26869
|
1 |
(* $Id$ *)
|
|
2 |
|
|
3 |
theory Proof
|
|
4 |
imports Main
|
|
5 |
begin
|
|
6 |
|
|
7 |
chapter {* Proofs *}
|
|
8 |
|
26870
|
9 |
text {*
|
|
10 |
Proof commands perform transitions of Isar/VM machine
|
|
11 |
configurations, which are block-structured, consisting of a stack of
|
|
12 |
nodes with three main components: logical proof context, current
|
|
13 |
facts, and open goals. Isar/VM transitions are \emph{typed}
|
|
14 |
according to the following three different modes of operation:
|
|
15 |
|
|
16 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
17 |
|
|
18 |
\item [@{text "proof(prove)"}] means that a new goal has just been
|
|
19 |
stated that is now to be \emph{proven}; the next command may refine
|
|
20 |
it by some proof method, and enter a sub-proof to establish the
|
|
21 |
actual result.
|
|
22 |
|
|
23 |
\item [@{text "proof(state)"}] is like a nested theory mode: the
|
|
24 |
context may be augmented by \emph{stating} additional assumptions,
|
|
25 |
intermediate results etc.
|
|
26 |
|
|
27 |
\item [@{text "proof(chain)"}] is intermediate between @{text
|
|
28 |
"proof(state)"} and @{text "proof(prove)"}: existing facts (i.e.\
|
|
29 |
the contents of the special ``@{fact_ref this}'' register) have been
|
|
30 |
just picked up in order to be used when refining the goal claimed
|
|
31 |
next.
|
|
32 |
|
|
33 |
\end{descr}
|
|
34 |
|
|
35 |
The proof mode indicator may be read as a verb telling the writer
|
|
36 |
what kind of operation may be performed next. The corresponding
|
|
37 |
typings of proof commands restricts the shape of well-formed proof
|
|
38 |
texts to particular command sequences. So dynamic arrangements of
|
|
39 |
commands eventually turn out as static texts of a certain structure.
|
|
40 |
\Appref{ap:refcard} gives a simplified grammar of the overall
|
|
41 |
(extensible) language emerging that way.
|
|
42 |
*}
|
|
43 |
|
|
44 |
|
|
45 |
section {* Context elements \label{sec:proof-context} *}
|
|
46 |
|
|
47 |
text {*
|
|
48 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
49 |
@{command_def "fix"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
50 |
@{command_def "assume"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
51 |
@{command_def "presume"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
52 |
@{command_def "def"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
53 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
54 |
|
|
55 |
The logical proof context consists of fixed variables and
|
|
56 |
assumptions. The former closely correspond to Skolem constants, or
|
|
57 |
meta-level universal quantification as provided by the Isabelle/Pure
|
|
58 |
logical framework. Introducing some \emph{arbitrary, but fixed}
|
|
59 |
variable via ``@{command "fix"}~@{text x}'' results in a local value
|
|
60 |
that may be used in the subsequent proof as any other variable or
|
|
61 |
constant. Furthermore, any result @{text "\<turnstile> \<phi>[x]"} exported from
|
|
62 |
the context will be universally closed wrt.\ @{text x} at the
|
|
63 |
outermost level: @{text "\<turnstile> \<And>x. \<phi>[x]"} (this is expressed in normal
|
|
64 |
form using Isabelle's meta-variables).
|
|
65 |
|
|
66 |
Similarly, introducing some assumption @{text \<chi>} has two effects.
|
|
67 |
On the one hand, a local theorem is created that may be used as a
|
|
68 |
fact in subsequent proof steps. On the other hand, any result
|
|
69 |
@{text "\<chi> \<turnstile> \<phi>"} exported from the context becomes conditional wrt.\
|
|
70 |
the assumption: @{text "\<turnstile> \<chi> \<Longrightarrow> \<phi>"}. Thus, solving an enclosing goal
|
|
71 |
using such a result would basically introduce a new subgoal stemming
|
|
72 |
from the assumption. How this situation is handled depends on the
|
|
73 |
version of assumption command used: while @{command "assume"}
|
|
74 |
insists on solving the subgoal by unification with some premise of
|
|
75 |
the goal, @{command "presume"} leaves the subgoal unchanged in order
|
|
76 |
to be proved later by the user.
|
|
77 |
|
|
78 |
Local definitions, introduced by ``@{command "def"}~@{text "x \<equiv>
|
|
79 |
t"}'', are achieved by combining ``@{command "fix"}~@{text x}'' with
|
|
80 |
another version of assumption that causes any hypothetical equation
|
|
81 |
@{text "x \<equiv> t"} to be eliminated by the reflexivity rule. Thus,
|
|
82 |
exporting some result @{text "x \<equiv> t \<turnstile> \<phi>[x]"} yields @{text "\<turnstile>
|
|
83 |
\<phi>[t]"}.
|
|
84 |
|
|
85 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
86 |
'fix' (vars + 'and')
|
|
87 |
;
|
|
88 |
('assume' | 'presume') (props + 'and')
|
|
89 |
;
|
|
90 |
'def' (def + 'and')
|
|
91 |
;
|
|
92 |
def: thmdecl? \\ name ('==' | equiv) term termpat?
|
|
93 |
;
|
|
94 |
\end{rail}
|
|
95 |
|
|
96 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
97 |
|
|
98 |
\item [@{command "fix"}~@{text x}] introduces a local variable
|
|
99 |
@{text x} that is \emph{arbitrary, but fixed.}
|
|
100 |
|
|
101 |
\item [@{command "assume"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"} and @{command
|
|
102 |
"presume"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"}] introduce a local fact @{text "\<phi> \<turnstile> \<phi>"} by
|
|
103 |
assumption. Subsequent results applied to an enclosing goal (e.g.\
|
|
104 |
by @{command_ref "show"}) are handled as follows: @{command
|
|
105 |
"assume"} expects to be able to unify with existing premises in the
|
|
106 |
goal, while @{command "presume"} leaves @{text \<phi>} as new subgoals.
|
|
107 |
|
|
108 |
Several lists of assumptions may be given (separated by
|
|
109 |
@{keyword_ref "and"}; the resulting list of current facts consists
|
|
110 |
of all of these concatenated.
|
|
111 |
|
|
112 |
\item [@{command "def"}~@{text "x \<equiv> t"}] introduces a local
|
|
113 |
(non-polymorphic) definition. In results exported from the context,
|
|
114 |
@{text x} is replaced by @{text t}. Basically, ``@{command
|
|
115 |
"def"}~@{text "x \<equiv> t"}'' abbreviates ``@{command "fix"}~@{text
|
|
116 |
x}~@{command "assume"}~@{text "x \<equiv> t"}'', with the resulting
|
|
117 |
hypothetical equation solved by reflexivity.
|
|
118 |
|
|
119 |
The default name for the definitional equation is @{text x_def}.
|
|
120 |
Several simultaneous definitions may be given at the same time.
|
|
121 |
|
|
122 |
\end{descr}
|
|
123 |
|
|
124 |
The special name @{fact_ref prems} refers to all assumptions of the
|
|
125 |
current context as a list of theorems. This feature should be used
|
|
126 |
with great care! It is better avoided in final proof texts.
|
|
127 |
*}
|
|
128 |
|
|
129 |
|
|
130 |
section {* Facts and forward chaining *}
|
|
131 |
|
|
132 |
text {*
|
|
133 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
134 |
@{command_def "note"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
135 |
@{command_def "then"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(chain)} \\
|
|
136 |
@{command_def "from"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(chain)} \\
|
|
137 |
@{command_def "with"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(chain)} \\
|
|
138 |
@{command_def "using"} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
139 |
@{command_def "unfolding"} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
140 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
141 |
|
|
142 |
New facts are established either by assumption or proof of local
|
|
143 |
statements. Any fact will usually be involved in further proofs,
|
|
144 |
either as explicit arguments of proof methods, or when forward
|
|
145 |
chaining towards the next goal via @{command "then"} (and variants);
|
|
146 |
@{command "from"} and @{command "with"} are composite forms
|
|
147 |
involving @{command "note"}. The @{command "using"} elements
|
|
148 |
augments the collection of used facts \emph{after} a goal has been
|
|
149 |
stated. Note that the special theorem name @{fact_ref this} refers
|
|
150 |
to the most recently established facts, but only \emph{before}
|
|
151 |
issuing a follow-up claim.
|
|
152 |
|
|
153 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
154 |
'note' (thmdef? thmrefs + 'and')
|
|
155 |
;
|
|
156 |
('from' | 'with' | 'using' | 'unfolding') (thmrefs + 'and')
|
|
157 |
;
|
|
158 |
\end{rail}
|
|
159 |
|
|
160 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
161 |
|
|
162 |
\item [@{command "note"}~@{text "a = b\<^sub>1 \<dots> b\<^sub>n"}]
|
|
163 |
recalls existing facts @{text "b\<^sub>1, \<dots>, b\<^sub>n"}, binding
|
|
164 |
the result as @{text a}. Note that attributes may be involved as
|
|
165 |
well, both on the left and right hand sides.
|
|
166 |
|
|
167 |
\item [@{command "then"}] indicates forward chaining by the current
|
|
168 |
facts in order to establish the goal to be claimed next. The
|
|
169 |
initial proof method invoked to refine that will be offered the
|
|
170 |
facts to do ``anything appropriate'' (see also
|
|
171 |
\secref{sec:proof-steps}). For example, method @{method_ref rule}
|
|
172 |
(see \secref{sec:pure-meth-att}) would typically do an elimination
|
|
173 |
rather than an introduction. Automatic methods usually insert the
|
|
174 |
facts into the goal state before operation. This provides a simple
|
|
175 |
scheme to control relevance of facts in automated proof search.
|
|
176 |
|
|
177 |
\item [@{command "from"}~@{text b}] abbreviates ``@{command
|
|
178 |
"note"}~@{text b}~@{command "then"}''; thus @{command "then"} is
|
|
179 |
equivalent to ``@{command "from"}~@{text this}''.
|
|
180 |
|
|
181 |
\item [@{command "with"}~@{text "b\<^sub>1 \<dots> b\<^sub>n"}]
|
|
182 |
abbreviates ``@{command "from"}~@{text "b\<^sub>1 \<dots> b\<^sub>n \<AND>
|
|
183 |
this"}''; thus the forward chaining is from earlier facts together
|
|
184 |
with the current ones.
|
|
185 |
|
|
186 |
\item [@{command "using"}~@{text "b\<^sub>1 \<dots> b\<^sub>n"}] augments
|
|
187 |
the facts being currently indicated for use by a subsequent
|
|
188 |
refinement step (such as @{command_ref "apply"} or @{command_ref
|
|
189 |
"proof"}).
|
|
190 |
|
|
191 |
\item [@{command "unfolding"}~@{text "b\<^sub>1 \<dots> b\<^sub>n"}] is
|
|
192 |
structurally similar to @{command "using"}, but unfolds definitional
|
|
193 |
equations @{text "b\<^sub>1, \<dots> b\<^sub>n"} throughout the goal state
|
|
194 |
and facts.
|
|
195 |
|
|
196 |
\end{descr}
|
|
197 |
|
|
198 |
Forward chaining with an empty list of theorems is the same as not
|
|
199 |
chaining at all. Thus ``@{command "from"}~@{text nothing}'' has no
|
|
200 |
effect apart from entering @{text "prove(chain)"} mode, since
|
|
201 |
@{fact_ref nothing} is bound to the empty list of theorems.
|
|
202 |
|
|
203 |
Basic proof methods (such as @{method_ref rule}) expect multiple
|
|
204 |
facts to be given in their proper order, corresponding to a prefix
|
|
205 |
of the premises of the rule involved. Note that positions may be
|
|
206 |
easily skipped using something like @{command "from"}~@{text "_
|
|
207 |
\<AND> a \<AND> b"}, for example. This involves the trivial rule
|
|
208 |
@{text "PROP \<psi> \<Longrightarrow> PROP \<psi>"}, which is bound in Isabelle/Pure as
|
|
209 |
``@{fact_ref "_"}'' (underscore).
|
|
210 |
|
|
211 |
Automated methods (such as @{method simp} or @{method auto}) just
|
|
212 |
insert any given facts before their usual operation. Depending on
|
|
213 |
the kind of procedure involved, the order of facts is less
|
|
214 |
significant here.
|
|
215 |
*}
|
|
216 |
|
|
217 |
|
|
218 |
section {* Goal statements \label{sec:goals} *}
|
|
219 |
|
|
220 |
text {*
|
|
221 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
222 |
@{command_def "lemma"} & : & \isartrans{local{\dsh}theory}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
223 |
@{command_def "theorem"} & : & \isartrans{local{\dsh}theory}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
224 |
@{command_def "corollary"} & : & \isartrans{local{\dsh}theory}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
225 |
@{command_def "have"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state) ~|~ proof(chain)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
226 |
@{command_def "show"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state) ~|~ proof(chain)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
227 |
@{command_def "hence"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
228 |
@{command_def "thus"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
229 |
@{command_def "print_statement"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
|
|
230 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
231 |
|
|
232 |
From a theory context, proof mode is entered by an initial goal
|
|
233 |
command such as @{command "lemma"}, @{command "theorem"}, or
|
|
234 |
@{command "corollary"}. Within a proof, new claims may be
|
|
235 |
introduced locally as well; four variants are available here to
|
|
236 |
indicate whether forward chaining of facts should be performed
|
|
237 |
initially (via @{command_ref "then"}), and whether the final result
|
|
238 |
is meant to solve some pending goal.
|
|
239 |
|
|
240 |
Goals may consist of multiple statements, resulting in a list of
|
|
241 |
facts eventually. A pending multi-goal is internally represented as
|
|
242 |
a meta-level conjunction (printed as @{text "&&"}), which is usually
|
|
243 |
split into the corresponding number of sub-goals prior to an initial
|
|
244 |
method application, via @{command_ref "proof"}
|
|
245 |
(\secref{sec:proof-steps}) or @{command_ref "apply"}
|
|
246 |
(\secref{sec:tactic-commands}). The @{method_ref induct} method
|
|
247 |
covered in \secref{sec:cases-induct} acts on multiple claims
|
|
248 |
simultaneously.
|
|
249 |
|
|
250 |
Claims at the theory level may be either in short or long form. A
|
|
251 |
short goal merely consists of several simultaneous propositions
|
|
252 |
(often just one). A long goal includes an explicit context
|
|
253 |
specification for the subsequent conclusion, involving local
|
|
254 |
parameters and assumptions. Here the role of each part of the
|
|
255 |
statement is explicitly marked by separate keywords (see also
|
|
256 |
\secref{sec:locale}); the local assumptions being introduced here
|
|
257 |
are available as @{fact_ref assms} in the proof. Moreover, there
|
|
258 |
are two kinds of conclusions: @{element_def "shows"} states several
|
|
259 |
simultaneous propositions (essentially a big conjunction), while
|
|
260 |
@{element_def "obtains"} claims several simultaneous simultaneous
|
|
261 |
contexts of (essentially a big disjunction of eliminated parameters
|
|
262 |
and assumptions, cf.\ \secref{sec:obtain}).
|
|
263 |
|
|
264 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
265 |
('lemma' | 'theorem' | 'corollary') target? (goal | longgoal)
|
|
266 |
;
|
|
267 |
('have' | 'show' | 'hence' | 'thus') goal
|
|
268 |
;
|
|
269 |
'print\_statement' modes? thmrefs
|
|
270 |
;
|
|
271 |
|
|
272 |
goal: (props + 'and')
|
|
273 |
;
|
|
274 |
longgoal: thmdecl? (contextelem *) conclusion
|
|
275 |
;
|
|
276 |
conclusion: 'shows' goal | 'obtains' (parname? case + '|')
|
|
277 |
;
|
|
278 |
case: (vars + 'and') 'where' (props + 'and')
|
|
279 |
;
|
|
280 |
\end{rail}
|
|
281 |
|
|
282 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
283 |
|
|
284 |
\item [@{command "lemma"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"}] enters proof mode with
|
|
285 |
@{text \<phi>} as main goal, eventually resulting in some fact @{text "\<turnstile>
|
|
286 |
\<phi>"} to be put back into the target context. An additional
|
|
287 |
\railnonterm{context} specification may build up an initial proof
|
|
288 |
context for the subsequent claim; this includes local definitions
|
|
289 |
and syntax as well, see the definition of @{syntax contextelem} in
|
|
290 |
\secref{sec:locale}.
|
|
291 |
|
|
292 |
\item [@{command "theorem"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"} and @{command
|
|
293 |
"corollary"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"}] are essentially the same as @{command
|
|
294 |
"lemma"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"}, but the facts are internally marked as
|
|
295 |
being of a different kind. This discrimination acts like a formal
|
|
296 |
comment.
|
|
297 |
|
|
298 |
\item [@{command "have"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"}] claims a local goal,
|
|
299 |
eventually resulting in a fact within the current logical context.
|
|
300 |
This operation is completely independent of any pending sub-goals of
|
|
301 |
an enclosing goal statements, so @{command "have"} may be freely
|
|
302 |
used for experimental exploration of potential results within a
|
|
303 |
proof body.
|
|
304 |
|
|
305 |
\item [@{command "show"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"}] is like @{command
|
|
306 |
"have"}~@{text "a: \<phi>"} plus a second stage to refine some pending
|
|
307 |
sub-goal for each one of the finished result, after having been
|
|
308 |
exported into the corresponding context (at the head of the
|
|
309 |
sub-proof of this @{command "show"} command).
|
|
310 |
|
|
311 |
To accommodate interactive debugging, resulting rules are printed
|
|
312 |
before being applied internally. Even more, interactive execution
|
|
313 |
of @{command "show"} predicts potential failure and displays the
|
|
314 |
resulting error as a warning beforehand. Watch out for the
|
|
315 |
following message:
|
|
316 |
|
|
317 |
%FIXME proper antiquitation
|
|
318 |
\begin{ttbox}
|
|
319 |
Problem! Local statement will fail to solve any pending goal
|
|
320 |
\end{ttbox}
|
|
321 |
|
|
322 |
\item [@{command "hence"}] abbreviates ``@{command "then"}~@{command
|
|
323 |
"have"}'', i.e.\ claims a local goal to be proven by forward
|
|
324 |
chaining the current facts. Note that @{command "hence"} is also
|
|
325 |
equivalent to ``@{command "from"}~@{text this}~@{command "have"}''.
|
|
326 |
|
|
327 |
\item [@{command "thus"}] abbreviates ``@{command "then"}~@{command
|
|
328 |
"show"}''. Note that @{command "thus"} is also equivalent to
|
|
329 |
``@{command "from"}~@{text this}~@{command "show"}''.
|
|
330 |
|
|
331 |
\item [@{command "print_statement"}~@{text a}] prints facts from the
|
|
332 |
current theory or proof context in long statement form, according to
|
|
333 |
the syntax for @{command "lemma"} given above.
|
|
334 |
|
|
335 |
\end{descr}
|
|
336 |
|
|
337 |
Any goal statement causes some term abbreviations (such as
|
|
338 |
@{variable_ref "?thesis"}) to be bound automatically, see also
|
|
339 |
\secref{sec:term-abbrev}. Furthermore, the local context of a
|
|
340 |
(non-atomic) goal is provided via the @{case_ref rule_context} case.
|
|
341 |
|
|
342 |
The optional case names of @{element_ref "obtains"} have a twofold
|
|
343 |
meaning: (1) during the of this claim they refer to the the local
|
|
344 |
context introductions, (2) the resulting rule is annotated
|
|
345 |
accordingly to support symbolic case splits when used with the
|
|
346 |
@{method_ref cases} method (cf. \secref{sec:cases-induct}).
|
|
347 |
|
|
348 |
\medskip
|
|
349 |
|
|
350 |
\begin{warn}
|
|
351 |
Isabelle/Isar suffers theory-level goal statements to contain
|
|
352 |
\emph{unbound schematic variables}, although this does not conform
|
|
353 |
to the aim of human-readable proof documents! The main problem
|
|
354 |
with schematic goals is that the actual outcome is usually hard to
|
|
355 |
predict, depending on the behavior of the proof methods applied
|
|
356 |
during the course of reasoning. Note that most semi-automated
|
|
357 |
methods heavily depend on several kinds of implicit rule
|
|
358 |
declarations within the current theory context. As this would
|
|
359 |
also result in non-compositional checking of sub-proofs,
|
|
360 |
\emph{local goals} are not allowed to be schematic at all.
|
|
361 |
Nevertheless, schematic goals do have their use in Prolog-style
|
|
362 |
interactive synthesis of proven results, usually by stepwise
|
|
363 |
refinement via emulation of traditional Isabelle tactic scripts
|
|
364 |
(see also \secref{sec:tactic-commands}). In any case, users
|
|
365 |
should know what they are doing.
|
|
366 |
\end{warn}
|
|
367 |
*}
|
|
368 |
|
|
369 |
|
|
370 |
section {* Initial and terminal proof steps \label{sec:proof-steps} *}
|
|
371 |
|
|
372 |
text {*
|
|
373 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
374 |
@{command_def "proof"} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
375 |
@{command_def "qed"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state) ~|~ theory} \\
|
|
376 |
@{command_def "by"} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(state) ~|~ theory} \\
|
|
377 |
@{command_def ".."} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(state) ~|~ theory} \\
|
|
378 |
@{command_def "."} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(state) ~|~ theory} \\
|
|
379 |
@{command_def "sorry"} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(state) ~|~ theory} \\
|
|
380 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
381 |
|
|
382 |
Arbitrary goal refinement via tactics is considered harmful.
|
|
383 |
Structured proof composition in Isar admits proof methods to be
|
|
384 |
invoked in two places only.
|
|
385 |
|
|
386 |
\begin{enumerate}
|
|
387 |
|
|
388 |
\item An \emph{initial} refinement step @{command_ref
|
|
389 |
"proof"}~@{text "m\<^sub>1"} reduces a newly stated goal to a number
|
|
390 |
of sub-goals that are to be solved later. Facts are passed to
|
|
391 |
@{text "m\<^sub>1"} for forward chaining, if so indicated by @{text
|
|
392 |
"proof(chain)"} mode.
|
|
393 |
|
|
394 |
\item A \emph{terminal} conclusion step @{command_ref "qed"}~@{text
|
|
395 |
"m\<^sub>2"} is intended to solve remaining goals. No facts are
|
|
396 |
passed to @{text "m\<^sub>2"}.
|
|
397 |
|
|
398 |
\end{enumerate}
|
|
399 |
|
|
400 |
The only other (proper) way to affect pending goals in a proof body
|
|
401 |
is by @{command_ref "show"}, which involves an explicit statement of
|
|
402 |
what is to be solved eventually. Thus we avoid the fundamental
|
|
403 |
problem of unstructured tactic scripts that consist of numerous
|
|
404 |
consecutive goal transformations, with invisible effects.
|
|
405 |
|
|
406 |
\medskip As a general rule of thumb for good proof style, initial
|
|
407 |
proof methods should either solve the goal completely, or constitute
|
|
408 |
some well-understood reduction to new sub-goals. Arbitrary
|
|
409 |
automatic proof tools that are prone leave a large number of badly
|
|
410 |
structured sub-goals are no help in continuing the proof document in
|
|
411 |
an intelligible manner.
|
|
412 |
|
|
413 |
Unless given explicitly by the user, the default initial method is
|
|
414 |
``@{method_ref rule}'', which applies a single standard elimination
|
|
415 |
or introduction rule according to the topmost symbol involved.
|
|
416 |
There is no separate default terminal method. Any remaining goals
|
|
417 |
are always solved by assumption in the very last step.
|
|
418 |
|
|
419 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
420 |
'proof' method?
|
|
421 |
;
|
|
422 |
'qed' method?
|
|
423 |
;
|
|
424 |
'by' method method?
|
|
425 |
;
|
|
426 |
('.' | '..' | 'sorry')
|
|
427 |
;
|
|
428 |
\end{rail}
|
|
429 |
|
|
430 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
431 |
|
|
432 |
\item [@{command "proof"}~@{text "m\<^sub>1"}] refines the goal by
|
|
433 |
proof method @{text "m\<^sub>1"}; facts for forward chaining are
|
|
434 |
passed if so indicated by @{text "proof(chain)"} mode.
|
|
435 |
|
|
436 |
\item [@{command "qed"}~@{text "m\<^sub>2"}] refines any remaining
|
|
437 |
goals by proof method @{text "m\<^sub>2"} and concludes the
|
|
438 |
sub-proof by assumption. If the goal had been @{text "show"} (or
|
|
439 |
@{text "thus"}), some pending sub-goal is solved as well by the rule
|
|
440 |
resulting from the result \emph{exported} into the enclosing goal
|
|
441 |
context. Thus @{text "qed"} may fail for two reasons: either @{text
|
|
442 |
"m\<^sub>2"} fails, or the resulting rule does not fit to any
|
|
443 |
pending goal\footnote{This includes any additional ``strong''
|
|
444 |
assumptions as introduced by @{command "assume"}.} of the enclosing
|
|
445 |
context. Debugging such a situation might involve temporarily
|
|
446 |
changing @{command "show"} into @{command "have"}, or weakening the
|
|
447 |
local context by replacing occurrences of @{command "assume"} by
|
|
448 |
@{command "presume"}.
|
|
449 |
|
|
450 |
\item [@{command "by"}~@{text "m\<^sub>1 m\<^sub>2"}] is a
|
|
451 |
\emph{terminal proof}\index{proof!terminal}; it abbreviates
|
|
452 |
@{command "proof"}~@{text "m\<^sub>1"}~@{text "qed"}~@{text
|
|
453 |
"m\<^sub>2"}, but with backtracking across both methods. Debugging
|
|
454 |
an unsuccessful @{command "by"}~@{text "m\<^sub>1 m\<^sub>2"}
|
|
455 |
command can be done by expanding its definition; in many cases
|
|
456 |
@{command "proof"}~@{text "m\<^sub>1"} (or even @{text
|
|
457 |
"apply"}~@{text "m\<^sub>1"}) is already sufficient to see the
|
|
458 |
problem.
|
|
459 |
|
|
460 |
\item [``@{command ".."}''] is a \emph{default
|
|
461 |
proof}\index{proof!default}; it abbreviates @{command "by"}~@{text
|
|
462 |
"rule"}.
|
|
463 |
|
|
464 |
\item [``@{command "."}''] is a \emph{trivial
|
|
465 |
proof}\index{proof!trivial}; it abbreviates @{command "by"}~@{text
|
|
466 |
"this"}.
|
|
467 |
|
|
468 |
\item [@{command "sorry"}] is a \emph{fake proof}\index{proof!fake}
|
|
469 |
pretending to solve the pending claim without further ado. This
|
|
470 |
only works in interactive development, or if the @{ML
|
|
471 |
quick_and_dirty} flag is enabled (in ML). Facts emerging from fake
|
|
472 |
proofs are not the real thing. Internally, each theorem container
|
|
473 |
is tainted by an oracle invocation, which is indicated as ``@{text
|
|
474 |
"[!]"}'' in the printed result.
|
|
475 |
|
|
476 |
The most important application of @{command "sorry"} is to support
|
|
477 |
experimentation and top-down proof development.
|
|
478 |
|
|
479 |
\end{descr}
|
|
480 |
*}
|
|
481 |
|
|
482 |
|
|
483 |
section {* Fundamental methods and attributes \label{sec:pure-meth-att} *}
|
|
484 |
|
|
485 |
text {*
|
|
486 |
The following proof methods and attributes refer to basic logical
|
|
487 |
operations of Isar. Further methods and attributes are provided by
|
|
488 |
several generic and object-logic specific tools and packages (see
|
|
489 |
\chref{ch:gen-tools} and \chref{ch:hol}).
|
|
490 |
|
|
491 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
492 |
@{method_def "-"} & : & \isarmeth \\
|
|
493 |
@{method_def "fact"} & : & \isarmeth \\
|
|
494 |
@{method_def "assumption"} & : & \isarmeth \\
|
|
495 |
@{method_def "this"} & : & \isarmeth \\
|
|
496 |
@{method_def "rule"} & : & \isarmeth \\
|
|
497 |
@{method_def "iprover"} & : & \isarmeth \\[0.5ex]
|
|
498 |
@{attribute_def "intro"} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
499 |
@{attribute_def "elim"} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
500 |
@{attribute_def "dest"} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
501 |
@{attribute_def "rule"} & : & \isaratt \\[0.5ex]
|
|
502 |
@{attribute_def "OF"} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
503 |
@{attribute_def "of"} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
504 |
@{attribute_def "where"} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
505 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
506 |
|
|
507 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
508 |
'fact' thmrefs?
|
|
509 |
;
|
|
510 |
'rule' thmrefs?
|
|
511 |
;
|
|
512 |
'iprover' ('!' ?) (rulemod *)
|
|
513 |
;
|
|
514 |
rulemod: ('intro' | 'elim' | 'dest') ((('!' | () | '?') nat?) | 'del') ':' thmrefs
|
|
515 |
;
|
|
516 |
('intro' | 'elim' | 'dest') ('!' | () | '?') nat?
|
|
517 |
;
|
|
518 |
'rule' 'del'
|
|
519 |
;
|
|
520 |
'OF' thmrefs
|
|
521 |
;
|
|
522 |
'of' insts ('concl' ':' insts)?
|
|
523 |
;
|
|
524 |
'where' ((name | var | typefree | typevar) '=' (type | term) * 'and')
|
|
525 |
;
|
|
526 |
\end{rail}
|
|
527 |
|
|
528 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
529 |
|
|
530 |
\item [``@{method "-"}'' (minus)] does nothing but insert the
|
|
531 |
forward chaining facts as premises into the goal. Note that command
|
|
532 |
@{command_ref "proof"} without any method actually performs a single
|
|
533 |
reduction step using the @{method_ref rule} method; thus a plain
|
|
534 |
\emph{do-nothing} proof step would be ``@{command "proof"}~@{text
|
|
535 |
"-"}'' rather than @{command "proof"} alone.
|
|
536 |
|
|
537 |
\item [@{method "fact"}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"}] composes
|
|
538 |
some fact from @{text "a\<^sub>1, \<dots>, a\<^sub>n"} (or implicitly from
|
|
539 |
the current proof context) modulo unification of schematic type and
|
|
540 |
term variables. The rule structure is not taken into account, i.e.\
|
|
541 |
meta-level implication is considered atomic. This is the same
|
|
542 |
principle underlying literal facts (cf.\ \secref{sec:syn-att}):
|
|
543 |
``@{command "have"}~@{text "\<phi>"}~@{command "by"}~@{text fact}'' is
|
|
544 |
equivalent to ``@{command "note"}~@{verbatim "`"}@{text \<phi>}@{verbatim
|
|
545 |
"`"}'' provided that @{text "\<turnstile> \<phi>"} is an instance of some known
|
|
546 |
@{text "\<turnstile> \<phi>"} in the proof context.
|
|
547 |
|
|
548 |
\item [@{method assumption}] solves some goal by a single assumption
|
|
549 |
step. All given facts are guaranteed to participate in the
|
|
550 |
refinement; this means there may be only 0 or 1 in the first place.
|
|
551 |
Recall that @{command "qed"} (\secref{sec:proof-steps}) already
|
|
552 |
concludes any remaining sub-goals by assumption, so structured
|
|
553 |
proofs usually need not quote the @{method assumption} method at
|
|
554 |
all.
|
|
555 |
|
|
556 |
\item [@{method this}] applies all of the current facts directly as
|
|
557 |
rules. Recall that ``@{command "."}'' (dot) abbreviates ``@{command
|
|
558 |
"by"}~@{text this}''.
|
|
559 |
|
|
560 |
\item [@{method rule}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"}] applies some
|
|
561 |
rule given as argument in backward manner; facts are used to reduce
|
|
562 |
the rule before applying it to the goal. Thus @{method rule}
|
|
563 |
without facts is plain introduction, while with facts it becomes
|
|
564 |
elimination.
|
|
565 |
|
|
566 |
When no arguments are given, the @{method rule} method tries to pick
|
|
567 |
appropriate rules automatically, as declared in the current context
|
|
568 |
using the @{attribute intro}, @{attribute elim}, @{attribute dest}
|
|
569 |
attributes (see below). This is the default behavior of @{command
|
|
570 |
"proof"} and ``@{command ".."}'' (double-dot) steps (see
|
|
571 |
\secref{sec:proof-steps}).
|
|
572 |
|
|
573 |
\item [@{method iprover}] performs intuitionistic proof search,
|
|
574 |
depending on specifically declared rules from the context, or given
|
|
575 |
as explicit arguments. Chained facts are inserted into the goal
|
|
576 |
before commencing proof search; ``@{method iprover}@{text "!"}''
|
|
577 |
means to include the current @{fact prems} as well.
|
|
578 |
|
|
579 |
Rules need to be classified as @{attribute intro}, @{attribute
|
|
580 |
elim}, or @{attribute dest}; here the ``@{text "!"}'' indicator
|
|
581 |
refers to ``safe'' rules, which may be applied aggressively (without
|
|
582 |
considering back-tracking later). Rules declared with ``@{text
|
|
583 |
"?"}'' are ignored in proof search (the single-step @{method rule}
|
|
584 |
method still observes these). An explicit weight annotation may be
|
|
585 |
given as well; otherwise the number of rule premises will be taken
|
|
586 |
into account here.
|
|
587 |
|
|
588 |
\item [@{attribute intro}, @{attribute elim}, and @{attribute dest}]
|
|
589 |
declare introduction, elimination, and destruct rules, to be used
|
|
590 |
with the @{method rule} and @{method iprover} methods. Note that
|
|
591 |
the latter will ignore rules declared with ``@{text "?"}'', while
|
|
592 |
``@{text "!"}'' are used most aggressively.
|
|
593 |
|
|
594 |
The classical reasoner (see \secref{sec:classical}) introduces its
|
|
595 |
own variants of these attributes; use qualified names to access the
|
|
596 |
present versions of Isabelle/Pure, i.e.\ @{attribute "Pure.intro"}.
|
|
597 |
|
|
598 |
\item [@{attribute rule}~@{text del}] undeclares introduction,
|
|
599 |
elimination, or destruct rules.
|
|
600 |
|
|
601 |
\item [@{attribute OF}~@{text "a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n"}] applies some
|
|
602 |
theorem to all of the given rules @{text "a\<^sub>1, \<dots>, a\<^sub>n"}
|
|
603 |
(in parallel). This corresponds to the @{ML "op MRS"} operation in
|
|
604 |
ML, but note the reversed order. Positions may be effectively
|
|
605 |
skipped by including ``@{text _}'' (underscore) as argument.
|
|
606 |
|
|
607 |
\item [@{attribute of}~@{text "t\<^sub>1 \<dots> t\<^sub>n"}] performs
|
|
608 |
positional instantiation of term variables. The terms @{text
|
|
609 |
"t\<^sub>1, \<dots>, t\<^sub>n"} are substituted for any schematic
|
|
610 |
variables occurring in a theorem from left to right; ``@{text
|
|
611 |
_}'' (underscore) indicates to skip a position. Arguments following
|
|
612 |
a ``@{keyword "concl"}@{text ":"}'' specification refer to positions
|
|
613 |
of the conclusion of a rule.
|
|
614 |
|
|
615 |
\item [@{attribute "where"}~@{text "x\<^sub>1 = t\<^sub>1 \<AND> \<dots>
|
|
616 |
x\<^sub>n = t\<^sub>n"}] performs named instantiation of schematic
|
|
617 |
type and term variables occurring in a theorem. Schematic variables
|
|
618 |
have to be specified on the left-hand side (e.g.\ @{text "?x1.3"}).
|
|
619 |
The question mark may be omitted if the variable name is a plain
|
|
620 |
identifier without index. As type instantiations are inferred from
|
|
621 |
term instantiations, explicit type instantiations are seldom
|
|
622 |
necessary.
|
|
623 |
|
|
624 |
\end{descr}
|
|
625 |
*}
|
|
626 |
|
|
627 |
|
|
628 |
section {* Term abbreviations \label{sec:term-abbrev} *}
|
|
629 |
|
|
630 |
text {*
|
|
631 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
632 |
@{command_def "let"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
633 |
@{keyword_def "is"} & : & syntax \\
|
|
634 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
635 |
|
|
636 |
Abbreviations may be either bound by explicit @{command
|
|
637 |
"let"}~@{text "p \<equiv> t"} statements, or by annotating assumptions or
|
|
638 |
goal statements with a list of patterns ``@{text "(\<IS> p\<^sub>1 \<dots>
|
|
639 |
p\<^sub>n)"}''. In both cases, higher-order matching is invoked to
|
|
640 |
bind extra-logical term variables, which may be either named
|
|
641 |
schematic variables of the form @{text ?x}, or nameless dummies
|
|
642 |
``@{variable _}'' (underscore). Note that in the @{command "let"}
|
|
643 |
form the patterns occur on the left-hand side, while the @{keyword
|
|
644 |
"is"} patterns are in postfix position.
|
|
645 |
|
|
646 |
Polymorphism of term bindings is handled in Hindley-Milner style,
|
|
647 |
similar to ML. Type variables referring to local assumptions or
|
|
648 |
open goal statements are \emph{fixed}, while those of finished
|
|
649 |
results or bound by @{command "let"} may occur in \emph{arbitrary}
|
|
650 |
instances later. Even though actual polymorphism should be rarely
|
|
651 |
used in practice, this mechanism is essential to achieve proper
|
|
652 |
incremental type-inference, as the user proceeds to build up the
|
|
653 |
Isar proof text from left to right.
|
|
654 |
|
|
655 |
\medskip Term abbreviations are quite different from local
|
|
656 |
definitions as introduced via @{command "def"} (see
|
|
657 |
\secref{sec:proof-context}). The latter are visible within the
|
|
658 |
logic as actual equations, while abbreviations disappear during the
|
|
659 |
input process just after type checking. Also note that @{command
|
|
660 |
"def"} does not support polymorphism.
|
|
661 |
|
|
662 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
663 |
'let' ((term + 'and') '=' term + 'and')
|
|
664 |
;
|
|
665 |
\end{rail}
|
|
666 |
|
|
667 |
The syntax of @{keyword "is"} patterns follows \railnonterm{termpat}
|
|
668 |
or \railnonterm{proppat} (see \secref{sec:term-decls}).
|
|
669 |
|
|
670 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
671 |
|
|
672 |
\item [@{command "let"}~@{text "p\<^sub>1 = t\<^sub>1 \<AND> \<dots>
|
|
673 |
p\<^sub>n = t\<^sub>n"}] binds any text variables in patterns @{text
|
|
674 |
"p\<^sub>1, \<dots>, p\<^sub>n"} by simultaneous higher-order matching
|
|
675 |
against terms @{text "t\<^sub>1, \<dots>, t\<^sub>n"}.
|
|
676 |
|
|
677 |
\item [@{text "(\<IS> p\<^sub>1 \<dots> p\<^sub>n)"}] resembles @{command
|
|
678 |
"let"}, but matches @{text "p\<^sub>1, \<dots>, p\<^sub>n"} against the
|
|
679 |
preceding statement. Also note that @{keyword "is"} is not a
|
|
680 |
separate command, but part of others (such as @{command "assume"},
|
|
681 |
@{command "have"} etc.).
|
|
682 |
|
|
683 |
\end{descr}
|
|
684 |
|
|
685 |
Some \emph{implicit} term abbreviations\index{term abbreviations}
|
|
686 |
for goals and facts are available as well. For any open goal,
|
|
687 |
@{variable_ref thesis} refers to its object-level statement,
|
|
688 |
abstracted over any meta-level parameters (if present). Likewise,
|
|
689 |
@{variable_ref this} is bound for fact statements resulting from
|
|
690 |
assumptions or finished goals. In case @{variable this} refers to
|
|
691 |
an object-logic statement that is an application @{text "f t"}, then
|
|
692 |
@{text t} is bound to the special text variable ``@{variable "\<dots>"}''
|
|
693 |
(three dots). The canonical application of this convenience are
|
|
694 |
calculational proofs (see \secref{sec:calculation}).
|
|
695 |
*}
|
|
696 |
|
|
697 |
|
|
698 |
section {* Block structure *}
|
|
699 |
|
|
700 |
text {*
|
|
701 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
702 |
@{command_def "next"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
703 |
@{command_def "{"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
704 |
@{command_def "}"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
705 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
706 |
|
|
707 |
While Isar is inherently block-structured, opening and closing
|
|
708 |
blocks is mostly handled rather casually, with little explicit
|
|
709 |
user-intervention. Any local goal statement automatically opens
|
|
710 |
\emph{two} internal blocks, which are closed again when concluding
|
|
711 |
the sub-proof (by @{command "qed"} etc.). Sections of different
|
|
712 |
context within a sub-proof may be switched via @{command "next"},
|
|
713 |
which is just a single block-close followed by block-open again.
|
|
714 |
The effect of @{command "next"} is to reset the local proof context;
|
|
715 |
there is no goal focus involved here!
|
|
716 |
|
|
717 |
For slightly more advanced applications, there are explicit block
|
|
718 |
parentheses as well. These typically achieve a stronger forward
|
|
719 |
style of reasoning.
|
|
720 |
|
|
721 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
722 |
|
|
723 |
\item [@{command "next"}] switches to a fresh block within a
|
|
724 |
sub-proof, resetting the local context to the initial one.
|
|
725 |
|
|
726 |
\item [@{command "{"} and @{command "}"}] explicitly open and close
|
|
727 |
blocks. Any current facts pass through ``@{command "{"}''
|
|
728 |
unchanged, while ``@{command "}"}'' causes any result to be
|
|
729 |
\emph{exported} into the enclosing context. Thus fixed variables
|
|
730 |
are generalized, assumptions discharged, and local definitions
|
|
731 |
unfolded (cf.\ \secref{sec:proof-context}). There is no difference
|
|
732 |
of @{command "assume"} and @{command "presume"} in this mode of
|
|
733 |
forward reasoning --- in contrast to plain backward reasoning with
|
|
734 |
the result exported at @{command "show"} time.
|
|
735 |
|
|
736 |
\end{descr}
|
|
737 |
*}
|
|
738 |
|
|
739 |
|
|
740 |
section {* Emulating tactic scripts \label{sec:tactic-commands} *}
|
|
741 |
|
|
742 |
text {*
|
|
743 |
The Isar provides separate commands to accommodate tactic-style
|
|
744 |
proof scripts within the same system. While being outside the
|
|
745 |
orthodox Isar proof language, these might come in handy for
|
|
746 |
interactive exploration and debugging, or even actual tactical proof
|
|
747 |
within new-style theories (to benefit from document preparation, for
|
|
748 |
example). See also \secref{sec:tactics} for actual tactics, that
|
|
749 |
have been encapsulated as proof methods. Proper proof methods may
|
|
750 |
be used in scripts, too.
|
|
751 |
|
|
752 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
753 |
@{command_def "apply"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
754 |
@{command_def "apply_end"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
755 |
@{command_def "done"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isartrans{proof(prove)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
756 |
@{command_def "defer"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isartrans{proof}{proof} \\
|
|
757 |
@{command_def "prefer"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isartrans{proof}{proof} \\
|
|
758 |
@{command_def "back"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isartrans{proof}{proof} \\
|
|
759 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
760 |
|
|
761 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
762 |
( 'apply' | 'apply\_end' ) method
|
|
763 |
;
|
|
764 |
'defer' nat?
|
|
765 |
;
|
|
766 |
'prefer' nat
|
|
767 |
;
|
|
768 |
\end{rail}
|
|
769 |
|
|
770 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
771 |
|
|
772 |
\item [@{command "apply"}~@{text m}] applies proof method @{text m}
|
|
773 |
in initial position, but unlike @{command "proof"} it retains
|
|
774 |
``@{text "proof(prove)"}'' mode. Thus consecutive method
|
|
775 |
applications may be given just as in tactic scripts.
|
|
776 |
|
|
777 |
Facts are passed to @{text m} as indicated by the goal's
|
|
778 |
forward-chain mode, and are \emph{consumed} afterwards. Thus any
|
|
779 |
further @{command "apply"} command would always work in a purely
|
|
780 |
backward manner.
|
|
781 |
|
|
782 |
\item [@{command "apply_end"}~@{text "m"}] applies proof method
|
|
783 |
@{text m} as if in terminal position. Basically, this simulates a
|
|
784 |
multi-step tactic script for @{command "qed"}, but may be given
|
|
785 |
anywhere within the proof body.
|
|
786 |
|
|
787 |
No facts are passed to @{method m} here. Furthermore, the static
|
|
788 |
context is that of the enclosing goal (as for actual @{command
|
|
789 |
"qed"}). Thus the proof method may not refer to any assumptions
|
|
790 |
introduced in the current body, for example.
|
|
791 |
|
|
792 |
\item [@{command "done"}] completes a proof script, provided that
|
|
793 |
the current goal state is solved completely. Note that actual
|
|
794 |
structured proof commands (e.g.\ ``@{command "."}'' or @{command
|
|
795 |
"sorry"}) may be used to conclude proof scripts as well.
|
|
796 |
|
|
797 |
\item [@{command "defer"}~@{text n} and @{command "prefer"}~@{text
|
|
798 |
n}] shuffle the list of pending goals: @{command "defer"} puts off
|
|
799 |
sub-goal @{text n} to the end of the list (@{text "n = 1"} by
|
|
800 |
default), while @{command "prefer"} brings sub-goal @{text n} to the
|
|
801 |
front.
|
|
802 |
|
|
803 |
\item [@{command "back"}] does back-tracking over the result
|
|
804 |
sequence of the latest proof command. Basically, any proof command
|
|
805 |
may return multiple results.
|
|
806 |
|
|
807 |
\end{descr}
|
|
808 |
|
|
809 |
Any proper Isar proof method may be used with tactic script commands
|
|
810 |
such as @{command "apply"}. A few additional emulations of actual
|
|
811 |
tactics are provided as well; these would be never used in actual
|
|
812 |
structured proofs, of course.
|
|
813 |
*}
|
|
814 |
|
|
815 |
|
|
816 |
section {* Omitting proofs *}
|
|
817 |
|
|
818 |
text {*
|
|
819 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
820 |
@{command_def "oops"} & : & \isartrans{proof}{theory} \\
|
|
821 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
822 |
|
|
823 |
The @{command "oops"} command discontinues the current proof
|
|
824 |
attempt, while considering the partial proof text as properly
|
|
825 |
processed. This is conceptually quite different from ``faking''
|
|
826 |
actual proofs via @{command_ref "sorry"} (see
|
|
827 |
\secref{sec:proof-steps}): @{command "oops"} does not observe the
|
|
828 |
proof structure at all, but goes back right to the theory level.
|
|
829 |
Furthermore, @{command "oops"} does not produce any result theorem
|
|
830 |
--- there is no intended claim to be able to complete the proof
|
|
831 |
anyhow.
|
|
832 |
|
|
833 |
A typical application of @{command "oops"} is to explain Isar proofs
|
|
834 |
\emph{within} the system itself, in conjunction with the document
|
|
835 |
preparation tools of Isabelle described in \cite{isabelle-sys}.
|
|
836 |
Thus partial or even wrong proof attempts can be discussed in a
|
|
837 |
logically sound manner. Note that the Isabelle {\LaTeX} macros can
|
|
838 |
be easily adapted to print something like ``@{text "\<dots>"}'' instead of
|
|
839 |
the keyword ``@{command "oops"}''.
|
|
840 |
|
|
841 |
\medskip The @{command "oops"} command is undo-able, unlike
|
|
842 |
@{command_ref "kill"} (see \secref{sec:history}). The effect is to
|
|
843 |
get back to the theory just before the opening of the proof.
|
|
844 |
*}
|
|
845 |
|
|
846 |
|
|
847 |
section {* Generalized elimination \label{sec:obtain} *}
|
|
848 |
|
|
849 |
text {*
|
|
850 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
851 |
@{command_def "obtain"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
852 |
@{command_def "guess"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(prove)} \\
|
|
853 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
854 |
|
|
855 |
Generalized elimination means that additional elements with certain
|
|
856 |
properties may be introduced in the current context, by virtue of a
|
|
857 |
locally proven ``soundness statement''. Technically speaking, the
|
|
858 |
@{command "obtain"} language element is like a declaration of
|
|
859 |
@{command "fix"} and @{command "assume"} (see also see
|
|
860 |
\secref{sec:proof-context}), together with a soundness proof of its
|
|
861 |
additional claim. According to the nature of existential reasoning,
|
|
862 |
assumptions get eliminated from any result exported from the context
|
|
863 |
later, provided that the corresponding parameters do \emph{not}
|
|
864 |
occur in the conclusion.
|
|
865 |
|
|
866 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
867 |
'obtain' parname? (vars + 'and') 'where' (props + 'and')
|
|
868 |
;
|
|
869 |
'guess' (vars + 'and')
|
|
870 |
;
|
|
871 |
\end{rail}
|
|
872 |
|
|
873 |
The derived Isar command @{command "obtain"} is defined as follows
|
|
874 |
(where @{text "b\<^sub>1, \<dots>, b\<^sub>k"} shall refer to (optional)
|
|
875 |
facts indicated for forward chaining).
|
|
876 |
\begin{matharray}{l}
|
|
877 |
@{text "\<langle>using b\<^sub>1 \<dots> b\<^sub>k\<rangle>"}~~@{command "obtain"}~@{text "x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m \<WHERE> a: \<phi>\<^sub>1 \<dots> \<phi>\<^sub>n \<langle>proof\<rangle> \<equiv>"} \\[1ex]
|
|
878 |
\quad @{command "have"}~@{text "\<And>thesis. (\<And>x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m. \<phi>\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<phi>\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> thesis) \<Longrightarrow> thesis"} \\
|
|
879 |
\quad @{command "proof"}~@{text succeed} \\
|
|
880 |
\qquad @{command "fix"}~@{text thesis} \\
|
|
881 |
\qquad @{command "assume"}~@{text "that [Pure.intro?]: \<And>x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m. \<phi>\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots> \<phi>\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> thesis"} \\
|
|
882 |
\qquad @{command "then"}~@{command "show"}~@{text thesis} \\
|
|
883 |
\quad\qquad @{command "apply"}~@{text -} \\
|
|
884 |
\quad\qquad @{command "using"}~@{text "b\<^sub>1 \<dots> b\<^sub>k \<langle>proof\<rangle>"} \\
|
|
885 |
\quad @{command "qed"} \\
|
|
886 |
\quad @{command "fix"}~@{text "x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m"}~@{command "assume"}@{text "\<^sup>* a: \<phi>\<^sub>1 \<dots> \<phi>\<^sub>n"} \\
|
|
887 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
888 |
|
|
889 |
Typically, the soundness proof is relatively straight-forward, often
|
|
890 |
just by canonical automated tools such as ``@{command "by"}~@{text
|
|
891 |
simp}'' or ``@{command "by"}~@{text blast}''. Accordingly, the
|
|
892 |
``@{text that}'' reduction above is declared as simplification and
|
|
893 |
introduction rule.
|
|
894 |
|
|
895 |
In a sense, @{command "obtain"} represents at the level of Isar
|
|
896 |
proofs what would be meta-logical existential quantifiers and
|
|
897 |
conjunctions. This concept has a broad range of useful
|
|
898 |
applications, ranging from plain elimination (or introduction) of
|
|
899 |
object-level existential and conjunctions, to elimination over
|
|
900 |
results of symbolic evaluation of recursive definitions, for
|
|
901 |
example. Also note that @{command "obtain"} without parameters acts
|
|
902 |
much like @{command "have"}, where the result is treated as a
|
|
903 |
genuine assumption.
|
|
904 |
|
|
905 |
An alternative name to be used instead of ``@{text that}'' above may
|
|
906 |
be given in parentheses.
|
|
907 |
|
|
908 |
\medskip The improper variant @{command "guess"} is similar to
|
|
909 |
@{command "obtain"}, but derives the obtained statement from the
|
|
910 |
course of reasoning! The proof starts with a fixed goal @{text
|
|
911 |
thesis}. The subsequent proof may refine this to anything of the
|
|
912 |
form like @{text "\<And>x\<^sub>1 \<dots> x\<^sub>m. \<phi>\<^sub>1 \<Longrightarrow> \<dots>
|
|
913 |
\<phi>\<^sub>n \<Longrightarrow> thesis"}, but must not introduce new subgoals. The
|
|
914 |
final goal state is then used as reduction rule for the obtain
|
|
915 |
scheme described above. Obtained parameters @{text "x\<^sub>1, \<dots>,
|
|
916 |
x\<^sub>m"} are marked as internal by default, which prevents the
|
|
917 |
proof context from being polluted by ad-hoc variables. The variable
|
|
918 |
names and type constraints given as arguments for @{command "guess"}
|
|
919 |
specify a prefix of obtained parameters explicitly in the text.
|
|
920 |
|
|
921 |
It is important to note that the facts introduced by @{command
|
|
922 |
"obtain"} and @{command "guess"} may not be polymorphic: any
|
|
923 |
type-variables occurring here are fixed in the present context!
|
|
924 |
*}
|
|
925 |
|
|
926 |
|
|
927 |
section {* Calculational reasoning \label{sec:calculation} *}
|
|
928 |
|
|
929 |
text {*
|
|
930 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
931 |
@{command_def "also"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
932 |
@{command_def "finally"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(chain)} \\
|
|
933 |
@{command_def "moreover"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(state)} \\
|
|
934 |
@{command_def "ultimately"} & : & \isartrans{proof(state)}{proof(chain)} \\
|
|
935 |
@{command_def "print_trans_rules"}@{text "\<^sup>*"} & : & \isarkeep{theory~|~proof} \\
|
|
936 |
@{attribute trans} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
937 |
@{attribute sym} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
938 |
@{attribute symmetric} & : & \isaratt \\
|
|
939 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
940 |
|
|
941 |
Calculational proof is forward reasoning with implicit application
|
|
942 |
of transitivity rules (such those of @{text "="}, @{text "\<le>"},
|
|
943 |
@{text "<"}). Isabelle/Isar maintains an auxiliary fact register
|
|
944 |
@{fact_ref calculation} for accumulating results obtained by
|
|
945 |
transitivity composed with the current result. Command @{command
|
|
946 |
"also"} updates @{fact calculation} involving @{fact this}, while
|
|
947 |
@{command "finally"} exhibits the final @{fact calculation} by
|
|
948 |
forward chaining towards the next goal statement. Both commands
|
|
949 |
require valid current facts, i.e.\ may occur only after commands
|
|
950 |
that produce theorems such as @{command "assume"}, @{command
|
|
951 |
"note"}, or some finished proof of @{command "have"}, @{command
|
|
952 |
"show"} etc. The @{command "moreover"} and @{command "ultimately"}
|
|
953 |
commands are similar to @{command "also"} and @{command "finally"},
|
|
954 |
but only collect further results in @{fact calculation} without
|
|
955 |
applying any rules yet.
|
|
956 |
|
|
957 |
Also note that the implicit term abbreviation ``@{text "\<dots>"}'' has
|
|
958 |
its canonical application with calculational proofs. It refers to
|
|
959 |
the argument of the preceding statement. (The argument of a curried
|
|
960 |
infix expression happens to be its right-hand side.)
|
|
961 |
|
|
962 |
Isabelle/Isar calculations are implicitly subject to block structure
|
|
963 |
in the sense that new threads of calculational reasoning are
|
|
964 |
commenced for any new block (as opened by a local goal, for
|
|
965 |
example). This means that, apart from being able to nest
|
|
966 |
calculations, there is no separate \emph{begin-calculation} command
|
|
967 |
required.
|
|
968 |
|
|
969 |
\medskip The Isar calculation proof commands may be defined as
|
|
970 |
follows:\footnote{We suppress internal bookkeeping such as proper
|
|
971 |
handling of block-structure.}
|
|
972 |
|
|
973 |
\begin{matharray}{rcl}
|
|
974 |
@{command "also"}@{text "\<^sub>0"} & \equiv & @{command "note"}~@{text "calculation = this"} \\
|
|
975 |
@{command "also"}@{text "\<^sub>n\<^sub>+\<^sub>1"} & \equiv & @{command "note"}~@{text "calculation = trans [OF calculation this]"} \\[0.5ex]
|
|
976 |
@{command "finally"} & \equiv & @{command "also"}~@{command "from"}~@{text calculation} \\[0.5ex]
|
|
977 |
@{command "moreover"} & \equiv & @{command "note"}~@{text "calculation = calculation this"} \\
|
|
978 |
@{command "ultimately"} & \equiv & @{command "moreover"}~@{command "from"}~@{text calculation} \\
|
|
979 |
\end{matharray}
|
|
980 |
|
|
981 |
\begin{rail}
|
|
982 |
('also' | 'finally') ('(' thmrefs ')')?
|
|
983 |
;
|
|
984 |
'trans' (() | 'add' | 'del')
|
|
985 |
;
|
|
986 |
\end{rail}
|
|
987 |
|
|
988 |
\begin{descr}
|
|
989 |
|
|
990 |
\item [@{command "also"}~@{text "(a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n)"}]
|
|
991 |
maintains the auxiliary @{fact calculation} register as follows.
|
|
992 |
The first occurrence of @{command "also"} in some calculational
|
|
993 |
thread initializes @{fact calculation} by @{fact this}. Any
|
|
994 |
subsequent @{command "also"} on the same level of block-structure
|
|
995 |
updates @{fact calculation} by some transitivity rule applied to
|
|
996 |
@{fact calculation} and @{fact this} (in that order). Transitivity
|
|
997 |
rules are picked from the current context, unless alternative rules
|
|
998 |
are given as explicit arguments.
|
|
999 |
|
|
1000 |
\item [@{command "finally"}~@{text "(a\<^sub>1 \<dots> a\<^sub>n)"}]
|
|
1001 |
maintaining @{fact calculation} in the same way as @{command
|
|
1002 |
"also"}, and concludes the current calculational thread. The final
|
|
1003 |
result is exhibited as fact for forward chaining towards the next
|
|
1004 |
goal. Basically, @{command "finally"} just abbreviates @{command
|
|
1005 |
"also"}~@{command "from"}~@{fact calculation}. Typical idioms for
|
|
1006 |
concluding calculational proofs are ``@{command "finally"}~@{command
|
|
1007 |
"show"}~@{text ?thesis}~@{command "."}'' and ``@{command
|
|
1008 |
"finally"}~@{command "have"}~@{text \<phi>}~@{command "."}''.
|
|
1009 |
|
|
1010 |
\item [@{command "moreover"} and @{command "ultimately"}] are
|
|
1011 |
analogous to @{command "also"} and @{command "finally"}, but collect
|
|
1012 |
results only, without applying rules.
|
|
1013 |
|
|
1014 |
\item [@{command "print_trans_rules"}] prints the list of
|
|
1015 |
transitivity rules (for calculational commands @{command "also"} and
|
|
1016 |
@{command "finally"}) and symmetry rules (for the @{attribute
|
|
1017 |
symmetric} operation and single step elimination patters) of the
|
|
1018 |
current context.
|
|
1019 |
|
|
1020 |
\item [@{attribute trans}] declares theorems as transitivity rules.
|
|
1021 |
|
|
1022 |
\item [@{attribute sym}] declares symmetry rules, as well as
|
|
1023 |
@{attribute "Pure.elim?"} rules.
|
|
1024 |
|
|
1025 |
\item [@{attribute symmetric}] resolves a theorem with some rule
|
|
1026 |
declared as @{attribute sym} in the current context. For example,
|
|
1027 |
``@{command "assume"}~@{text "[symmetric]: x = y"}'' produces a
|
|
1028 |
swapped fact derived from that assumption.
|
|
1029 |
|
|
1030 |
In structured proof texts it is often more appropriate to use an
|
|
1031 |
explicit single-step elimination proof, such as ``@{command
|
|
1032 |
"assume"}~@{text "x = y"}~@{command "then"}~@{command "have"}~@{text
|
|
1033 |
"y = x"}~@{command ".."}''.
|
|
1034 |
|
|
1035 |
\end{descr}
|
|
1036 |
*}
|
|
1037 |
|
26869
|
1038 |
end
|