\ a;\ P\ (f\ a)\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ (f\ (f\ a))
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   858
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   859
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   860
We have created the assumption \isa{P(f\ a)}, which is progress.  To finish the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   861
proof, we apply \isa{spec} one last time, using \isa{drule}.  One final trick: if
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   862
we then apply
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   863
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   864
\ \ \ \ \ (drule\ mp,\ assumption)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   865
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   866
it will add a second copy of \isa{P(f\ a)} instead of the desired \isa{P(f\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   867
(f\ a))}.  Bundling both \isa{assumption} calls with \isa{drule mp} causes
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   868
Isabelle to backtrack and find the correct one.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   869
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   870
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   871
\section{The existential quantifier}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   872
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   873
The concepts just presented also apply to the existential quantifier,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   874
whose introduction rule looks like this in Isabelle: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   875
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   876
?P\ ?x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymexists}x.\ ?P\ x\rulename{exI}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   877
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   878
If we can exhibit some $x$ such that $P(x)$ is true, then $\exists x.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   879
P(x)$ is also true. It is essentially a dual of the universal elimination rule, and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   880
logic texts present it using the same notation for substitution.  The existential
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   881
elimination rule looks like this
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   882
in a logic text: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   883
\[ \infer{R}{\exists x.\,P & \infer*{R}{[P]}} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   884
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   885
It looks like this in Isabelle: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   886
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   887
\isasymlbrakk{\isasymexists}x.\ ?P\ x;\ \isasymAnd x.\ ?P\ x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?Q\rulename{exE}
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   888
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   889
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   890
Given an existentially quantified theorem and some
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   891
formula $Q$ to prove, it creates a new assumption by removing the quantifier.  As with
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   892
the universal introduction  rule, the textbook version imposes a proviso on the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   893
quantified variable, which Isabelle expresses using its meta-logic.  Note that it is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   894
enough to have a universal quantifier in the meta-logic; we do not need an existential
10399
e37e123738f7 minor modifications for new Springer style
paulson
parents: 10341
diff changeset
   895
quantifier to be built in as well.\REMARK{EX example needed?}
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   896
 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   897
Isabelle/HOL also provides Hilbert's
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   898
$\epsilon$-operator.  The term $\epsilon x. P(x)$ denotes some $x$ such that $P(x)$ is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   899
true, provided such a value exists.  Using this operator, we can express an
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   900
existential destruction rule:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   901
\[ \infer{P[(\epsilon x. P) / \, x]}{\exists x.\,P} \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   902
This rule is seldom used, for it can cause exponential blow-up.  The
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   903
main use of $\epsilon x. P(x)$ is in definitions when $P(x)$ characterizes $x$
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   904
uniquely.  For instance, we can define the cardinality of a finite set~$A$ to be that
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
   905
$n$ such that $A$ is in one-to-one correspondence with $\{1,\ldots,n\}$.  We can then
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   906
prove that the cardinality of the empty set is zero (since $n=0$ satisfies the
10399
e37e123738f7 minor modifications for new Springer style
paulson
parents: 10341
diff changeset
   907
description) and proceed to prove other facts.\REMARK{SOME theorems
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   908
and example}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   909
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   910
\begin{exercise}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   911
Prove the lemma
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   912
\[ \exists x.\, P\conj Q(x)\Imp P\conj(\exists x.\, Q(x)). \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   913
\emph{Hint}: the proof is similar 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   914
to the one just above for the universal quantifier. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   915
\end{exercise}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   916
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   917
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   918
\section{Some proofs that fail}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   919
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   920
Most of the examples in this tutorial involve proving theorems.  But not every 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   921
conjecture is true, and it can be instructive to see how  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   922
proofs fail. Here we attempt to prove a distributive law involving 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   923
the existential quantifier and conjunction. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   924
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   925
\isacommand{lemma}\ "({\isasymexists}x.\ P\ x)\ \isasymand\ ({\isasymexists}x.\ Q\ x)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymexists}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymand\ Q\ x"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   926
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ conjE)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   927
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ exE)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   928
\isacommand{apply}\ (erule\ exE)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   929
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ exI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   930
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ conjI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   931
\ \isacommand{apply}\ assumption\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   932
\isacommand{oops}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   933
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   934
The first steps are  routine.  We apply conjunction elimination (\isa{erule
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   935
conjE}) to split the assumption  in two, leaving two existentially quantified
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   936
assumptions.  Applying existential elimination  (\isa{erule exE}) removes one of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   937
the quantifiers. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   938
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   939
%({\isasymexists}x.\ P\ x)\ \isasymand\ ({\isasymexists}x.\ Q\ x)\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   940
%\isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymexists}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymand\ Q\ x\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   941
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymexists}x.\ Q\ x;\ P\ x\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymexists}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymand\ Q\ x
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   942
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   943
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   944
When we remove the other quantifier, we get a different bound 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   945
variable in the subgoal.  (The name \isa{xa} is generated automatically.)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   946
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   947
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x\ xa.\ \isasymlbrakk P\ x;\ Q\ xa\isasymrbrakk\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   948
\isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymexists}x.\ P\ x\ \isasymand\ Q\ x
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   949
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   950
The proviso of the existential elimination rule has forced the variables to
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   951
differ: we can hardly expect two arbitrary values to be equal!  There is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   952
no way to prove this subgoal.  Removing the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   953
conclusion's existential quantifier yields two
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   954
identical placeholders, which can become  any term involving the variables \bigisa{x}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   955
and~\bigisa{xa}.  We need one to become \bigisa{x}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   956
and the other to become~\bigisa{xa}, but Isabelle requires all instances of a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   957
placeholder to be identical. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   958
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   959
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x\ xa.\ \isasymlbrakk P\ x;\ Q\ xa\isasymrbrakk\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   960
\isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ (?x3\ x\ xa)\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   961
\ 2.\ \isasymAnd x\ xa.\ \isasymlbrakk P\ x;\ Q\ xa\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ (?x3\ x\ xa)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   962
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   963
We can prove either subgoal 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   964
using the \isa{assumption} method.  If we prove the first one, the placeholder
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   965
changes  into~\bigisa{x}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   966
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
   967
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x\ xa.\ \isasymlbrakk P\ x;\ Q\ xa\isasymrbrakk\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   968
\isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ x
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   969
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   970
We are left with a subgoal that cannot be proved, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   971
because there is no way to prove that \bigisa{x}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   972
equals~\bigisa{xa}.  Applying the \isa{assumption} method results in an
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   973
error message:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   974
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   975
*** empty result sequence -- proof command failed
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   976
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   977
We can tell Isabelle to abandon a failed proof using the \isacommand{oops} command.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   978
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   979
\medskip 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   980
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   981
Here is another abortive proof, illustrating the interaction between 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   982
bound variables and unknowns.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   983
If $R$ is a reflexive relation, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   984
is there an $x$ such that $R\,x\,y$ holds for all $y$?  Let us see what happens when
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   985
we attempt to prove it. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   986
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   987
\isacommand{lemma}\ "{\isasymforall}z.\ R\ z\ z\ \isasymLongrightarrow\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   988
{\isasymexists}x.\ {\isasymforall}y.\ R\ x\ y"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   989
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ exI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   990
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ allI)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   991
\isacommand{apply}\ (drule\ spec)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   992
\isacommand{oops}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   993
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   994
First, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   995
we remove the existential quantifier. The new proof state has 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   996
an unknown, namely~\bigisa{?x}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   997
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   998
%{\isasymforall}z.\ R\ z\ z\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymexists}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
   999
%{\isasymforall}y.\ R\ x\ y\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1000
\ 1.\ {\isasymforall}z.\ R\ z\ z\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ {\isasymforall}y.\ R\ ?x\ y
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1001
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1002
Next, we remove the universal quantifier 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1003
from the conclusion, putting the bound variable~\isa{y} into the subgoal. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1004
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1005
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd y.\ {\isasymforall}z.\ R\ z\ z\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ R\ ?x\ y
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1006
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1007
Finally, we try to apply our reflexivity assumption.  We obtain a 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1008
new assumption whose identical placeholders may be replaced by 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1009
any term involving~\bigisa{y}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1010
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1011
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd y.\ R\ (?z2\ y)\ (?z2\ y)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ R\ ?x\ y
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1012
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1013
This subgoal can only be proved by putting \bigisa{y} for all the placeholders,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1014
making the assumption and conclusion become \isa{R\ y\ y}. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1015
But Isabelle refuses to substitute \bigisa{y}, a bound variable, for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1016
\bigisa{?x}; that would be a bound variable capture.  The proof fails.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1017
Note that Isabelle can replace \bigisa{?z2~y} by \bigisa{y}; this involves
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1018
instantiating
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1019
\bigisa{?z2} to the identity function.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1020
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1021
This example is typical of how Isabelle enforces sound quantifier reasoning. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1022
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1023
10578
b32513971481 fixed formatting in section heading
paulson
parents: 10546
diff changeset
  1024
\section{Proving theorems using the {\tt\slshape blast} method}
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1025
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1026
It is hard to prove substantial theorems using the methods 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1027
described above. A proof may be dozens or hundreds of steps long.  You 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1028
may need to search among different ways of proving certain 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1029
subgoals. Often a choice that proves one subgoal renders another 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1030
impossible to prove.  There are further complications that we have not
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1031
discussed, concerning negation and disjunction.  Isabelle's
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1032
\textbf{classical reasoner} is a family of tools that perform such
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1033
proofs automatically.  The most important of these is the 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1034
\isa{blast} method. 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1035
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1036
In this section, we shall first see how to use the classical 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1037
reasoner in its default mode and then how to insert additional 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1038
rules, enabling it to work in new problem domains. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1039
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1040
 We begin with examples from pure predicate logic. The following 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1041
example is known as Andrew's challenge. Peter Andrews designed 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1042
it to be hard to prove by automatic means.%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1043
\footnote{Pelletier~\cite{pelletier86} describes it and many other
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1044
problems for automatic theorem provers.}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1045
The nested biconditionals cause an exponential explosion: the formal
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1046
proof is  enormous.  However, the \isa{blast} method proves it in
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1047
a fraction  of a second. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1048
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1049
\isacommand{lemma}\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1050
"(({\isasymexists}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1051
{\isasymforall}y.\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1052
p(x){=}p(y))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1053
=\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1054
(({\isasymexists}x.\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1055
q(x))=({\isasymforall}y.\
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1056
p(y))))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1057
\ \ =\ \ \ \ \isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1058
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1059
(({\isasymexists}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1060
{\isasymforall}y.\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1061
q(x){=}q(y))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1062
=\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1063
(({\isasymexists}x.\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1064
p(x))=({\isasymforall}y.\
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1065
q(y))))"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1066
\isacommand{apply}\ blast\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1067
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1068
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1069
The next example is a logic problem composed by Lewis Carroll. 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1070
The \isa{blast} method finds it trivial. Moreover, it turns out 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1071
that not all of the assumptions are necessary. We can easily 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1072
experiment with variations of this formula and see which ones 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1073
can be proved. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1074
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1075
\isacommand{lemma}\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1076
"({\isasymforall}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1077
honest(x)\ \isasymand\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1078
industrious(x)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1079
healthy(x))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1080
\isasymand\ \ \isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1081
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \isasymnot\ ({\isasymexists}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1082
grocer(x)\ \isasymand\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1083
healthy(x))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1084
\isasymand\ \isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1085
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ ({\isasymforall}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1086
industrious(x)\ \isasymand\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1087
grocer(x)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1088
honest(x))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1089
\isasymand\ \isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1090
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ ({\isasymforall}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1091
cyclist(x)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1092
industrious(x))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1093
\isasymand\ \isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1094
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ ({\isasymforall}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1095
{\isasymnot}healthy(x)\ \isasymand\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1096
cyclist(x)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1097
{\isasymnot}honest(x))\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1098
\ \isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1099
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \isasymlongrightarrow\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1100
({\isasymforall}x.\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1101
grocer(x)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1102
{\isasymnot}cyclist(x))"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1103
\isacommand{apply}\ blast\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1104
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1105
\end{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1106
The \isa{blast} method is also effective for set theory, which is
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1107
described in the next chapter.  This formula below may look horrible, but
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1108
the \isa{blast} method proves it easily. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1109
\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1110
\isacommand{lemma}\ "({\isasymUnion}i{\isasymin}I.\ A(i))\ \isasyminter\ ({\isasymUnion}j{\isasymin}J.\ B(j))\ =\isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1111
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ ({\isasymUnion}i{\isasymin}I.\ {\isasymUnion}j{\isasymin}J.\ A(i)\ \isasyminter\ B(j))"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1112
\isacommand{apply}\ blast\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1113
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1114
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1115
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1116
Few subgoals are couched purely in predicate logic and set theory.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1117
We can extend the scope of the classical reasoner by giving it new rules. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1118
Extending it effectively requires understanding the notions of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1119
introduction, elimination and destruction rules.  Moreover, there is a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1120
distinction between  safe and unsafe rules. A \textbf{safe} rule is one
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1121
that can be applied  backwards without losing information; an
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1122
\textbf{unsafe} rule loses  information, perhaps transforming the subgoal
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1123
into one that cannot be proved.  The safe/unsafe
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1124
distinction affects the proof search: if a proof attempt fails, the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1125
classical reasoner backtracks to the most recent unsafe rule application
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1126
and makes another choice. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1127
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1128
An important special case avoids all these complications.  A logical 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1129
equivalence, which in higher-order logic is an equality between 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1130
formulas, can be given to the classical 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1131
reasoner and simplifier by using the attribute \isa{iff}.  You 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1132
should do so if the right hand side of the equivalence is  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1133
simpler than the left-hand side.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1134
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1135
For example, here is a simple fact about list concatenation. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1136
The result of appending two lists is empty if and only if both 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1137
of the lists are themselves empty. Obviously, applying this equivalence 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1138
will result in a simpler goal. When stating this lemma, we include 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1139
the \isa{iff} attribute. Once we have proved the lemma, Isabelle 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1140
will make it known to the classical reasoner (and to the simplifier). 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1141
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1142
\isacommand{lemma}\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1143
[iff]:\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1144
"(xs{\isacharat}ys\ =\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1145
\isacharbrackleft{]})\ =\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1146
(xs=[]\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1147
\isacharampersand\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1148
ys=[])"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1149
\isacommand{apply}\ (induct_tac\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1150
xs)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1151
\isacommand{apply}\ (simp_all)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1152
\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1153
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1154
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1155
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1156
This fact about multiplication is also appropriate for 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1157
the \isa{iff} attribute:\REMARK{the ?s are ugly here but we need
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1158
them again when talking about \isa{of}; we need a consistent style}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1159
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1160
(\mbox{?m}\ *\ \mbox{?n}\ =\ 0)\ =\ (\mbox{?m}\ =\ 0\ \isasymor\ \mbox{?n}\ =\ 0)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1161
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1162
A product is zero if and only if one of the factors is zero.  The
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1163
reasoning  involves a logical \textsc{or}.  Proving new rules for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1164
disjunctive reasoning  is hard, but translating to an actual disjunction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1165
works:  the classical reasoner handles disjunction properly.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1166
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1167
In more detail, this is how the \isa{iff} attribute works.  It converts
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1168
the equivalence $P=Q$ to a pair of rules: the introduction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1169
rule $Q\Imp P$ and the destruction rule $P\Imp Q$.  It gives both to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1170
classical reasoner as safe rules, ensuring that all occurrences of $P$ in
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1171
a subgoal are replaced by~$Q$.  The simplifier performs the same
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1172
replacement, since \isa{iff} gives $P=Q$ to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1173
simplifier.  But classical reasoning is different from
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1174
simplification.  Simplification is deterministic: it applies rewrite rules
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1175
repeatedly, as long as possible, in order to \emph{transform} a goal.  Classical
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1176
reasoning uses search and backtracking in order to \emph{prove} a goal. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1177
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1178
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1179
\section{Proving the correctness of Euclid's algorithm}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1180
\label{sec:proving-euclid}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1181
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1182
A brief development will illustrate advanced use of  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1183
\isa{blast}.  In \S\ref{sec:recdef-simplification}, we declared the
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1184
recursive function \isa{gcd}:
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1185
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1186
\isacommand{consts}\ gcd\ ::\ "nat*nat\ \isasymRightarrow\ nat"\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1187
\
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1188
\
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1189
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1190
\isacommand{recdef}\ gcd\ "measure\ ((\isasymlambda(m,n).n)\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1191
::nat*nat\ \isasymRightarrow\ nat)"\isanewline
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1192
\ \ \ \ "gcd\ (m,n)\ =\ (if\ n=0\ then\ m\ else\ gcd(n,\ m\ mod\ n))"
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1193
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1194
Let us prove that it computes the greatest common
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1195
divisor of its two arguments.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1196
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1197
%The declaration yields a recursion
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1198
%equation  for \isa{gcd}.  Simplifying with this equation can 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1199
%cause looping, expanding to ever-larger expressions of if-then-else 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1200
%and \isa{gcd} calls.  To prevent this, we prove separate simplification rules
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1201
%for $n=0$\ldots
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1202
%\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1203
%\isacommand{lemma}\ gcd_0\ [simp]:\ "gcd(m,0)\ =\ m"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1204
%\isacommand{apply}\ (simp)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1205
%\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1206
%\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1207
%\ldots{} and for $n>0$:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1208
%\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1209
%\isacommand{lemma}\ gcd_non_0:\ "0{\isacharless}n\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ gcd(m,n)\ =\ gcd\ (n,\ m\ mod\ n)"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1210
%\isacommand{apply}\ (simp)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1211
%\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1212
%\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1213
%This second rule is similar to the original equation but
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1214
%does not loop because it is conditional.  It can be applied only
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1215
%when the second argument is known to be non-zero.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1216
%Armed with our two new simplification rules, we now delete the 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1217
%original \isa{gcd} recursion equation. 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1218
%\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1219
%\isacommand{declare}\ gcd.simps\ [simp\ del]
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1220
%\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1221
%
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1222
%Now we can prove  some interesting facts about the \isa{gcd} function,
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1223
%for exampe, that it computes a common divisor of its arguments.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1224
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1225
The theorem is expressed in terms of the familiar
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1226
\textbf{divides} relation from number theory: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1227
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1228
?m\ dvd\ ?n\ \isasymequiv\ {\isasymexists}k.\ ?n\ =\ ?m\ *\ k
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1229
\rulename{dvd_def}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1230
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1231
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1232
A simple induction proves the theorem.  Here \isa{gcd.induct} refers to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1233
induction rule returned by \isa{recdef}.  The proof relies on the simplification
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1234
rules proved in \S\ref{sec:recdef-simplification}, since rewriting by the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1235
definition of \isa{gcd} can cause looping.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1236
\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1237
\isacommand{lemma}\ gcd_dvd_both:\ "(gcd(m,n)\ dvd\ m)\ \isasymand\ (gcd(m,n)\ dvd\ n)"\isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1238
\isacommand{apply}\ (induct_tac\ m\ n\ rule:\ gcd.induct)\isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1239
\isacommand{apply}\ (case_tac\ "n=0")\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1240
\isacommand{apply}\ (simp_all)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1241
\isacommand{apply}\ (blast\ dest:\ dvd_mod_imp_dvd)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1242
\isacommand{done}%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1243
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1244
Notice that the induction formula 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1245
is a conjunction.  This is necessary: in the inductive step, each 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1246
half of the conjunction establishes the other. The first three proof steps 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1247
are applying induction, performing a case analysis on \isa{n}, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1248
and simplifying.  Let us pass over these quickly and consider
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1249
the use of \isa{blast}.  We have reached the following 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1250
subgoal: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1251
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1252
%gcd\ (m,\ n)\ dvd\ m\ \isasymand\ gcd\ (m,\ n)\ dvd\ n\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1253
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd m\ n.\ \isasymlbrakk0\ \isacharless\ n;\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1254
 \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ gcd\ (n,\ m\ mod\ n)\ dvd\ n\ \isasymand\ gcd\ (n,\ m\ mod\ n)\ dvd\ (m\ mod\ n)\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
10546
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1255
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ gcd\ (n,\ m\ mod\ n)\ dvd\ m
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1256
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1257
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1258
One of the assumptions, the induction hypothesis, is a conjunction. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1259
The two divides relationships it asserts are enough to prove 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1260
the conclusion, for we have the following theorem at our disposal: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1261
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1262
\isasymlbrakk?k\ dvd\ (?m\ mod\ ?n){;}\ ?k\ dvd\ ?n\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?k\ dvd\ ?m%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1263
\rulename{dvd_mod_imp_dvd}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1264
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1265
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1266
This theorem can be applied in various ways.  As an introduction rule, it
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1267
would cause backward chaining from  the conclusion (namely
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1268
\isa{?k\ dvd\ ?m}) to the two premises, which 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1269
also involve the divides relation. This process does not look promising
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1270
and could easily loop.  More sensible is  to apply the rule in the forward
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1271
direction; each step would eliminate  the \isa{mod} symbol from an
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1272
assumption, so the process must terminate.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1273
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1274
So the final proof step applies the \isa{blast} method.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1275
Attaching the {\isa{dest}} attribute to \isa{dvd_mod_imp_dvd} tells \isa{blast}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1276
to use it as destruction rule: in the forward direction.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1277
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1278
\medskip
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1279
We have proved a conjunction.  Now, let us give names to each of the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1280
two halves:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1281
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1282
\isacommand{lemmas}\ gcd_dvd1\ [iff]\ =\ gcd_dvd_both\ [THEN\ conjunct1]\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1283
\isacommand{lemmas}\ gcd_dvd2\ [iff]\ =\ gcd_dvd_both\ [THEN\ conjunct2]%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1284
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1285
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1286
Several things are happening here. The keyword \isacommand{lemmas}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1287
tells Isabelle to transform a theorem in some way and to
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1288
give a name to the resulting theorem.  Attributes can be given,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1289
here \isa{iff}, which supplies the new theorems to the classical reasoner
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1290
and the simplifier.  The directive \isa{THEN}, which will be explained
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1291
below, supplies the lemma 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1292
\isa{gcd_dvd_both} to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1293
destruction rule \isa{conjunct1} in order to extract the first part.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1294
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1295
\ \ \ \ \ gcd\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1296
(?m1,\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1297
?n1)\ dvd\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1298
?m1%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1299
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1300
The variable names \isa{?m1} and \isa{?n1} arise because
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1301
Isabelle renames schematic variables to prevent 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1302
clashes.  The second \isacommand{lemmas} declaration yields
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1303
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1304
\ \ \ \ \ gcd\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1305
(?m1,\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1306
?n1)\ dvd\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1307
?n1%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1308
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1309
Later, we shall explore this type of forward reasoning in detail. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1310
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1311
To complete the verification of the \isa{gcd} function, we must 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1312
prove that it returns the greatest of all the common divisors 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1313
of its arguments.  The proof is by induction and simplification.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1314
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1315
\isacommand{lemma}\ gcd_greatest\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1316
[rule_format]:\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1317
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ "(k\ dvd\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1318
m)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ (k\ dvd\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1319
n)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ k\ dvd\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1320
gcd(m,n)"\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1321
\isacommand{apply}\ (induct_tac\ m\ n\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1322
rule:\ gcd.induct)\isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1323
\isacommand{apply}\ (case_tac\ "n=0")\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1324
\isacommand{apply}\ (simp_all\ add:\ gcd_non_0\ dvd_mod)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1325
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1326
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1327
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1328
Note that the theorem has been expressed using HOL implication,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1329
\isa{\isasymlongrightarrow}, because the induction affects the two
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1330
preconditions.  The directive \isa{rule_format} tells Isabelle to replace
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1331
each \isa{\isasymlongrightarrow} by \isa{\isasymLongrightarrow} before
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1332
storing the theorem we have proved.  This directive also removes outer
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1333
universal quantifiers, converting a theorem into the usual format for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1334
inference rules.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1335
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1336
The facts proved above can be summarized as a single logical 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1337
equivalence.  This step gives us a chance to see another application
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1338
of \isa{blast}, and it is worth doing for sound logical reasons.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1339
\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1340
\isacommand{theorem}\ gcd_greatest_iff\ [iff]:\isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1341
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ "k\ dvd\ gcd(m,n)\ =\ (k\ dvd\ m\ \isasymand\ k\ dvd\ n)"\isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1342
\isacommand{apply}\ (blast\ intro!:\ gcd_greatest\ intro:\ dvd_trans)\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1343
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1344
\end{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1345
This theorem concisely expresses the correctness of the \isa{gcd} 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1346
function. 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1347
We state it with the \isa{iff} attribute so that 
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1348
Isabelle can use it to remove some occurrences of \isa{gcd}. 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1349
The theorem has a one-line 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1350
proof using \isa{blast} supplied with four introduction 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1351
rules: note the {\isa{intro}} attribute. The exclamation mark 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1352
({\isa{intro}}{\isa{!}})\ signifies safe rules, which are 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1353
applied aggressively.  Rules given without the exclamation mark 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1354
are applied reluctantly and their uses can be undone if 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1355
the search backtracks.  Here the unsafe rule expresses transitivity  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1356
of the divides relation:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1357
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1358
\isasymlbrakk?m\ dvd\ ?n;\ ?n\ dvd\ ?p\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?m\ dvd\ ?p%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1359
\rulename{dvd_trans}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1360
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1361
Applying \isa{dvd_trans} as 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1362
an introduction rule entails a risk of looping, for it multiplies 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1363
occurrences of the divides symbol. However, this proof relies 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1364
on transitivity reasoning.  The rule {\isa{gcd\_greatest}} is safe to apply 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1365
aggressively because it yields simpler subgoals.  The proof implicitly
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1366
uses \isa{gcd_dvd1} and \isa{gcd_dvd2} as safe rules, because they were
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1367
declared using \isa{iff}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1368
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1369
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1370
\section{Other classical reasoning methods}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1371
 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1372
The \isa{blast} method is our main workhorse for proving theorems 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1373
automatically. Other components of the classical reasoner interact 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1374
with the simplifier. Still others perform classical reasoning 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1375
to a limited extent, giving the user fine control over the proof. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1376
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1377
Of the latter methods, the most useful is {\isa{clarify}}. It performs 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1378
all obvious reasoning steps without splitting the goal into multiple 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1379
parts. It does not apply rules that could render the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1380
goal unprovable (so-called unsafe rules). By performing the obvious 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1381
steps, {\isa{clarify}} lays bare the difficult parts of the problem, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1382
where human intervention is necessary. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1383
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1384
For example, the following conjecture is false:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1385
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1386
\isacommand{lemma}\ "({\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x)\ \isasymand\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1387
({\isasymexists}x.\ Q\ x)\ \isasymlongrightarrow\ ({\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1388
\isasymand\ Q\ x)"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1389
\isacommand{apply}\ clarify
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1390
\end{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1391
The \isa{blast} method would simply fail, but {\isa{clarify}} presents 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1392
a subgoal that helps us see why we cannot continue the proof. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1393
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1394
\ 1.\ \isasymAnd x\ xa.\ \isasymlbrakk{\isasymforall}x.\ P\ x;\ Q\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1395
xa\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ x\ \isasymand\ Q\ x
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1396
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1397
The proof must fail because the assumption \isa{Q\ xa} and conclusion \isa{Q\ x}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1398
refer to distinct bound variables.  To reach this state, \isa{clarify} applied
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1399
the introduction rules for \isa{\isasymlongrightarrow} and \isa{\isasymforall}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1400
and the elimination rule for ~\isa{\isasymand}.  It did not apply the introduction
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1401
rule for  \isa{\isasymand} because of its policy never to split goals.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1402
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1403
Also available is {\isa{clarsimp}}, a method that interleaves {\isa{clarify}}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1404
and {\isa{simp}}.  Also there is \isa{safe}, which like \isa{clarify} performs
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1405
obvious steps and even applies those that split goals.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1406
10546
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1407
The \isa{force} method applies the classical reasoner and simplifier 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1408
to one goal. 
10546
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1409
\REMARK{example needed of \isa{force}?}
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1410
Unless it can prove the goal, it fails. Contrast 
10546
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1411
that with the \isa{auto} method, which also combines classical reasoning 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1412
with simplification. The latter's purpose is to prove all the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1413
easy subgoals and parts of subgoals. Unfortunately, it can produce 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1414
large numbers of new subgoals; also, since it proves some subgoals 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1415
and splits others, it obscures the structure of the proof tree. 
10546
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1416
The \isa{force} method does not have these drawbacks. Another 
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1417
difference: \isa{force} tries harder than {\isa{auto}} to prove 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1418
its goal, so it can take much longer to terminate.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1419
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1420
Older components of the classical reasoner have largely been 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1421
superseded by \isa{blast}, but they still have niche applications. 
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1422
Most important among these are \isa{fast} and \isa{best}. While \isa{blast} 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1423
searches for proofs using a built-in first-order reasoner, these 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1424
earlier methods search for proofs using standard Isabelle inference. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1425
That makes them slower but enables them to work correctly in the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1426
presence of the more unusual features of Isabelle rules, such 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1427
as type classes and function unknowns. For example, the introduction rule
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1428
for Hilbert's epsilon-operator has the following form: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1429
\begin{isabelle}
10546
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1430
?P\ ?x\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P\ (SOME\ x.\ ?P x)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1431
\rulename{someI}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1432
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1433
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1434
The repeated occurrence of the variable \isa{?P} makes this rule tricky 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1435
to apply. Consider this contrived example: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1436
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1437
\isacommand{lemma}\ "\isasymlbrakk Q\ a;\ P\ a\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1438
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \,\isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ (SOME\ x.\ P\ x\ \isasymand\ Q\ x)\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1439
\isasymand\ Q\ (SOME\ x.\ P\ x\ \isasymand\ Q\ x)"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1440
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ someI)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1441
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1442
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1443
We can apply rule \isa{someI} explicitly.  It yields the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1444
following subgoal: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1445
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1446
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk Q\ a;\ P\ a\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ P\ ?x\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1447
\isasymand\ Q\ ?x%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1448
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1449
The proof from this point is trivial.  The question now arises, could we have
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1450
proved the theorem with a single command? Not using \isa{blast} method: it
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1451
cannot perform  the higher-order unification that is necessary here.  The
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1452
\isa{fast} method succeeds: 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1453
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1454
\isacommand{apply}\ (fast\ intro!:\ someI)
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1455
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1456
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1457
The \isa{best} method is similar to \isa{fast} but it uses a 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1458
best-first search instead of depth-first search. Accordingly, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1459
it is slower but is less susceptible to divergence. Transitivity 
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1460
rules usually cause \isa{fast} to loop where often \isa{best} 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1461
can manage.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1462
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1463
Here is a summary of the classical reasoning methods:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1464
\begin{itemize}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1465
\item \isa{blast} works automatically and is the fastest
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1466
\item \isa{clarify} and \isa{clarsimp} perform obvious steps without splitting the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1467
goal; \isa{safe} even splits goals
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1468
\item \isa{force} uses classical reasoning and simplification to prove a goal;
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1469
 \isa{auto} is similar but leaves what it cannot prove
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1470
\item \isa{fast} and \isa{best} are legacy methods that work well with rules involving
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1471
unusual features
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1472
\end{itemize}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1473
A table illustrates the relationships among four of these methods. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1474
\begin{center}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1475
\begin{tabular}{r|l|l|}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1476
           & no split   & split \\ \hline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1477
  no simp  & \isa{clarify}    & \isa{safe} \\ \hline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1478
     simp  & \isa{clarsimp}   & \isa{auto} \\ \hline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1479
\end{tabular}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1480
\end{center}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1481
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1482
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1483
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1484
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1485
\section{Forward proof}\label{sec:forward}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1486
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1487
Forward proof means deriving new facts from old ones.  It is  the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1488
most fundamental type of proof.  Backward proof, by working  from goals to
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1489
subgoals, can help us find a difficult proof.  But it is
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1490
not always the best way of presenting the proof so found.  Forward
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1491
proof is particularly good for reasoning from the general
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1492
to the specific.  For example, consider the following distributive law for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1493
the 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1494
\isa{gcd} function:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1495
\[ k\times\gcd(m,n) = \gcd(k\times m,k\times n)\]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1496
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1497
Putting $m=1$ we get (since $\gcd(1,n)=1$ and $k\times1=k$) 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1498
\[ k = \gcd(k,k\times n)\]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1499
We have derived a new fact about \isa{gcd}; if re-oriented, it might be
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1500
useful for simplification.  After re-orienting it and putting $n=1$, we
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1501
derive another useful law: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1502
\[ \gcd(k,k)=k \]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1503
Substituting values for variables --- instantiation --- is a forward step. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1504
Re-orientation works by applying the symmetry of equality to 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1505
an equation, so it too is a forward step.  
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1506
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1507
Now let us reproduce our examples in Isabelle.  Here is the distributive
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1508
law:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1509
\begin{isabelle}%
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1510
?k\ *\ gcd\ (?m,\ ?n)\ =\ gcd\ (?k\ *\ ?m,\ ?k\ *\ ?n)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1511
\rulename{gcd_mult_distrib2}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1512
\end{isabelle}%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1513
The first step is to replace \isa{?m} by~1 in this law.  We refer to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1514
variables not by name but by their position in the theorem, from left to
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1515
right.  In this case, the variables  are \isa{?k}, \isa{?m} and~\isa{?n}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1516
So, the expression
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1517
\hbox{\texttt{[of k 1]}} replaces \isa{?k} by~\isa{k} and \isa{?m}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1518
by~\isa{1}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1519
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1520
\isacommand{lemmas}\ gcd_mult_0\ =\ gcd_mult_distrib2\ [of\ k\ 1]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1521
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1522
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1523
The command 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1524
\isa{thm gcd_mult_0}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1525
displays the resulting theorem:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1526
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1527
\ \ \ \ \ k\ *\ gcd\ (1,\ ?n)\ =\ gcd\ (k\ *\ 1,\ k\ *\ ?n)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1528
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1529
Something is odd: {\isa{k}} is an ordinary variable, while {\isa{?n}} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1530
is schematic.  We did not specify an instantiation 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1531
for {\isa{?n}}.  In its present form, the theorem does not allow 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1532
substitution for {\isa{k}}.  One solution is to avoid giving an instantiation for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1533
\isa{?k}: instead of a term we can put an underscore~(\isa{_}).  For example,
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1534
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1535
\ \ \ \ \ gcd_mult_distrib2\ [of\ _\ 1]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1536
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1537
replaces \isa{?m} by~\isa{1} but leaves \isa{?k} unchanged.  Anyway, let us put
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1538
the theorem \isa{gcd_mult_0} into a simplified form: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1539
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1540
\isacommand{lemmas}\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1541
gcd_mult_1\ =\ gcd_mult_0\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1542
[simplified]%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1543
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1544
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1545
Again, we display the resulting theorem:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1546
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1547
\ \ \ \ \ k\ =\ gcd\ (k,\ k\ *\ ?n)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1548
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1549
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1550
To re-orient the equation requires the symmetry rule:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1551
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1552
?s\ =\ ?t\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1553
\isasymLongrightarrow\ ?t\ =\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1554
?s%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1555
\rulename{sym}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1556
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1557
The following declaration gives our equation to \isa{sym}:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1558
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1559
\ \ \ \isacommand{lemmas}\ gcd_mult\ =\ gcd_mult_1\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1560
[THEN\ sym]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1561
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1562
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1563
Here is the result:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1564
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1565
\ \ \ \ \ gcd\ (k,\ k\ *\ ?n)\ =\ k%
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1566
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1567
\isa{THEN~sym} gives the current theorem to the rule \isa{sym} and returns the
10399
e37e123738f7 minor modifications for new Springer style
paulson
parents: 10341
diff changeset
  1568
resulting conclusion.\REMARK{figure necessary?}  The effect is to exchange the
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1569
two operands of the equality. Typically \isa{THEN} is used with destruction
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1570
rules.  Above we have used
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1571
\isa{THEN~conjunct1} to extract the first part of the theorem
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1572
\isa{gcd_dvd_both}.  Also useful is \isa{THEN~spec}, which removes the quantifier
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1573
from a theorem of the form $\forall x.\,P$, and \isa{THEN~mp}, which converts the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1574
implication $P\imp Q$ into the rule $\vcenter{\infer{Q}{P}}$.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1575
Similar to \isa{mp} are the following two rules, which extract 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1576
the two directions of reasoning about a boolean equivalence:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1577
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1578
\isasymlbrakk?Q\ =\ ?P;\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P%
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1579
\rulename{iffD1}%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1580
\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1581
\isasymlbrakk?P\ =\ ?Q;\ ?Q\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?P%
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1582
\rulename{iffD2}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1583
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1584
%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1585
Normally we would never name the intermediate theorems
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1586
such as \isa{gcd_mult_0} and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1587
\isa{gcd_mult_1} but would combine
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1588
the three forward steps: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1589
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1590
\isacommand{lemmas}\ gcd_mult\ =\ gcd_mult_distrib2\ [of\ k\ 1,\ simplified,\ THEN\ sym]%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1591
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1592
The directives, or attributes, are processed from left to right.  This
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1593
declaration of \isa{gcd_mult} is equivalent to the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1594
previous one.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1595
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1596
Such declarations can make the proof script hard to read: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1597
what is being proved?  More legible   
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1598
is to state the new lemma explicitly and to prove it using a single
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1599
\isa{rule} method whose operand is expressed using forward reasoning:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1600
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1601
\isacommand{lemma}\ gcd_mult\
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1602
[simp]:\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1603
"gcd(k,\ k*n)\ =\ k"\isanewline
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1604
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ gcd_mult_distrib2\ [of\ k\ 1,\ simplified,\ THEN\ sym])\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1605
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1606
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1607
Compared with the previous proof of \isa{gcd_mult}, this
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1608
version shows the reader what has been proved.  Also, it receives
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1609
the usual Isabelle treatment.  In particular, Isabelle generalizes over all
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1610
variables: the resulting theorem will have {\isa{?k}} instead of {\isa{k}}.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1611
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1612
At the start  of this section, we also saw a proof of $\gcd(k,k)=k$.  Here
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1613
is the Isabelle version: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1614
\begin{isabelle}
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1615
\isacommand{lemma}\ gcd_self\ [simp]:\ "gcd(k,k)\ =\ k"\isanewline
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1616
\isacommand{apply}\ (rule\ gcd_mult\ [of\ k\ 1,\ simplified])\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1617
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1618
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1619
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1620
Recall that \isa{of} generates an instance of a rule by specifying
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1621
values for its variables.  Analogous is \isa{OF}, which generates an
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1622
instance of a rule by specifying facts for its premises.  Let us try
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1623
it with this rule:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1624
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1625
\isasymlbrakk gcd(?k,?n){=}1;\ ?k\ dvd\ (?m * ?n)\isasymrbrakk\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1626
\isasymLongrightarrow\ ?k\ dvd\ ?m
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1627
\rulename{relprime_dvd_mult}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1628
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1629
First, we
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1630
prove an instance of its first premise:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1631
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1632
\isacommand{lemma}\ relprime_20_81:\ "gcd(\#20,\#81)\ =\ 1"\isanewline
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1633
\isacommand{apply}\ (simp\ add:\ gcd.simps)\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1634
\isacommand{done}%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1635
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1636
We have evaluated an application of the \isa{gcd} function by
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1637
simplification.  Expression evaluation  is not guaranteed to terminate, and
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1638
certainly is not  efficient; Isabelle performs arithmetic operations by 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1639
rewriting symbolic bit strings.  Here, however, the simplification takes
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1640
less than one second.  We can specify this new lemma to \isa{OF},
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1641
generating an instance of \isa{relprime_dvd_mult}.  The expression
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1642
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1643
\ \ \ \ \ relprime_dvd_mult [OF relprime_20_81]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1644
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1645
yields the theorem
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1646
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1647
\ \ \ \ \ \#20\ dvd\ (?m\ *\ \#81)\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ \#20\ dvd\ ?m%
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1648
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1649
%
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1650
\isa{OF} takes any number of operands.  Consider 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1651
the following facts about the divides relation: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1652
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1653
\isasymlbrakk?k\ dvd\ ?m;\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1654
?k\ dvd\ ?n\isasymrbrakk\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1655
\isasymLongrightarrow\ ?k\ dvd\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1656
(?m\ +\ ?n)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1657
\rulename{dvd_add}\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1658
?m\ dvd\ ?m%
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1659
\rulename{dvd_refl}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1660
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1661
Let us supply \isa{dvd_refl} for each of the premises of \isa{dvd_add}:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1662
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1663
\ \ \ \ \ dvd_add [OF dvd_refl dvd_refl]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1664
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1665
Here is the theorem that we have expressed: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1666
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1667
\ \ \ \ \ ?k\ dvd\ (?k\ +\ ?k)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1668
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1669
As with \isa{of}, we can use the \isa{_} symbol to leave some positions
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1670
unspecified:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1671
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1672
\ \ \ \ \ dvd_add [OF _ dvd_refl]
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1673
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1674
The result is 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1675
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1676
\ \ \ \ \ ?k\ dvd\ ?m\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ ?k\ dvd\ (?m\ +\ ?k)
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1677
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1678
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1679
You may have noticed that \isa{THEN} and \isa{OF} are based on 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1680
the same idea, namely to combine two rules.  They differ in the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1681
order of the combination and thus in their effect.  We use \isa{THEN}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1682
typically with a destruction rule to extract a subformula of the current
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1683
theorem.  We use \isa{OF} with a list of facts to generate an instance of
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1684
the current theorem.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1685
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1686
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1687
Here is a summary of the primitives for forward reasoning:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1688
\begin{itemize}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1689
\item \isa{of} instantiates the variables of a rule to a list of terms
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1690
\item \isa{OF} applies a rule to a list of theorems
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1691
\item \isa{THEN} gives a theorem to a named rule and returns the
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1692
conclusion 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1693
\end{itemize}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1694
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1695
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1696
\section{Methods for forward proof}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1697
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1698
We have seen that forward proof works well within a backward 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1699
proof.  Also in that spirit is the \isa{insert} method, which inserts a
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1700
given theorem as a new assumption of the current subgoal.  This already
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1701
is a forward step; moreover, we may (as always when using a theorem) apply
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1702
\isa{of}, \isa{THEN} and other directives.  The new assumption can then
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1703
be used to help prove the subgoal.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1704
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1705
For example, consider this theorem about the divides relation. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1706
Only the first proof step is given; it inserts the distributive law for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1707
\isa{gcd}.  We specify its variables as shown. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1708
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1709
\isacommand{lemma}\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1710
relprime_dvd_mult:\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1711
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ "\isasymlbrakk \ gcd(k,n){=}1;\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1712
k\ dvd\ (m*n)\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1713
\isasymrbrakk\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1714
\isasymLongrightarrow\ k\ dvd\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1715
m"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1716
\isacommand{apply}\ (insert\ gcd_mult_distrib2\ [of\ m\ k\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1717
n])
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1718
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1719
In the resulting subgoal, note how the equation has been 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1720
inserted: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1721
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1722
\isasymlbrakk gcd\ (k,\ n)\ =\ 1;\ k\
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1723
dvd\ (m\ *\ n)\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ k\ dvd\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1724
m\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1725
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk gcd\ (k,\ n)\ =\ 1;\ k\ dvd\ (m\ *\ n){;}\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1726
\ \ \ \ \ m\ *\ gcd\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1727
(k,\ n)\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1728
=\ gcd\ (m\ *\ k,\ m\ *\ n)\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1729
\ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ k\ dvd\ m
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1730
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1731
The next proof step, \isa{\isacommand{apply}(simp)}, 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1732
utilizes the assumption \isa{gcd(k,n)\ =\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1733
1}. Here is the result: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1734
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1735
\isasymlbrakk gcd\ (k,\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1736
n)\ =\ 1;\ k\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1737
dvd\ (m\ *\ n)\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ k\ dvd\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1738
m\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1739
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk gcd\ (k,\ n)\ =\ 1;\ k\ dvd\ (m\ *\ n){;}\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1740
\ \ \ \ \ m\ =\ gcd\ (m\ *\ k,\ m\ *\ n)\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1741
\ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ k\ dvd\ m
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1742
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1743
Simplification has yielded an equation for \isa{m} that will be used to
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1744
complete the proof. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1745
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1746
\medskip
10399
e37e123738f7 minor modifications for new Springer style
paulson
parents: 10341
diff changeset
  1747
Here is another proof using \isa{insert}.  \REMARK{Effect with unknowns?}
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1748
Division  and remainder obey a well-known law: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1749
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1750
(?m\ div\ ?n)\ *\ ?n\ +\ ?m\ mod\ ?n\ =\ ?m
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1751
\rulename{mod_div_equality}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1752
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1753
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1754
We refer to this law explicitly in the following proof: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1755
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1756
\isacommand{lemma}\ div_mult_self_is_m:\ \isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1757
\ \ \ \ \ \ "0{\isacharless}n\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ (m*n)\ div\ n\ =\
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1758
(m::nat)"\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1759
\isacommand{apply}\ (insert\ mod_div_equality\ [of\ "m*n"\ n])\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1760
\isacommand{apply}\ (simp)\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1761
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1762
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1763
The first step inserts the law, specifying \isa{m*n} and
10301
paulson
parents: 10295
diff changeset
  1764
\isa{n} for its variables.  Notice that non-trivial expressions must be
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1765
enclosed in quotation marks.  Here is the resulting 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1766
subgoal, with its new assumption: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1767
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1768
%0\ \isacharless\ n\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ (m\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1769
%*\ n)\ div\ n\ =\ m\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1770
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk0\ \isacharless\
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1771
n;\ \ (m\ *\ n)\ div\ n\ *\ n\ +\ (m\ *\ n)\ mod\ n\
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1772
=\ m\ *\ n\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1773
\ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ (m\ *\ n)\ div\ n\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1774
=\ m
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1775
\end{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1776
Simplification reduces \isa{(m\ *\ n)\ mod\ n} to zero.
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1777
Then it cancels the factor~\isa{n} on both
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1778
sides of the equation, proving the theorem. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1779
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1780
\medskip
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1781
A similar method is {\isa{subgoal_tac}}. Instead of inserting 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1782
a theorem as an assumption, it inserts an arbitrary formula. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1783
This formula must be proved later as a separate subgoal. The 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1784
idea is to claim that the formula holds on the basis of the current 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1785
assumptions, to use this claim to complete the proof, and finally 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1786
to justify the claim. It is a valuable means of giving the proof 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1787
some structure. The explicit formula will be more readable than 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1788
proof commands that yield that formula indirectly.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1789
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1790
Look at the following example. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1791
\begin{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1792
\isacommand{lemma}\ "\isasymlbrakk(z::int)\ <\ \#37;\ \#66\ <\ \#2*z;\ z*z\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1793
\isasymnoteq\ \#1225;\ Q(\#34);\ Q(\#36)\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1794
\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \,\isasymLongrightarrow\ Q(z)"\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1795
\isacommand{apply}\ (subgoal_tac\ "z\ =\ \#34\ \isasymor\ z\ =\
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1796
\#36")\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1797
\isacommand{apply}\ blast\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1798
\isacommand{apply}\ (subgoal_tac\ "z\ \isasymnoteq\ \#35")\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1799
\isacommand{apply}\ arith\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1800
\isacommand{apply}\ force\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1801
\isacommand{done}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1802
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1803
Let us prove it informally.  The first assumption tells us 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1804
that \isa{z} is no greater than 36. The second tells us that \isa{z} 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1805
is at least 34. The third assumption tells us that \isa{z} cannot be 35, since
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1806
$35\times35=1225$.  So \isa{z} is either 34 or 36, and since \isa{Q} holds for
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1807
both of those  values, we have the conclusion. 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1808
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1809
The Isabelle proof closely follows this reasoning. The first 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1810
step is to claim that \isa{z} is either 34 or 36. The resulting proof 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1811
state gives us two subgoals: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1812
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1813
%\isasymlbrakk z\ <\ \#37;\ \#66\ <\ \#2\ *\ z;\ z\ *\ z\ \isasymnoteq\ \#1225;\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1814
%Q\ \#34;\ Q\ \#36\isasymrbrakk\ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ z\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1815
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk z\ <\ \#37;\ \#66\ <\ \#2\ *\ z;\ z\ *\ z\ \isasymnoteq\ \#1225;\ Q\ \#34;\ Q\ \#36;\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1816
\ \ \ \ \ z\ =\ \#34\ \isasymor\ z\ =\ \#36\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1817
\ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ Q\ z\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1818
\ 2.\ \isasymlbrakk z\ <\ \#37;\ \#66\ <\ \#2\ *\ z;\ z\ *\ z\ \isasymnoteq\ \#1225;\ Q\ \#34;\ Q\ \#36\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1819
\ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ z\ =\ \#34\ \isasymor\ z\ =\ \#36
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1820
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1821
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1822
The first subgoal is trivial, but for the second Isabelle needs help to eliminate
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1823
the case
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1824
\isa{z}=35.  The second invocation  of {\isa{subgoal_tac}} leaves two
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1825
subgoals: 
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1826
\begin{isabelle}
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1827
\ 1.\ \isasymlbrakk z\ <\ \#37;\ \#66\ <\ \#2\ *\ z;\ z\ *\ z\ \isasymnoteq\
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1828
\#1225;\ Q\ \#34;\ Q\ \#36;\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1829
\ \ \ \ \ z\ \isasymnoteq\ \#35\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1830
\ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ z\ =\ \#34\ \isasymor\ z\ =\ \#36\isanewline
10596
77951eaeb5b0 tidying
paulson
parents: 10578
diff changeset
  1831
\ 2.\ \isasymlbrakk z\ <\ \#37;\ \#66\ <\ \#2\ *\ z;\ z\ *\ z\ \isasymnoteq\ \#1225;\ Q\ \#34;\ Q\ \#36\isasymrbrakk\isanewline
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1832
\ \ \ \ \isasymLongrightarrow\ z\ \isasymnoteq\ \#35
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1833
\end{isabelle}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1834
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1835
Assuming that \isa{z} is not 35, the first subgoal follows by linear arithmetic:
10546
b0ad1ed24cf6 replaced Eps by SOME
paulson
parents: 10399
diff changeset
  1836
the method {\isa{arith}}. For the second subgoal we apply the method \isa{force}, 
10295
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1837
which proceeds by assuming that \isa{z}=35 and arriving at a contradiction.
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1838
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1839
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1840
\medskip
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1841
Summary of these methods:
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1842
\begin{itemize}
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1843
\item {\isa{insert}} adds a theorem as a new assumption
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1844
\item {\isa{subgoal_tac}} adds a formula as a new assumption and leaves the
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1845
subgoal of proving that formula
8eb12693cead the Rules chapter and theories
paulson
parents:
diff changeset
  1846
\end{itemize}